Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T00:54:51.608Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intentional content in psychopathologies requires an expanded interpretivism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Marc Slors
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies, Radboud University Nijmegen, 6500 HD, Nijmegen, The Netherlands. [email protected]@ftr.ru.nlhttps://radboud.academia.edu/MarcSlors/https://radboud.academia.edu/DerekStrijbos/
Jolien C. Francken
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of Amsterdam, 1018 WT, Amsterdam, The Netherlands. [email protected] Amsterdam Brain and Cognition, University of Amsterdam, 1001 NK, Amsterdam, The Netherlands
Derek Strijbos
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies, Radboud University Nijmegen, 6500 HD, Nijmegen, The Netherlands. [email protected]@ftr.ru.nlhttps://radboud.academia.edu/MarcSlors/https://radboud.academia.edu/DerekStrijbos/ Center for Development Disorders, Dimence Mental Health Institute, 7416 SB, Deventer, The Netherlands.

Abstract

We argue that the explanatory role of intentional content in connecting symptoms in a network approach to psychopathology hinges neither on causality nor on rationality. Instead, we argue that it hinges on a pluralistic body of practical and clinical know-how. Incorporating this practical approach to intentional state ascription in psychopathological cases expands and improves traditional interpretivism.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Andrews, K. (2012) Do apes read minds? Towards a new folk-psychology. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1987) The intentional stance. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Eronen, M. I. (2017) Interventionism for the intentional stance: True believers and their brains. Topoi. (Published Online, 2nd December, 2017). Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9513-5.Google Scholar
Francken, J. C. & Slors, M. (2014) From commonsense to science, and back: The use of cognitive concepts in neuroscience. Consciousness and Cognition 29:248–58. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2014.08.019.Google Scholar
Francken, J. C. & Slors, M. (2018) Neuroscience and everyday life: Facing the translation problem. Brain and Cognition 120:6774. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.bandc.2017.09.004.Google Scholar
Gerrans, P. (2013) Delusional attitudes and default thinking. Mind and Language 28(1):83102. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12010.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. M. (1996) “Radical” simulationism. In: Theories of theories of mind, ed. Carruthers, P. & Smith, P. K., pp. 1121. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Radden, J. (2011) On delusion. Routledge.Google Scholar
Ratcliffe, M. (2015) Experiences of depression: A study in phenomenology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slors, M. V. P. (2007) Intentional systems theory, mental causation and empathic resonance. Erkenntnis 67:321–36. Available at: https://doi:org/10.1007/s10670-007-9074-x.Google Scholar