No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Art and fiction are signals with indeterminate truth values
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 29 November 2017
Abstract
Menninghaus et al. distinguish art from fiction, but no current arguments or data suggest that the concept of art can be meaningfully circumscribed. This is a problem for aesthetic psychology. I sketch a solution by rejecting the distinction: Unlike most animal communication, in which signals are either true or false, art and fiction consist of signals without determinate truth values.
- Type
- Open Peer Commentary
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017
References
Blount, J. D., Metcalfe, N. B., Birkhead, T. R. & Surai, P. F. (2003) Carotenoid modulation of immune function and sexual attractiveness in zebra finches. Science
300(5616):125–27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bullot, N. J. & Reber, R. (2013b) A psycho-historical research program for the integrative science of art. Behavioral and Brain Sciences
36(2):163–80. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X12002464.Google Scholar
Chatterjee, A. & Vartanian, O. (2014) Neuroaesthetics. Trends in Cognitive Sciences
18(7):370–75.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. (2000) Adaptations for decoupling and metarepresentation. In: Metarepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective, ed. Sperber, D.. Oxford.Google Scholar
Gabrielsson, A. & Wik, S. L. (2003) Strong experiences related to music: A descriptive system. Musicae Scientiae
7(2):157–217.Google Scholar
Gerger, G., Leder, H. & Kremer, A. (2014) Context effects on emotional and aesthetic evaluations of artworks and IAPS pictures. Acta Psychologica
151(1):174–83. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.actpsy.2014.06.008.Google Scholar
Green, M. C. & Brock, T. C. (2000) The role of transportation in the persuasiveness of public narratives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
79(5):701.Google Scholar
Heinen, V. K. & Stephens, D. W. (2016) Blue jays, Cyanocitta cristata, devalue social information in uncertain environments. Animal Behaviour
112:53–62.Google Scholar
Iñiguez, G., Govezensky, T., Dunbar, R., Kaski, K. & Barrio, R. A. (2014) Effects of deception in social networks. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences
281(1790):20141195.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kamber, R. (2011) Experimental philosophy of art. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
69(2):197–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leder, H. & Nadal, M. (2014) Ten years of a model of aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic judgments: The aesthetic episode – Developments and challenges in empirical aesthetics. British Journal of Psychology
105(4):443–64. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1111/bjop.12084.Google Scholar
Malt, B. C. (1990) Features and beliefs in the mental representation of categories. Journal of Memory and Language
29(3):289–315.Google Scholar
Mar, R. A. & Oatley, K. (2008) The function of fiction is the abstraction and simulation of social experience. Perspectives on Psychological Science
3(3):173–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marsh, E. J. & Fazio, L. K. (2006) Learning errors from fiction: Difficulties in reducing reliance on fictional stories. Memory and Cognition
34(5):1140–49.Google Scholar
Mocaiber, I., Perakakis, P., Pereira, M. G., Pinheiro, W. M., Volchan, E., de Oliveira, L. & Vila, J. (2011a) Stimulus appraisal modulates cardiac reactivity to briefly presented mutilation pictures. International Journal of Psychophysiology
81(3):299–304.Google Scholar
Mocaiber, I., Pereira, M. G., Erthal, F. S., Machado-Pinheiro, W., David, I. A., Cagy, M., Volchan, E. & de Oliveira, L. (2010) Fact or fiction? An event-related potential study of implicit emotion regulation. Neuroscience Letters
476(2):84–88.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mocaiber, I., Sanchez, T. A., Pereira, M. G., Erthal, F. S., Joffily, M., Araujo, D. B., Volchan, E. & de Oliveira, L. (2011b) Antecedent descriptions change brain reactivity to emotional stimuli: A functional magnetic resonance imaging study of an extrinsic and incidental reappraisal strategy. Neuroscience
193:241–48.Google Scholar
Pearce, M. T., Zaidel, D. W., Vartanian, O., Skov, M., Leder, H., Chatterjee, A. & Nadal, M. (2016) Neuroaesthetics: The cognitive neuroscience of aesthetic experience. Perspectives on Psychological Science
