Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T09:57:00.721Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Deliberation is (probably) triggered and sustained by multiple mechanisms

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 July 2023

Gordon Pennycook*
Affiliation:
Hill/Levene Schools of Business, University of Regina, Regina, SK, Canada Department of Psychology, University of Regina, Regina, SK, Canada [email protected] gordonpennycook.com

Abstract

De Neys proposes that deliberation is triggered and sustained by uncertainty. I argue that there are cases where deliberation occurs with low uncertainty – such as when problems are excessively complicated and the reasoner decides against engaging in deliberation – and that there are likely multiple factors that lead to (or undermine) deliberation. Nonetheless, De Neys is correct to surface these issues.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

De Neys argues – lucidly, in my view – that dual-process theories have been (largely) ill-focused. Indeed, it seems that the core aspect of any dual-process model is not simply how it describes the two types of processes (or “systems”), but rather how describes the interaction between the processes. To this end, De Neys proposes that uncertainty is the key explanatory factor that determines when “type 2” deliberation is triggered (i.e., the “switch feature”).

Although many popular dual-process models have ignored the issue, as noted by De Neys, there is nonetheless a growing body of work that has focused on understanding what triggers deliberation. If intuitive (“type 1”) processing is autonomous (i.e., it is triggered automatically from some stimulus or thought process), as myself and others have argued (e.g., Pennycook, Reference Pennycook and De Neys2017; Thompson, Reference Thompson2013), then deliberative processes must be triggered by some underlying cognitive factor or factors. That is, when explaining the progeny of the process, intuitive processes can be explained by simple stimulus–response pairings. However, one needs to posit additional factors that would then lead to subsequent deliberative processes.

In my past work, I have focused on the potential role of response conflict in triggering deliberation (Pennycook, Reference Pennycook2023; Pennycook, Fugelsang, & Koehler, Reference Pennycook, Fugelsang and Koehler2015) – that is, cases where the system detects a conflict between intuitive outputs lead to subsequent deliberation. The three-stage dual-process model separates the initial “intuition” stage (where processes are initiated autonomously) from the subsequent “metacognition” stage (where conflicts between outputs of stage 1 are monitored). The presence or absence of conflict then determines the extent of deliberation in the final “reason” stage. This matches well with the sort of tasks that are common in the literature because they typically involve a salient (but incorrect) intuition that conflicts with some other relevant (and more normatively accurate) factor. However, as De Neys notes, a model that focuses solely on intuitive conflict does not help explain why deliberation occurs in the absence of intuitions.

To solve this problem, De Neys argues that general uncertainty casts a wider net and can explain both cases where conflict detection leads to deliberation but also cases where there are no apparent intuitions present. As conflict between intuitions leads to uncertainty, so to does a lack of clear answer. There is a lot to like about this proposal; however, I am hesitant to adopt uncertainty as the key explanatory factor.

One possibility is that “uncertainty” is merely correlated with the underlying causal feature (or features) that trigger deliberation. Indeed, there may be cases when uncertainty is high but deliberation is low. For example, when an individual is facing a problem that is prohibitively complicated they surely have a feeling of high uncertainty – nonetheless, the individual may decide to not engage in deliberation and to simply not bother attempting a solution (and, indeed, people do tend to prefer tasks that require less cognitive effort; Chong, Bonnelle, & Husain, Reference Chong, Bonnelle, Husain, Studer and Knecht2016; Shenhav et al., Reference Shenhav, Musslick, Lieder, Kool, Griffiths, Cohen and Botvinick2017). Hence, in such a scenario uncertainty would not lead to deliberation.

De Neys has offered a strong framework for understanding how type 1 outputs contribute to the engagement of subsequent deliberation. He even mentions a similar case where deliberation does not lead to an answer and the individual decides to stop deliberating. This is accommodating by noting that opportunity cost could be factored into the uncertainty parameter. However, one may question at that point whether deliberation is prompted by several separate mechanisms and that uncertainty is just a reasonable proxy for many of them.

