We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
Cambridge Companions are a series of authoritative guides, written by leading experts, offering lively, accessible introductions to major writers, artists, philosophers, topics, and periods.
Cambridge Companions are a series of authoritative guides, written by leading experts, offering lively, accessible introductions to major writers, artists, philosophers, topics, and periods.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Of all post-Enlightenment social sciences, economics might be easily classified as having the least in common with natural law theory. To the extent, for example, that economics is concerned with matters such as utility maximisation, cost–benefit analysis or identifying unintended consequences of particular decisions, its goals differ from natural law theory’s central focus on individuals and communities (including the state) knowing and choosing the good through right reason. Typically, what is called ‘positive economics’ – famously defined by the British economist Lionel Robbins as ‘the science which studies human behaviour as a relationship between ends and scarce means which have alternative uses’ (Robbins 1952: 16) – brackets off the type of normative questions with which natural law theory is concerned.
Those engaged in natural law reflection have, however, always brought their methods of reasoning to bear upon questions with significant economic components.
Not every creature has reason to live so as to fulfil its purpose in life. Just ask a battery hen. Her purpose in life is to produce as many eggs at as little cost as possible, then be turned into a raw material of the fast-food industry. The resultant misery and distress to the hen is just a corollary of her living according to her purpose, her telos – as a frank egg-farmer might admit. From the battery hen’s own point of view, there is no reason at all for her to live this way. As she would see it (if she had a chance to consider the question), she would be better off doing almost anything other than fulfilling her telos. Her telos and her flourishing are not the same thing. Almost all of the time, they do not even coincide.
The New Natural Law (NNL) theory is the name given to a particular revival and development of Thomistic natural law theory, first proposed in the 1960s by Germain Grisez in an interpretative article on St Thomas Aquinas, in which Grisez challenged the then-dominant interpretation of Aquinas on natural law. In subsequent decades Grisez, John Finnis, Joseph Boyle and others richly developed the theory and applied it to other issues (free choice, moral absolutes, abortion, euthanasia, marriage and others).
According to the interpretation of Aquinas’ natural law theory standard in the 1960s, the basic moral criterion is human nature itself. Actions are morally permissible if they conform to the teleologies inscribed within human nature, morally wrong if not. Since the standard for what is morally right is what fulfils human nature, one must first determine by a theoretical procedure what end or ends fulfil human nature.
The natural law conception of ethics is more closely associated with Thomas Aquinas than with any other thinker, and Aquinas’ position is famously grounded in a metaphysics of Aristotelian essentialism and teleology. It is often claimed that this metaphysics was decisively undermined by the scientific revolution. Hence it might appear that modern science has refuted what has been, historically, the main approach to understanding natural law.
Alternative versions of natural law may seem to sidestep this difficulty by looking for foundations in something other than an essentialist and teleological conception of nature. For example, Locke’s theory of natural law is grounded in the thesis of divine ownership of human beings. Violating the rights to life, liberty and property that we have under natural law is, for Locke, essentially a matter of damaging God’s property.
Any attempt to offer an account of natural law in Stoicism is confronted with the notorious problem of evidence. Not a single work of the ‘early’ Stoics (Zeno of Citium, Cleanthes and Chrysippus, all working in the third century BCE) has fully survived from antiquity. Reconstructions of their views depend on reports by authors who wrote much later and are in many cases anything but unbiased. The information that these authors provide usually leaves a rather wide scope for different interpretations. And the decision between these interpretations is often a matter of the general assumptions which guide our approach to the Stoics: whether we tend to think, for instance, that the early Stoics stood on common ground with their predecessors and contemporaries or whether we assume that they tried to distinguish themselves from other philosophers. As we shall see, this alternative is particularly relevant in the case of the natural law.