11(2):265–79.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pelowski, M. J. (2015) Tears and transformation: Feeling like crying as an indicator of insightful or “aesthetic” experience with art. Frontiers in Psychology
6:1006.Google Scholar
Sloman, S. A. & Lagnado, D. (2015) Causality in thought. Annual Review of Psychology
66:223–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stolnitz, J. (1961) On the origins of “aesthetic disinterestedness.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
20(2):131–43.Google Scholar
Strange, J. J. & Leung, C. C. (1999) How anecdotal accounts in news and in fiction can influence judgments of a social problem's urgency, causes, and cures. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin
25(4):436–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (2001) Does beauty build adapted minds? Toward an evolutionary theory of aesthetics, fiction, and the arts. SubStance
30(1):6–27.Google Scholar
Van Dongen, N. N., Van Strien, J. W. & Dijkstra, K. (2016) Implicit emotion regulation in the context of viewing artworks: ERP evidence in response to pleasant and unpleasant pictures. Brain and Cognition
107:48–54. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.bandc.2016.06.003.Google Scholar
Wagner, V., Menninghaus, W., Hanich, J. & Jacobsen, T. (2014) Art schema effects on affective experience: The case of disgusting images. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts
8(2):120–29. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0036126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisberg, D. S. (2015) Pretend play. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science
6(3):249–61.Google ScholarPubMed
Weisberg, D. S. & Gopnik, A. (2013) Pretense, counterfactuals, and Bayesian causal models: Why what is not real really matters. Cognitive Science
37(7):1368–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Target article
The Distancing-Embracing model of the enjoyment of negative emotions in art reception
Related commentaries (32)
A social dimension to enjoyment of negative emotion in art reception
Art and fiction are signals with indeterminate truth values
Art as emotional exploration
Art enhances meaning by stimulating integrative complexity and aesthetic interest
Art reception as an interoceptive embodied predictive experience
Artistic misunderstandings: The emotional significance of historical learning in the arts
Being moved is a positive emotion, and emotions should not be equated with their vernacular labels
Boredom in art
Considering the filmmaker: Intensified continuity, narrative structure, and the Distancing-Embracing model
Context matters: How macroeconomic forces may alter the reception of negative emotions in art
Distancing, not embracing, the Distancing-Embracing model of art reception
Does art expertise facilitate distancing?
Embracing nonfiction: How to extend the Distancing-Embracing model
Emotional granularity and the musical enjoyment of sadness itself
Empathy as a guide for understanding the balancing of Distancing-Embracing with negative art
Explaining the enjoyment of negative emotions evoked by the arts: The need to consider empathy and other underlying mechanisms of emotion induction
Fiction as a bridge to action
Genre scripts and appreciation of negative emotion in the reception of film
Individual differences in embracing negatively valenced art: The roles of openness and sensation seeking
Live theatre as exception and test case for experiencing negative emotions in art
Orange is the new aesthetic
Parental response to baby cry involves brain circuits for negative emotion Distancing-Embracing
Positivity versus negativity is a matter of timing
Psychological models of art reception must be empirically grounded
Reconciling an underlying contradiction in the Distancing-Embracing model
The enjoyment of negative emotions in the experience of magic
The paradox of tragedy and emotional response to simulation
The urge to judge: Why the judgmental attitude has anything to do with the aesthetic enjoyment of negative emotions
Tuning in to art: A predictive processing account of negative emotion in art
What is art and how does it differ from aesthetics?
You are not alone – Social sharing as a necessary addition to the Embracing factor
“Negative emotions” live in stories, not in the hearts of readers who enjoy them
Author response
Negative emotions in art reception: Refining theoretical assumptions and adding variables to the Distancing-Embracing model