Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T08:16:10.151Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Symbols, signs, and signals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

C. J. Ducasse*
Affiliation:
Brown University

Extract

In this address, no attempt to deal with any problem of symbolic technique will be made, for even if a problem of this kind should be found that was suitable to the present occasion, I should probably lack sufficient competence in the handling of symbols to deal with it satisfactorily. It occurred to me, however, that it might be interesting to consider the nature of symbols in general, to point out certain characteristics peculiar to the symbols used by logicians and mathematicians, and to say something concerning the relations of these symbols to the knowledge of Nature. Although developments in the science of logic are not dependent on such an inquiry, it yet provides us with a perspective on the nature and importance of that science which we cannot gain so long as we attend only to the problems arising inside its field.

The symbolic relation. Our attempt to gain this perspective may well begin with the trite remark that nothing is intrinsically a symbol, but that anything is a symbol if and only if it symbolizes. Moreover, the relation called symbolizing is not a dyadic but rather a tetradic relation. That is, in order for something A to be a symbol of something B, there must be in addition C, a mind trained in a special way, and D, a certain manner in which that mind is occupied at the time. For although we do say, for instance, that a mark consisting of a little cross is the symbol of addition, the fact is of course that at times when that mark is not present to a mind, it does not symbolize addition or anything else. Moreover, even when it is present to a mind, it does not symbolize addition unless that mind has been trained in a certain manner; for obviously such a mark does not symbolize addition to the mind of a Hottentot or other wholly illiterate person.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1939

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For the defense I would give of this view of causation, see On the nature and the observability of the causal relation, Journal of philosophy, vol. 23 (1926), pp. 5768CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 When that which a semeiotic interpretandum makes us “conscious of” is not something objective but on the contrary is itself a state of consciousness (as when in some persons perception of wavy motion causes the feeling of nausea), the relation is still that of sign to signified as just described, but what we then have is a limiting case of it. That is, the person is made conscious of the feeling, not in the sense of being made to think of it, but in the sense of being made to experience that feeling itself; and that it is at the time occurring in him is something then impossible for him to doubt, i.e., it is something he completely believes, even if tacitly. Of course, in the majority of cases what we are said to believe is something not itself present to our observation at the time; but the common remark, “Seeing is believing,” indicates that ordinary usage permits us to say that we believe even what we are actually experiencing.