No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Moral psychology biases toward individual, not systemic, representations
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 30 August 2023
Abstract
We expand Chater & Loewenstein's discussion of barriers to s-frames by highlighting moral psychological mechanisms. Systemic aspects of moralized social issues can be neglected because of (a) the individualistic frame through which we perceive moral transgressions; (b) the desire to punish elicited by moral emotions; and (c) the motivation to attribute agency and moral responsibility to transgressors.
- Type
- Open Peer Commentary
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press
Footnotes
*
IAT and NRK contributed equally and share first authorship.
References
Clark, C. J., Chen, E. E., & Ditto, P. H. (2015). Moral coherence processes: Constructing culpability and consequences. Current Opinion in Psychology, 6, 123–128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, C. J., Luguri, J. B., Ditto, P. H., Knobe, J., Shariff, A. F., & Baumeister, R. F. (2014). Free to punish: A motivated account of free will belief. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 106(4), 501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clifford, S. (2019). How emotional frames moralize and polarize political attitudes. Political Psychology, 40(1), 75–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cushman, F., Knobe, J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Moral appraisals affect doing/allowing judgments. Cognition, 108(1), 281–289.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
D'Amore, C., van Zomeren, M., & Koudenburg, N. (2022). Attitude moralization within polarized contexts: An emotional value-protective response to dyadic harm cues. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 48(11), 1566–1579. https://doi.org/10.1177/01461672211047375CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Feinberg, M., Kovacheff, C., Teper, R., & Inbar, Y. (2019). Understanding the process of moralization: How eating meat becomes a moral issue. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 117(1), 50–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ginther, M. R., Hartsough, L. E. S., & Marois, R. (2022). Moral outrage drives the interaction of harm and culpable intent in third-party punishment decisions. Emotion, 22(4), 795–804.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). Moral character predominates in person perception and evaluation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 106(1), 148–168.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind perception is the essence of morality. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kominsky, J. F., Phillips, J., Gerstenberg, T., Lagnado, D., & Knobe, J. (2015). Causal superseding. Cognition, 137, 196–209.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Konishi, N., Oe, T., Shimizu, H., Tanaka, K., & Ohtsubo, Y. (2017). Perceived shared condemnation intensifies punitive moral emotions. Scientific Reports, 7(1), 7289.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rhee, J. J., Schein, C., & Bastian, B. (2019). The what, how, and why of moralization: A review of current definitions, methods, and evidence in moralization research. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 13(12), e12511. https://doi.org/10.1111/spc3.12511CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76(4), 574–586.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wisneski, D. C., & Skitka, L. J. (2017). Moralization through moral shock: Exploring emotional antecedents to moral conviction. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin, 43(2), 139–150.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Young, L., & Phillips, J. (2011). The paradox of moral focus. Cognition, 119(2), 166–178.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
You have
Access
Many societal ills are rooted in deep systemic causes that nonetheless operate through the behavior of individuals. This leaves ambiguity as to where the responsibility lies, and Chater & Loewenstein (C&L) propose that people resolve this ambiguity with a bias toward overrepresenting the role of individual behavior compared to systemic factors. They describe this bias as arising from several psychological mechanisms, including the fundamental attribution error, a present-biased emotional system that is not adapted to a systemic analysis of problems, functional fixedness, and so on. Missing from this predominantly cognitive list, however, are mechanisms related to morality. Without disputing the contributions of more cognitive processes, we contend that the emerging science of moral psychology implies additional pathways that explain why people overemphasize the role of individuals in the most pressing issues of our time.
The relevance of morality is inherent to a great many of these issues: Questions of police brutality, sexual harassment, the redistribution of wealth, and the rights of non-citizens, to name a few, evoke moral values of harm, justice, and group loyalty. But morality can also become attached to social issues that seem on their surface morally neutral (Rhee, Schein, & Bastian, Reference Rhee, Schein and Bastian2019), if these arouse certain moral emotions, such as guilt, anger, outrage, and disgust (Clifford, Reference Clifford2019; D'Amore, van Zomeren, & Koudenburg, Reference D'Amore, van Zomeren and Koudenburg2022; Rozin, Lowery, Imada, & Haidt, Reference Rozin, Lowery, Imada and Haidt1999; Wisneski & Skitka, Reference Wisneski and Skitka2017). For example, in the lab, people who were made to feel disgusted by or guilty about their meat consumption later moralize this issue (Feinberg, Kovacheff, Teper, & Inbar, Reference Feinberg, Kovacheff, Teper and Inbar2019).
