Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T09:06:21.434Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The four different modes of psychological explanation, and their proper evaluative schemas

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2022

Michael Gilead*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Beer-Sheva8410501, Israel. [email protected]

Abstract

I apply Benjamin's (1941) taxonomy of common scientific “modes of explanation” to the psychological context. I argue that: (i) in a “naming” mode, generalizability is not necessary; (ii) in an “analysis,” generalizability is desired; (iii) in a “causal ontology,” generalizability is merely one of the means to an end (theory-challenge); (iv) in a “synthesis,” generalizability is (eventually) critical. A better appreciation of the diversity in psychologists' modes of explanation is crucial for cogent meta-psychological discussions.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baddeley, A. D., & Hitch, G. (1993). The recency effect – implicit learning with explicit retrieval. Memory & Cognition, 21(2), 146155. doi:10.3758/bf03202726.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Benjamin, A. C. (1941). Modes of scientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 8(4), 486492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frederick, S., & Loewenstein, G. (1999). 16 Hedonic adaptation. In D. Kahneman, E. Diener, & N. Schwarz (Eds.), The foundations of Hedonic (pp. 302–329). Russell Sage.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (2003). A treatise of human nature. Courier Corporation.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Fredrickson, B. L., Schreiber, C. A., & Redelmeier, D. A. (1993). When more pain is preferred to less: Adding a better end. Psychological Science, 4(6), 401405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1908). Critique of pure reason. 1781. Modern classical philosophers (pp. 370–456). Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1999). All life is problem solving. Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Rutledge, R. B., Skandali, N., Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. (2014). A computational and neural model of momentary subjective well-being. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 111(33), 1225212257. doi:10.1073/pnas.1407535111.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed