Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T19:16:36.409Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Are involuntary autobiographical memory and déjà vu cognitive failures?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 November 2023

John H. Mace*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Eastern Illinois University, Charleston, IL, USA [email protected] https://www.eiu.edu/psych/

Abstract

This commentary supports Barzykowski and Moulin's model, but departs from it on the question of functionality, where IAMs and déjà vu fractionate. The authors seem to say that IAMs are functional, while déjà vu is not. As there is no hard evidence supporting the idea that IAMs are functional, I argue that both phenomena should be viewed as cognitive failures.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Barzykowski and Moulin (B&M) present an interesting model for understanding involuntary autobiographical memories (IAMs) and déjà vu, two mysterious cognitive phenomena. They argue that déjà vu is the likely non-functional by-product (or “side effect”) of other cognitive processes, and while they make similar arguments for IAMs, they seem to indicate that IAMs have, in contrast, many functions (see Table 1 in their article). It is at this point, the question of adaptive functionality (e.g., Baddeley, Reference Baddeley, Gruneberg, Morris and Sykes1988; Bluck & Alea, Reference Bluck, Alea, Webster and Haight2002), that I depart from their model. It is not clear to me how one (déjà vu) is seen as a cognitive failure and the other (IAM) is not. There is plenty of evidence that IAMs are by-products of other processes (e.g., unique cuing and priming; Ball, Reference Ball2015; Berntsen, Staugaard, & Sørensen, Reference Berntsen, Staugaard and Sørensen2013; Johannessen & Berntsen, Reference Johannessen and Berntsen2010; Mace, Reference Mace2005; Mace & Kruchten, Reference Mace and Kruchten2022; Mace, McQueen, Hayslett, Staley, & Welch, Reference Mace, McQueen, Hayslett, Staley and Welch2019; Mace & Unlu, Reference Mace and Unlu2020, see target article). It is also reasonable to assume, even without this evidence, that IAMs, like déjà vu, may merely be cognitive failures. Thus, my commentary focuses on the idea that IAMs, like déjà vu and other similar phenomena, may be cognitive failures.

Proponents of the view that IAMs are functional have a number of challenges to overcome. For example, questionnaire studies on IAM functions report functional hit rates ranging from one- to two-thirds (e.g., Mace & Atkinson, Reference Mace, Atkinson and Kelly2009; Rasmussen & Berntsen, Reference Rasmussen and Berntsen2011; Rasmussen, Ramsgaard, & Berntsen, Reference Rasmussen, Ramsgaard and Berntsen2015). One challenge is to explain how an evolved adaptive mechanism functions with such a low hit rate, presuming these numbers can be accepted. Relatedly, many of the reported functions in these studies can be seen as dubious (e.g., an IAM was entertaining or it made one feel better). Function theorists will also need to show how responses like these are functional, and not merely the function of the means used to assess the question, the survey method. Another challenge is to explain how an evolved adaptive mechanism, one which presumably reads the environment in some way to produce needed memories, interfaces with the cuing and priming variables to accomplish the same task. Indeed, aligning the function hypothesis with variables that seem to independently produce IAMs may prove challenging.

One additional explanatory variable for IAMs is the concept of retrieval mode (Tulving, Reference Tulving1983), a phenomenon which the target article addresses. Though originally discussed by Tulving (Reference Tulving1983) as a tentative proposition, there is now good evidence that when the cognitive system is focused on intentional retrieval that stimuli are treated as episodic cues and memories of the past come to mind automatically and effortlessly (e.g., Herron, Reference Herron2018; see also Rugg & Wilding, Reference Rugg and Wilding2000). This process has been shown to be a routine, and often dominant, part of voluntary recall in autobiographical memory (e.g., Uzer, Lee, & Brown, Reference Uzer, Lee and Brown2012, known as direct retrieval, see also Conway, Reference Conway2005, and the literature on direct retrieval). It is certainly possible that some IAMs may be the product of retrieval mode, a state which may be initiated inadvertently by aspects of the internal and external environment (e.g., Mace, Reference Mace and Mace2010). If some IAMs are the products of retrieval mode gone awry, then this variable, too, would need to be aligned with the functional mechanism approach. However, this could be the more promising case if one could show that all IAMs were a function of the retrieval mode state, and such a state was not functioning erratically, but purposefully. This would raise a set of additional questions (e.g., the role of intent, or covert intent), and it clearly would be difficult to establish (but see Herron, Reference Herron2018, and the retrieval mode and orientation literature).

Another problem concerns individual perceptions of spontaneous processes. Perceptions of IAMs are likely to differ greatly from déjà vu and other spontaneous processes, like action slips (e.g., Norman & Shallice, Reference Norman, Shallice, Davidson, Schwartz and Shapiro1986; Reason, Reference Reason, Underwood and Stevens1979). A déjà vu is likely to be seen as a false impression, an impossibility, and the circumstance may often reveal that. The experience of IAMs, though, can be quite different. They can be perceived as pleasant, circumstantially congruent relivings of one's past (e.g., Berntsen, Reference Berntsen1998). As snippets of one's past, individuals may be more likely to imbue them with meaning, perceive them as functional, or imagine that they must be, even if they cannot see how. Such perceptions are likely to taint any self-report measure, and the design of such measures may only reinforce them. Given that experimental means are currently unavailable to answer questions of function (e.g., see interesting discussions in Downes, Reference Downes, Heams, Huneman, Lecointre and Silberstein2015), researchers have been forced to rely on self-report measures, like surveys. This presents another challenge for function theorists, as they also need to show that the data from such approaches are largely free of bias, or they can distinguish biased from unbiased data. A good example of potentially biased data are the dubious responses mentioned above, which do account for a substantial portion of the data (see Rasmussen et al., Reference Rasmussen, Ramsgaard and Berntsen2015). Researchers need to be cognizant of how personal biases might affect survey data, and guard against their own.

