Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T08:13:15.841Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Without Foundation: Stanley Fish and the Legal Academy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 December 2018

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Review Essay
Copyright
Copyright © American Bar Foundation, 1991 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Fish takes such a firm stand on each of his tenets that one wonders whether he would try to maintain that one could not predict that putting an arm in boiling water would very probably cause pain and tissue damage to most people most of the time. Is there not some intrinsic property of the human cell that makes it vulnerable to certain temperatures? Can we not rely sufficiently on theory of heat and cellular structure to act with as much assurance as any could desire to avoid a burning?.Google Scholar

2 The work of Toulmin that Fish discusses is Human Understanding (1972).Google Scholar

3 Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (1977).Google Scholar

4 Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (1986).Google Scholar

5 Richard Posner, Law and Literature (1988); see also id., The Problems of Jurisprudence (1990).Google Scholar

6 Roberto Unger, Knowledge and Power (Boston, 1975).Google Scholar

7 I am preparing a separate essay which, centering on postmodernism and law will examine the relationship between Fish and Unger, so I will not treat the matter here. See L. Kaplan,” Anti-Metaphysics and the Quandary of Liberal Philosophy,”Philosophy and the Social Sciences, an International Journal (forthcoming).Google Scholar

8 60 Tex. L. Rev. 495 (1982); 9 Critical Inquiry 179 (1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 Dworkin, Ronald, “Law as Interpretation,” 60 Tex. Law Review 527 (1982).Google Scholar

10 Stanley Fish, Is There a Text in This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980) (Fish, ”Text”).Google Scholar

11 Fish in one of his asides that rewards the reader sketches a reading of Agatha Christie's heroes and the nature of evil.Google Scholar

12 Ronald Dworkin,” My Reply to Stanley Fish (and Walter Benn Michaels): Please Don't Talk About Objectivity Anymore,”in W. Mitchell, ed., The Politics of Interpretation (1983).Google Scholar

13 Wolfgang Iser, The Act of Reading: A Theory of Aesthetic Response (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978).Google Scholar

14 Published in 1963.Google Scholar

15 Fish, Text.Google Scholar

16 Fish's references are here and throughout the essay to Posner's “Law and Literature: A Relationship Reargued,” published in 1986 in the Virginia Law Review, which in part has been incorporated in Posner's book Law and Literature: A Misunderstood Relationship (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1988).Google Scholar

17 Alfred Schutz, Collected Papers, ed. Maurice Natason (The Hague: Martin Nijhoff, 1962); for a summary of Schutz's work see Richard J. Bernstein, The Restructuring of Social and Political (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1978); Peter Berger & Thomas Luckmann, A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1967).Google Scholar

18 As it was indeed read, Fish points out, during the Middle Ages.Google Scholar

19 Posner at 223–43.Google Scholar

20 Published in 1989.Google Scholar

21 One issue on which Fish diverges from Carrington is on Carrington's characterization of the Critical Legal Studies movement as nihilistic. In his essay on “Fish v. Fiss,” (at 120–40), Fish argues that “nihilism is impossible” (at 139); interpretive community constrains against any possibility of unbridled interpretation even if one is a self-styled nihilist.Google Scholar

22 Fish has devoted a chapter in the book to Roberto Unger.Google Scholar

23 Kuhn related this experience in a university wide lecture he delivered at the University of Wisconsin in the late 1980s.Google Scholar