Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T00:18:09.648Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Provability of the pigeonhole principle and the existence of infinitely many primes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

J. B. Paris
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, University of Manchester, Manchester M13 9PL, England
A. J. Wilkie
Affiliation:
Institute of Mathematics, Oxford 0X1 3Lb, England
A. R. Woods
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut 06520

Extract

In this note we shall be interested in the following problems.

Problem 1. Can IΔ0 ⊢ ∀xy > x(y is prime)?

Here I Δ0 is Peano arithmetic with the induction axiom restricted to bounded (i.e. Δ0) formulae.

Problem 2. Can IΔ0 ⊢ Δ0 PHP?

Here Δ0 PHP (Δ0 pigeonhole principle) is the schema

for θ ∈ Δ0, or equivalently in IΔ0, for a Δ0 formula F(x,y)

written .

By obtaining partial solutions to Problem 2 we shall show that Problem 1 has a positive solution if IΔ0 is replaced by IΔ0 + ∀xx log(x) exists.

Our notation will be entirely standard (see for example [3] and [4]). In particular all logarithms will be to the base 2 and in expressions like log(x), (1 + ε)x, etc. we shall always mean the integer part of these quantities.

Concerning Problem 2 we remark that it is shown in [5] that for k ∈ N and F ∈ Δ0,

As far as we know this is the best result of this form, in that we do not know how to replace log(z) k by anything larger. However, as we shall show in Theorem 1, we can do much better if we increase the difference between the sizes of the domain and range of F.

In what follows let M be a countable nonstandard model of IΔ0, and let be those subsets of M defined by Δ0 formulae with parameters from M.

Theorem 1. For k ∈ N and F ∈ Δ0,

Here log0(x) = x, log k + 1(x) = log(log k (x)).

Proof. To simplify matters, consider first the case k = 1. So assume M ⊨ a log(a) exists and with and a > 1. The idea of the proof is the following.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCE

[1] Gaifman, H. and Dimitracopoulos, C., Fragments of Peano's arithmetic and the MRDP theorem, Logic and algorithmic (Zürich, 1980), Monographies de l'Enseignement Mathématique, no. 30, Universite de Genève, Geneva, 1982, pp. 187206.Google Scholar
[2] Paris, J. and Kirby, L., Σ n -collection schemes in arithmetic, Logic Colloquim '77, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1978, pp. 199209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] Paris, J. and Wilkie, A., Counting problems in bounded arithmetic, Methods in mathematical logic (proceedings of the sixth Latin American symposium on mathematical logic, Caracas, 1983), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1130, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1985, pp. 317340.Google Scholar
[4] Wilkie, A. and Paris, J., On the scheme of induction for bounded arithmetic formulas, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 35 (1987), pp. 261302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Paris, J. and Wilkie, A., Counting Δ0 sets, Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 127 (1987), pp. 6776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[6] Woods, A., Some problems in logic and number theory and their connections, Ph.D. thesis, University of Manchester, Manchester, 1981.Google Scholar