Thus, there are many challenges to the position that IAMs are functional, or sometimes can be. Because reliable means do not exist to adequately answer this question, the default, interim position, that IAMs are cognitive failures like déjà vu, appears to be the logical and prudent choice. Involuntary remembering can be explained in absence of a functional account. A number of variables have been identified as sources of IAMs (e.g., cuing, priming, and perhaps retrieval mode), variables which appear to independently cause them. B&M's model of IAM and déjà vu may work better if they presume the default position for both phenomena. Their model, and others, should treat IAM and déjà vu similarly if and until the function question can be answered. Alternative use accounts are possible (i.e., how memories might get used, Bluck, Alea, Habermas, & Rubin, Reference Bluck, Alea, Habermas and Rubin2005), but they should not be taken for function accounts.

Financial support

The writing of this commentary was not funded.

Competing interest

None.

References

Baddeley, A. (1988). But what the hell is it for? In Gruneberg, M. M., Morris, P. E. & Sykes, R. N. (Eds.), Practical aspects of memory: Current research and issues, vol. 1. Memory in everyday life (pp. 318). John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Ball, C. T. (2015). IAMs and restrained eating. Consciousness and Cognition, 33, 237244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berntsen, D. (1998). Voluntary and involuntary access to autobiographical memory. Memory, 6, 113141.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berntsen, D., Staugaard, S. R., & Sørensen, L. M. T. (2013). Why am I remembering this now? Predicting the occurrence of involuntary (spontaneous) episodic memories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 142, 426444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, S., & Alea, N. (2002). Exploring the functions of autobiographical memory: Why do I remember the autumn? In Webster, J. D. & Haight, B. K. (Eds.), Critical advances in reminiscence work: From theory to application (pp. 6175). Springer Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Bluck, S., Alea, N., Habermas, T., & Rubin, D. C. (2005). A TALE of three functions: The self- reported uses of autobiographical memory. Social Cognition, 23, 97117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conway, M. A. (2005). Memory and the self. Journal of Memory and Language, 53, 594628.Google Scholar
Downes, S. M. (2015). Evolutionary psychology, adaptation and design. In Heams, T., Huneman, P., Lecointre, G. & Silberstein, M. (Eds.), Handbook of evolutionary thinking in the sciences (pp. 659673). Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herron, J. E. (2018). Direct electrophysiological evidence for the maintenance of retrieval orientations and the role of cognitive control. NeuroImage, 172, 228238.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Johannessen, K. B., & Berntsen, D. (2010). Current concerns in involuntary and voluntary autobiographical memories. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 847860.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mace, J. H. (2005). Priming involuntary autobiographical memories. Memory, 13, 874884.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mace, J. H. (2010). Involuntary remembering and voluntary remembering: How different are they? In Mace, J. H. (Ed.), The act of remembering: Toward an understanding of how we recall the past (pp. 183201). Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mace, J. H., & Atkinson, E. (2009). Can we determine the functions of everyday involuntary autobiographical memories? In Kelly, M. (Ed.), Applied memory (pp. 199–212). Nova Science Publishers.Google Scholar
Mace, J. H., & Kruchten, E. A. (2022). Semantic-to-autobiographical memory priming causes involuntary autobiographical memory production: The effects of single and multiple prime presentations. Memory & Cognition, 51, 115–128.Google ScholarPubMed
Mace, J. H., McQueen, M. L., Hayslett, K. E., Staley, B. A., & Welch, T. J. (2019). Semantic memories prime autobiographical memories: Implications for everyday autobiographical remembering. Memory & Cognition, 47, 299312.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mace, J. H., & Unlu, M. (2020). Semantic-to-autobiographical memory priming occurs across multiple sources: Implications for autobiographical remembering. Memory & Cognition, 48, 931941.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Norman, D. A., & Shallice, T. (1986). Attention to action: Willed and automatic control of behaviour. In Davidson, R. J., Schwartz, G. E. & Shapiro, D. E. (Eds.), Consciousness and self-regulation (pp. 114). Plenum Press.Google Scholar
Rasmussen, A. S., & Berntsen, D. (2011). The unpredictable past: Spontaneously retrieved autobiographical memories outnumber autobiographical memories retrieved strategically. Consciousness and Cognition, 20, 18421846.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rasmussen, A. S., Ramsgaard, S. B., & Berntsen, D. (2015). The frequency and functions of involuntary and voluntary autobiographical memories across the day. The Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research and Practice, 2, 185205.Google Scholar
Reason, J. (1979). Actions not as planned. In Underwood, G. & Stevens, R. (Eds.), Aspects of consciousness (pp. 6789). Academic Press.Google Scholar
Rugg, M. D., & Wilding, E. L. (2000). Retrieval processing and episodic memory. Trends Cognitive Sciences, 4, 108115.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Uzer, T., Lee, P.J., & Brown, N.R. (2012). On the prevalence of directly retrieved autobiographical memories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 38, 12961308.Google ScholarPubMed