Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T16:23:04.509Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE MODAL LOGIC OF STONE SPACES: DIAMOND AS DERIVATIVE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 January 2010

GURAM BEZHANISHVILI*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematical Sciences, New Mexico State University
LEO ESAKIA*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematical Logic, A. Razmadze Mathematical Institute
DAVID GABELAIA*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematical Logic, A. Razmadze Mathematical Institute
*
*DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES, NEW MEXICO STATE UNIVERSITY, LAS CRUCES, NM 88003. E-mail:[email protected]
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICAL LOGIC, A. RAZMADZE MATHEMATICAL INSTITUTE, M. ALEKSIDZE STR. 1, TBILISI 0193, GEORGIA. E-mail:[email protected]
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICAL LOGIC, A. RAZMADZE MATHEMATICAL INSTITUTE, M. ALEKSIDZE STR. 1, TBILISI 0193, GEORGIA. E-mail:[email protected]

Abstract

We show that if we interpret modal diamond as the derived set operator of a topological space, then the modal logic of Stone spaces is K4 and the modal logic of weakly scattered Stone spaces is K4G. As a corollary, we obtain that K4 is also the modal logic of compact Hausdorff spaces and K4G is the modal logic of weakly scattered compact Hausdorff spaces.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Abashidze, M. (1988). Ordinal completeness of the Gödel-Löb modal system. In Intensional logics and the logical structure of theories, ed. Smirnov, V. and Bezhanishvili, M. (In Russian) (Telavi, 1985). Tbilisi, Georgia: Metsniereba, pp. 4973.Google Scholar
Aiello, M., van Benthem, J., & Bezhanishvili, G. (2003). Reasoning about space: The modal way. Journal of Logic and Computation, 13(6), 889920.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G., Esakia, L., & Gabelaia, D. (2005). Some results on modal axiomatization and definability for topological spaces. Studia Logica, 81(3), 325355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G., & Morandi, P. J. (2010). Scattered and hereditarily irresolvable spaces in modal logic. Archive for Mathematical Logic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chagrov, A., & Zakharyaschev, M. (1997) Modal Logic, volume 35 of Oxford Logic Guides. New York, NY: The Clarendon Press Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelking, R. (1977). General Topology. Warsaw, Poland: PWN—Polish Scientific Publishers.Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (1981). Diagonal constructions, Löb’s formula and Cantor’s scattered spaces. In Studies in logic and semantics, ed. Mikeladze, Z. (In Russian). Tbilisi, Georgia: Metsniereba, pp. 128143.Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (2002). A modal version of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem, and the McKinsey system. In Logical Investigations, No. 9, ed. Karpenko, A. (In Russian). Moscow, Russia: Nauka, pp. 292300.Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (2004). Intuitionistic logic and modality via topology. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 127(1–3), 155170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabelaia, D. (2004). Topological semantics and two-dimensional combinations of modal logics. PhD Thesis, King’s College, London.Google Scholar
McKinsey, J. C. C., & Tarski, A. (1944). The algebra of topology. Annals of Mathematics, 45, 141191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shehtman, V. (1990). Derived sets in Euclidean spaces and modal logic. Preprint X-90-05, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Terasawa, J. (1997). Metrizable compactification of ω is unique. Topology and its Applications, 76, 189191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar