We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Besides, there are – because some have indeed said: you were tricked, overwhelmed, surprised or whatever – situations when it is necessary to make decisions. I could not have waited for twelve hours and contemplated the issues. Those people converged on the borders, and so we took this decision.
Angela Merkel
What is the border for in the end? To unite us.
Régis Debray
Conviction and responsibility
One and a quarter million refugees applied for asylum in the Union in 2015, twice as many as the year before. The images were dramatic: small boats on the Mediterranean, handcarts on Balkan roads, full trains stranded on the way to the rich North. The influx of people looked to many like a mass migration, almost an invasion; and the public, in fearful bewilderment, had the impression the authorities had lost control. Could Europe act? Was Europe authorized to act?
The demand for action had a different character from that which accompanied previous crises. The Ukraine crisis of 2014–15 was a matter of war and peace; the Union itself had hardly any resources or powers to bring the conflict under control, so active intervention by the member states jointly was an obvious necessity. Moreover, application of the magnetic forces provided by the Brussels diplomatic toolkit, the showpiece being the association agreement with Kiev, had worked out badly. No one at that point, therefore, disputed the primacy of events-politics. In the fields of asylum and migration, by contrast, the Union had quite a few competences and regulations. The situation became unmanageable because the regulatory framework collapsed under divergent strategic interests and because of the disruptive impact of the situation on public opinion. For a long time Brussels was blind to the gap between what was administratively possible and what, in this exceptional situation, was politically required. Engagement by the highest political authority needed for events-politics was even actively hindered by some institutions, reinforcing the impression of a loss of control, of powerlessness.
The contrast with the euro crisis of 2010–12 is illustrative as well. To steer their poorly equipped currency through the storm, the leaders, at gunpoint, had both to design new tools and to deploy them immediately.
These three powers [judiciary, legislative and executive] should naturally form a state of repose or inaction. But as there is a necessity for movement in the course of human affairs, they are forced to move, but still to move in concert.
Charles de Montesquieu
It is quite obviously impossible to deal with political power and the structure of the state itself without knowing what Authority is as such.
Alexandre Kojève
Most truly has the wise man said that of things future and contingent we can have no certain knowledge. Turn this over in your mind as you will, the longer you turn it the more you will be satisfied of its truth.
Francesco Guicciardini
Emancipation of executive power
Anyone who visits Washington and sees the magnificence of the legislative Congress, with its majestic dome on the axis of the city, and then looks at the White House, built for the president, small by comparison and off to one side, senses what the founders of the American republic at the end of the eighteenth century believed the relationship should be between the main powers: the legislators in charge and the executive power in second place. The 13 newly united states had thrown off the British king, their colonial sovereign, and did not want a citizen-king in his place. Something similar happened in France. After the revolution of 1789 and the fall of absolute monarch Louis XVI, the focus was on the impersonal and all-encompassing authority of the law. As Pierre Rosanvallon shows in Good Government (2018), primacy was given to parliament, as guardian of the sovereignty of the people. France went through a turbulent episode under Napoleon (and half a century later his nephew), but distrust of arbitrary leaders ultimately produced the parliamentarianism of the Third Republic. Like the Americans, the French kept the executive power small.
The founders of the Community similarly drew a line under the past. Just as the young American and French republics had put aside their king, so the new European Community excluded national governments as far as possible.
Sergio Fabbrini proposes a way out of the EU's crises, which have triggered an unprecedented cleavage between 'sovereignist' and 'Europeanist' forces. The intergovernmental governance of the multiple crises of the past decade has led to a division on the very rationale of Europe's integration project. Sovereignism (the expression of nationalistic and populist forces) has demanded more decision-making autonomy for the EU member states, although Europeanism has struggled to make an effective case against this challenge. Fabbrini proposes a new perspective to release the EU from this predicament, involving the decoupling and reforming of the EU: on the one hand, the economic community of the single market (consisting of the current member states of the EU and of others interested in joining or re-joining it); and on the other, the political union (largely based on the eurozone reformed according to an original model of the federal union).
This article analyses the relationship between populist attitudes and political participation. We argue that populist attitudes can be a motivation for participation through their identity, emotional, and moral components, and that they have the potential to narrow socioeconomic gaps in participation. Using survey data from nine European countries, our results show that populist attitudes are positively related to expressive non-institutionalized modes of participation (petition signing, online participation and, in some contexts, demonstrating), but not to turnout. In addition, populist attitudes are found to reduce education-based gaps and even reverse income-based inequalities in political participation. The implications of these findings are discussed.
This chapter looks at how far the EU decision making process can meet the first criterion and satisfy the normative requirements of a two level game among the governments and the demoi of the different member states. It starts by exploring the concept of representation and notes that while decision making in the Commission and EP rests on an ontology of solidarism and that between states on that of singularity, both prove problematic. Instead, we need to encourage apolitical ontology of civicity. It is argued one way to achieve this result is through the involvement of national parliaments.
This chater explores the third criterion whereby a republican union of states must be voluntary. This has been the hardest to chieve whilst satisfying the first two criteria. However, it is argued that considerations of fairness, impartiality and equity require that there be some differentiated integration among member states. The first part of the chapter discusses which policy areas might be legitimately differentiated, the second part explores the implications of such DI for the legitimacy of majority rule and the constitutionalisation of the Treaties by the ECJ, applying the argument to the euro.
This chapter provides an overview of the main themes of the book, and outlines the key approaches of cosmopolitan statism and republican intergovernmentalism as offering a realistic utopia whereby the EU and other international organisations might achieve democratic legitimacy.
This chapter adresses the second criterionof ensuring all citizens are treated with equal concern and respect. It disputes that Union citizenship can be considered either as supra-, post-, or transnational, and instead argues that it is rightly linked to membership of a member state but allows for a system of equal concern and respect BETWEEN different national citizenships within the EU. As such there are justifable linits to union citizenship, with mobile citizens having duties to maintain the sustainability of the citizenship regiumes to which they move.