By acknowledging the place of reason in bioethics, natural law theory promises an ethics of life and death which, whilst acknowledging the social significance of consensus, consequences, cultural practices and competing religious precepts, offers a school of thought not reducible to these shifting, arbitrary and contradictory criteria. Advances in technology suggest that natural law theory can assist in the conduct of bioethics, if only because the natural law tradition entertains the possibility of universality, reason, objectivity and right answers in the realm of bioethics.
There are schools of thought that regard the death penalty a sound punishment for a change of religion or causing religious offence. In thirteen countries such legislation is recognised as binding and enforceable. These mandates are also seen by millions, both clerics and faith communities alike, as enforceable outside the jurisdictions that enact them.
The account of the natural law given by Thomas Aquinas has two claims to the title ‘natural’. First, the basic precepts of the natural law are naturally known, that is, they are accessible to us by the nature of our human minds. Second, the human good depends upon our nature. Philosophical inquiry, for instance, is part of the human good because of the nature of our minds. If we had the minds of squirrels, then philosophical inquiry would be alien to the human good.
For Aquinas, these two aspects of the natural law are intimately linked by way of natural inclinations. To possess a true nature – and not merely some abstract mathematical ‘nature’ – is to move towards certain ends. This natural movement or impetus Aquinas calls a ‘natural inclination’, not to be confused with an inborn desire.
Natural law ethics centres on the idea that ethical norms derive from human nature. The field has seen a remarkable revival since the millennium, with new work in Aristotelian metaphysics complementing innovative applied work in bioethics, economics and political theory. Starting with three chapters on the history of natural law ethics, this volume moves on to various twentieth-century theoretical innovations in the tradition, and then to natural law as embedded in the three Abrahamic faiths. It closes with sections on applied natural law ethics and the challenges and prospects for natural law ethics in the twenty-first century. Uniquely interdisciplinary and written without technical jargon, the book will be of great interest to students and researchers in philosophy, theology, political theory and economics. They will find this the go-to resource for cutting-edge thinking in natural law ethics.
The second edition of this Companion presents a philosophical perspective on an eighteenth-century phenomenon that has had a profound influence on Western culture. A distinguished team of contributors examines the writings of David Hume, Adam Smith, Thomas Reid, Adam Ferguson and other Scottish thinkers. Their subjects range across philosophy, natural theology, economics, anthropology, natural science, and law and the arts, and in addition, they relate the Scottish Enlightenment to its historical context and assess its impact and legacy. The result is a comprehensive and accessible volume that illuminates the richness, the intellectual variety and the underlying unity of this important movement. This volume contains five entirely new chapters on morality, the human mind, aesthetics, sentimentalism and political economy, and eleven other chapters have been significantly revised and updated. The book will be of interest to a wide range of readers in philosophy, theology, literature and the history of ideas.
This chapter investigates the problem of how the transplant and borrowing of foreign constitutional law and international law can influence constitution-making processes and constitutional interpretation – state actions which are still considered sovereign. International law, especially international human rights laws, are of pre-eminent importance in this context since they are virtually by definition based on limitations on national constitutional law to assert internationally shared constitutional principles. In other words, the chapter seeks to answer the question of how far the process of the internationalization of (national) constitutional law has progressed; to what extent are the framers of constitutions and the courts that interpret constitutions willing to accept alien, foreign, or international principles and rules? What underlies the decision by the constitutional organs of certain states to accede to such constitutional migration, and the rejection of such migration by their respective counterparts in other countries?
This chapter addresses the issue of democracy, in the context of this book on comparative constitutional law. It is readily apparent that the topic could be addressed from very different perspectives. Thus, the entire chapter could be directed towards differences between democratic and non-democratic constitutions. It might, alternatively, consider differences between constitutions within democratic polities, examining whether there are, or should be, constitutional differences that flow from different forms of democracy, or how far such differences result from the elevation of socio-economic norms to constitutional status. The chapter might have a different, more empirical, emphasis, with discussion as to the relative importance of constitutions in different countries. These are all significant issues, and each would occupy the entire chapter. They are not, however, addressed here.