If social issues frequently take on moral significance, any analysis of how people respond to them must take into account moral psychology, whose primary function is to enable people to distinguish between individuals who are trustworthy and reliable and those who might exploit or harm them (Goodwin, Piazza, & Rozin, Reference Goodwin, Piazza and Rozin2014). In fact, most documented reactions to moral violations focus on the level of individuals and attributions of responsibility internal to those individuals.
This individual lens is apparent as soon as people encounter a moral violation. When a person witnesses, for example, a police shooting of an unarmed Black man, a case of sexual harassment, or workers being exploited, his mind sees a vulnerable patient being harmed and automatically seeks to complete the picture by identifying an intentional moral agent to shoulder the blame (Gray, Young, & Waytz, Reference Gray, Young and Waytz2012). This dyadic template leaves little room to conceive of the role of broader systems, because the agentic member of the dyad must, by definition, have “the capacity to intend and to act (e.g., self-control, judgment, communication, thought, and memory)” (Gray et al., Reference Gray, Young and Waytz2012). Mindless systemic forces like institutionalized racism, cultural misogyny, or capitalism may not spring to mind; instead, the person witnessing the violation is likely to blame the officer who pulled the trigger, the sexual harasser, or the stingy employer.
The individual lens is also apparent in the present-oriented and punitive nature of the actions that moral emotions compel, once the dyadic template is in place. The specific combination of an intentional agent causing substantial harm to a patient uniquely evokes moral outrage (Ginther, Hartsough, & Marois, Reference Ginther, Hartsough and Marois2022). In turn, the proximate function of moral outrage is to enforce moral standards: Moral outrage motivates people to punish the perpetrator (Ginther et al., Reference Ginther, Hartsough and Marois2022; Konishi, Oe, Shimizu, Tanaka, & Ohtsubo, Reference Konishi, Oe, Shimizu, Tanaka and Ohtsubo2017), thus satisfying an immediate and visceral pull. Even if our witness managed to identify the system as the perpetrator, their drive to punish would have nowhere to go: Although it is at least in theory possible to punish an individual police officer, sexual harasser, or employer, it is not so clear how one could punish structural institutions like racism, sexism, or capitalism. The long and arduous task of systemic reform often requires going beyond gratifying one's immediate and intuitively appealing urge to punish.
This drive to punish likely leads people to further deemphasize situational and systemic causes for social ills. When seeking to punish an individual they have identified as a perpetrator, people will try to maximize that individual's moral responsibility. Whether this means downplaying additional causes for the violation or external constraints on the individual's actions (Clark et al., Reference Clark, Chen and Ditto2015; Cushman, Knobe, & Sinnott-Armstrong, Reference Cushman, Knobe and Sinnott-Armstrong2008; Kominsky, Phillips, Gerstenberg, Lagnado, & Knobe, Reference Kominsky, Phillips, Gerstenberg, Lagnado and Knobe2015; Young & Phillips, Reference Young and Phillips2011), or elevating philosophical beliefs in free will (Clark et al., Reference Clark, Luguri, Ditto, Knobe, Shariff and Baumeister2014), they adopt perceptions that justify punitive action. In other words, when people are most morally outraged and motivated to punish, they may push aside important systemic factors in the heat of the moment, so they can hold individual actors to account and mete out punishment without hesitation.
To summarize, representations of societal issues that center individual perpetrators tend to be inherently appealing because they align with our moral psychology and satisfy our immediate emotional needs. This tendency to individualize the causes of issues likely translates into preferences to correct (perhaps most often punish) individual behavior, rather than address the manifold structural imbalances at the root of the problem. As C&L suggest, this bias among the general public may affect policy decisions, both because policy-makers themselves are vulnerable to it, and because they are motivated to appeal to the majority. Advocates for system-oriented policies seeking to gain public support will need to confront not only the cognitive obstacles blocking their path, but also the moral ones too.
Financial support
This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.
Competing interest
None.