Article contents
Republican Ideals and Contemporary Realities
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2009
Extract
Despite its enduring appeal, the republican vision of political life has been the subject of numerous recent criticisms. Both its relevance to an age of large-scale organizations and its desirability in an era which professes concern for individual autonomy has been questioned. However, a reconsideration of these challenges to republicanism suggests that they can be effectively met without sacrificing the core values of republicanism. Consequently, by adapting it to contemporary political realities the republican ideal can in fact serve as an apt antidote against many current political ills. Admittedly, though, any form of republicanism that is going to be viable today will assume a character at odds with either republicanism's classical or commercial modes.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1984
References
1 Arendt, Hannah, On Revolution (New York, 1963).Google Scholar
2 Wolin, Sheldon, Politics and Vision (Boston, 1960).Google Scholar
3 Pocock, J. G. A., The Machiavellian Moment (Princeton, 1975).Google Scholar
4 Thurow, Lester, The Zero-Sum Society (New York, 1980);Google ScholarGalbraith, J. K., Economics and the Public Purpose (New York, 1973).Google Scholar
5 Habermas, Jürgen, Legitimation Crisis (Boston, 1975).Google Scholar
6 Dahl, Robert, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy (New Haven, 1982).Google Scholar
7 The quotation is from Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. For a discussion of this, see Mosher, Michael, “Civic Identity in the Juridical Society,” Political Theory, 02 1983, 117 ff.Google Scholar
8 Two asides are in order. First, the action-behavior distinction alluded to here is most prominent in ordinary language analysis. Second, the suggestion that an action's results are predictable is sure to give pause to those who see this running counter to Arend't claims. However, the predictability implied here is a minimalist one: nothing more is at stake than the contention that actions only persist so long as the actors themselves feel that certain results will flow from their acts. If this belief were consistently frustrated, then acting itself would disappear as we collectively wallowed in despair.
9 These possible goals for action are those implied by Arendt and Machiavelli, respectively.
10 Arendt, H., The Human Condition (New York, 1958).Google Scholar
11 Pocock, , Machiavellian Moment, pp. 211–18.Google Scholar
12 Ibid., pp. 446–461.
13 Ibid., p. 197; Wills, Garry, Explaining America (New York, 1981).Google Scholar
14 Pocock, , Machiavellian Moment, p. 165.Google Scholar
15 Ibid., p. 213.
16 There is, of course, a problem in this formulation, for it is haunted by a certain circularity of argument. Specifically, there is a sense in which worthy acts are necessary if one is to create a public space. Likewise, a public space is to some degree necessary if there are to be worthy acts. In this sense, a public space is both precondition for and consequence of the practice of virtue. Occasionally, republicanism has avoided confronting this issue by simply circumventing it: by invoking an event whose consequences or a person whose actions set the republican experience in motion. Hence, the recourse to “explanation” by way of the sagacious lawgiver or the founding experience. Just as often, though, republicans have contented themselves with a more mundane and less-heroic rendering – one which relies more fully on an evolutionary conception of the republic's rise. To some extent, Machiavelli's account of (or better yet, well-nigh silence on) the rise of Venice fits this pattern, as indeed, with emendations, does his discussion of Rome.
17 Pocock, , Machiavellian Moment, p. 210.Google Scholar
18 Ibid., p. 212 and p. 410.
19 See Arendt, , Human Condition, p. 30 ff.Google Scholar
20 Ibid., p. 30 ff; Pocock, , Machiavellian Moment, p. 210.Google Scholar
21 Saxonhouse, Arlene W., “Men, Women, War, and Politics,” Political Theory 8 (02 1980), 65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
22 Arendt, , Human Condition, p. 30.Google Scholar One might recall, as well, Captain Vere's speech to his officers during Billy Budd's court-martial. As Vere said, “do these buttons that we wear attest that our allegiance is to Nature? No, to the King. Though the ocean, which is inviolate Nature primeval, though this be the element where we move … as sailors, yet as the King's officers lies our duty in a sphere correspondingly natural? So little is that true that, in receiving our commissions, we in most regards ceased to be natural free agents” (Melville, H., Billy Budd [New York: Signet, 1961], p. 68).Google Scholar
23 Arendt, , Human Condition.Google Scholar
24 MacWilliams, Wilson C., “On Equality as the Moral Foundation for Community,” in The Moral Foundations of the American Republic, ed. Horwitz, R. H., 2nd ed. (Charlottesville, 1979), pp. 183–213.Google Scholar
25 Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice (New York, 1983).Google Scholar
26 Kant, I., “Eternal Peace,” The Philosophy of Kant, Friedrich, C. J., ed. (New York: Modern Library, 1949), p. 448 ff.Google Scholar
27 Pocock, , Machiavellian Moment, p. 165.Google Scholar
28 MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (Notre Dame, Indiana, 1981),Google Scholar argues, as have countless others, that the effort to remove teleological components from our understanding of man is both misguided and philosophically illegitimate.
29 Pocock, , Machiavellian Moment, p. 552.Google Scholar
30 Gunnell, John, Political Theory: Tradition and Interpretation (Cambridge, Mass., 1979), pp. 136–61.Google ScholarPopper, Karl, The Open Society and Its Enemies, 2 vols. (New York, 1962).Google Scholar
31 Shumer, Sara, “Machiavelli: Republican Politics and Its Corruption,” Political Theory, 7 (02 1979), 5–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
32 Saxonhouse, A., “Family, Polity, and Unity,” Polity, 15 (Winter 1982), 202–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
33 For Arendt's views on this, see Canovan, Margaret, “A Case of Distorted Communication: A Note on Habermas and Arendt,” Political Theory, 11 (02 1983), 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
34 Canovan, , “A Case of Distorted Communication”;Google ScholarMosher, , “Civic Identity in the Juridical Society.“Google Scholar
35 Dahl, , Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy, pp. 138–65.Google Scholar
36 Arendt, , Human Condition;Google ScholarSennett, Richard, The Fall of Public Man (New York, 1977).Google Scholar
37 Habermas, , Legitimation Crisis.Google Scholar
38 Thurow, , The Zero-Sum Society.Google Scholar
39 Dahl, , Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy, pp. 202–205.Google Scholar
40 Pateman, Carole, Participation and Political Theory (Cambridge, 1970).Google Scholar
41 Walzer, , Spheres of Justice,Google Scholar attempts both to vindicate and to reinforce distinctions within social and political life which, though not equivalent to the classical, public-private split, nonetheless bear a family resemblance to it. That he undertakes such a task testifies to the pervasiveness of the “social,” or, as Walzer phrases it, to the danger that those criteria relevant to one sphere of action will come to dominate all others. Moreover, his proposals, in terms of both political philosophy and public policy, intimate a number of ways in which such distinction might begin to break the grip of the social—and do so without recourse to utter anachronism.
42 Richter, Melvin, ed., The Political Theory of Montesquieu (Cambridge, 1977), pp. 111–22.Google Scholar Of course, Adam Smith, Alexis de Tocqueville, and countless others had doubts regarding liberalism quite akin to those of Dahl and Thurow. For a sketch of some of these, see Hirschman, Albert O., The Passions and the Interests (Princeton, 1977), pp. 67–128.Google Scholar
43 Hirsch, Fred, Social Limits to Growth (Cambridge, Mass., 1976).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
44 Hirsch, , Social Limits, p. 117 ff.Google Scholar
45 Burnham, Walter Dean, “The End of American Party Politics,” Society 7 (12 1969).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 2
- Cited by