This issue is related to recent work in the cognitive control literature that has investigated what might lead individuals to engage in effortful processing across situations. For example, the expected-value-of-control model posits that people weigh the costs and benefits of exerting mental effort (Shenhav, Botvinick, & Cohen, Reference Shenhav, Botvinick and Cohen2013; Shenhav, Prater Fahey, & Grahek, Reference Shenhav, Prater Fahey and Grahek2021). Of course, it may be that this calculation only occurs after deliberative processes have been initiated by some other process and therefore that costs/benefits play a role in how much deliberation occurs, not whether it is triggered in the first place. Nonetheless, if one takes the view that dual processes can be considered as opposite poles of a single continuum (as opposed to two fundamentally separate processes; De Neys, Reference De Neys2021), then the expected value of control is a factor that may play a role in whether substantive deliberation occurs. This is noted by De Neys but the implications for the focus on uncertainty are not addressed.

Relatedly, a great deal of research has focused on apparent individual differences in the willingness to engage in deliberation (see Pennycook [Reference Pennycook2023] for a review). If one were to focus solely on uncertainty as the factor that triggers deliberation, this would presume that individual differences in uncertainty-related processes (e.g., sensitivity to uncertainty) would be central. However, individual differences in deliberation tend to focus on whether people are willing to engage in cognitive effort (e.g., in the “Need for Cognition” scale; Petty, Brinol, Loersch, & McCaslin, Reference Petty, Brinol, Loersch, McCaslin and Hoyle2009) or in the willingness to question one's intuitions and prior beliefs (e.g., in the “Actively Open-minded Thinking” scale; Pennycook, Cheyne, Koehler, & Fugelsang, Reference Pennycook, Cheyne, Koehler and Fugelsang2020). Here too, the key factors that explain whether people engage in a meaningful level of deliberation may not be explained very well by appealing to uncertainty.

To conclude, I agree wholeheartedly with De Neys's argument that the underlying assumptions of many dual-process theories are poorly conceived – particularly as it related to the exclusivity feature. However, I am less convinced that deliberation can be explained by a single underlying causal mechanism. It seems likely to me that there are multiple separate mechanisms that are relevant for understanding why deliberation occurs. In any case, even if I am uncertain about using uncertainty as a key mechanism in dual-process models, I am nonetheless convinced that De Neys's proposal is certainly a step forward.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interest

The author has co-authored research with the author of the target article in the last 5 years. There are no other conflicts of interests to declare.

References

Chong, T. T.-J., Bonnelle, V., & Husain, M. (2016). Chapter 4 – Quantifying motivation with effort-based decision-making paradigms in health and disease. In Studer, B. & Knecht, S. (Eds.), Progress in brain research (Vol. 229, pp. 71100). Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/bs.pbr.2016.05.002Google Scholar
De Neys, W. (2021). On dual and single process models of thinking. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16, 14121427.10.1177/1745691620964172CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pennycook, G. (2017). A perspective on the theoretical foundation of dual-process models. In De Neys, W. (Ed.), Dual process theory 2.0 (pp. 539). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315204550CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pennycook, G. (2023). A framework for understanding reasoning errors: From fake news to climate change and beyond. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 67, 131208. https://doi.org/10.1016/bs.aesp.2022.11.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pennycook, G., Cheyne, J. A., Koehler, D. J., & Fugelsang, J. A. (2020). On the belief that beliefs should change according to evidence: Implications for conspiratorial, moral, paranormal, political, religious, and science beliefs. Judgment and Decision Making, 15, 476498. https://doi.org/10.31234/OSF.IO/A7K96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pennycook, G., Fugelsang, J. A., & Koehler, D. J. (2015). What makes us think? A three-stage dual-process model of analytic engagement. Cognitive Psychology, 80, 3472. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogpsych.2015.05.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Petty, R. E., Brinol, P., Loersch, C., & McCaslin, M. J. (2009). The need for cognition. In M. R. L. & Hoyle, R. H. (Eds.), Handbook of individual differences in social behavior (pp. 318329). Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Shenhav, A., Botvinick, M., & Cohen, J. (2013). The expected value of control: An integrative theory of anterior cingulate cortex function. Neuron, 79(2), 217240. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2013.07.007CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shenhav, A., Musslick, S., Lieder, F., Kool, W., Griffiths, T. L., Cohen, J. D., & Botvinick, M. M. (2017). Toward a rational and mechanistic account of mental effort. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 40(1), 99124. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-neuro-072116-031526CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shenhav, A., Prater Fahey, M., & Grahek, I. (2021). Decomposing the motivation to exert mental effort. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 30(4), 307314. https://doi.org/10.1177/09637214211009510CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thompson, V. A. (2013). Why it matters: The implications of autonomous processes for dual process theories – Commentary on Evans & Stanovich (2013). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 253256. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691613483476CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed