Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T04:20:50.614Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The model-companion of a class of structures1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

G. L. Cherlin*
Affiliation:
Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut 06520

Extract

If Σ is the class of all fields and Σ* is the class of all algebraically closed fields, then it is well known that Σ* is characterized by the following properties:

(i) Σ* is the class of models of some first order theory K*.

(ii) If m1m2 are in Σ* and m1m2 then m1m2 (m1 is an elementary substructure of m2, i.e. any first order sentence true in m1 is true in m2).

(iii) If m1 is in Σ then there is a structure m2 in Σ* such that m1m2.

If Σ is some other class of models of a first order theory K and a subclass Σ* of Σ exists satisfying (i)–(iii) then Σ* is uniquely determined and K* (which is unique up to logical equivalence) is called the model-companion of K. This notion is a generalization of the fundamental notion of model-completion introduced and extensively studied by A. Robinson [6], When the model-companion exists it provides the basis for a satisfactory treatment of the notion of an algebraically closed model of K.

Recently A. Robinson has developed a more general formulation of the notion of “algebraically closed” structures in Σ, which is applicable to any inductive elementary class Σ of structures (by elementary we always mean ECΔ). Condition (i) must be weakened to

(i′) Σ* is closed under elementary substructure (i.e. if m1 is in Σ* and m2m1 then m2 is in Σ*).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1972

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

The material in this paper is taken from my doctoral dissertation (Yale, 1971). Research supported by an NSF Graduate Fellowship. I would like to express my gratitude for the guidance given by my advisor, Abraham Robinson. I am also indebted to Jim Schmerl for highly constructive criticism.

References

REFERENCES

[1]Coven, C., Forcing in infinitary languages, Doctoral Dissertation, Yale University, New Haven, Ct., 1971.Google Scholar
[2]Eklof, P. and Sabbagh, G., Model-completions and modules, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 2 (1971), pp. 251295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Fisher, E., Homogeneous universal models revisited (in preparation).Google Scholar
[4]Kaiser, K., Über eine Verallgemeinerung der Robinsonschen Modellvervollständigung. I, Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 15 (1969), pp. 3748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5]Karp, C., Languages with expressions of infinite length, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1964.Google Scholar
[6]Robinson, A., Introduction to model theory and to the metamathematics of algebra, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1963.Google Scholar
[7]Robinson, A., Infinite forcing in model theory, Proceedings of the Second Scandinavian Logic Symposium (Fenstad, J., Editor), North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1971, pp. 317340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8]Robinson, A., Forcing in model theory, International Congress of Mathematicians, Nice, 1970.Google Scholar
[9]Robinson, A., On the notion of algebraic closedness for noncommutative groups and fields, this Journal, vol. 36 (1971), pp. 441444.Google Scholar
[10]Saracino, D., Infinite forcing in model theory and m-existentially closed structures, Notices of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 18 (1971), p. 668. Abstract 71T-E62.Google Scholar
[11]Scott, W., Algebraically closed groups, Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 2 (1951), pp. 118121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12]Cherlin, G., Second order forcing, algebraic completeness, and large cardinals (in preparation).Google Scholar