Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T08:28:33.120Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Taking the evolution of legal doctrine seriously: review of Katayoun Baghai, Social Systems Theory and Judicial Review: Taking Jurisprudence Seriously (Farnham: Ashgate, 2015. 188 pp. £65/£58.50)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 February 2017

Richard Nobles
Affiliation:
Department of Law, Queen Mary University of London. E-mail: [email protected].
David Schiff*
Affiliation:
Department of Law, Queen Mary University of London. E-mail: [email protected].

Extract

The endeavour to take jurisprudence seriously is addressed by Baghai, a sociologist, to those within her own discipline who fail to engage with the internal understandings of law, most particularly those exhibited within the discourse that accompanies appeal court decisions, namely the discourse that helps to establish and develop legal doctrine. In effect, the book is an appeal for sociologists to assign greater attention to legal doctrine as an object of study. But such an appeal can also be interpreted as a request for theorists who study legal doctrine to take sociology seriously – namely an invitation to legal theorists to bring sociology, or at least one version of it, to bear on their study of the evolution of doctrine. This proposal faces considerable resistance from those on both sides of this divide. Whilst Hart notoriously described The Concept of Law as an essay in both analytical jurisprudence and descriptive sociology, the analytic tradition that he sponsored has sought to augment its academic credentials by moving ever closer to philosophy rather than sociology. With the important exception of Brian Leiter's arguments for ‘naturalising jurisprudence’, the general drift of analytical jurisprudence has been towards a prioritising of philosophical methods over empirical insights. And the resistance to some rapprochement has not been limited to the philosophical side of the divide. The sociology of law has a long tradition of approaching the study of law in a manner that distances itself from the self-understandings of participants in the legal system (lawyers and especially judges). This transfers in turn into hostility towards the manner in which legal philosophy has engaged with those self-understandings, with its willingness to consider, at high levels of abstraction, whether law consists of rules, norms or principles. Rather than organising insiders' views into conceptual schemes, and then examining them for their coherence and consistency, legal sociology has generated its own facts and truths about laws and lawyers, principally using empirical methods (but also other methods) and contrasting these ‘truths’ with lawyer's self-understandings, treating the latter as an inferior form of knowledge either disconnected from reality or ideological rather than descriptive. It has also noticeably failed to engage with much of the central concern of legal philosophy – the attempt to identify law as a separate entity within society. Rather than considering the existence of law as a unity, it focuses instead on parts of law as examples of more general sociological categories, such as studying the legal profession within the sociology of professions or courts, legislatures and administrative agencies within the sociology of institutions or organisations.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Balkin, J.M. (1996) ‘Interdisciplinarity as Colonization’, Washington and Lee Law Review 53: 949970.Google Scholar
Balkin, Jack (2004) ‘What “Brown” Teaches Us about Constitutional Theory’, Virginia Law Review 90: 15371577.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (1995) Law's Community: Legal Theory in Sociological Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (1997) ‘A legal Concept of Community’, Canadian Journal of Law and Society 12: 7591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (1998) ‘Why Must Legal Ideas Be Interpreted Sociologically?’, Journal of Law and Society 25: 171192.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (2003) The Politics of Jurisprudence: A Critical Introduction to Legal Philosophy, 2nd edn. London: Lexis Nexis/Butterworths, and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (2006) Law, Culture and Society: Legal Ideas in the Mirror of Social Theory. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (2008) Living Law. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (2011) ‘Justice, Dignity, Torture, Headscarves: Can Durkheim's Sociology Clarify Legal Values?’, Social & Legal Studies 20: 320.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (2013) ‘The Jurists’ Conscience: Reflections around Radbruch’ in Del Mar, M. and Michelon, C. (eds) The Anxiety of the Jurist: Legality, Exchange and Judgement. Farnham: Ashgate, 1326.Google Scholar
Cotterrell, Roger (2014) ‘Why Jurisprudence Is Not Legal Philosophy’, Jurisprudence 5(1): 4155.Google Scholar
Duxbury, Neil (1995) Patterns of American Jurisprudence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1977a) Taking Rights Seriously. London: Duckworth, Chapter 8.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1977b) ‘Why Bakke Has No Case’, The New York Review of Books, 24/18: 10 November.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1985) A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Chapters 14, 15.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1986) Law's Empire. London: Fontana, 393–397.Google Scholar
Finnis, John (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Galligan, D.J. (2007) Law in Modern Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Graber, Christopher B. and Teubner, Ginther (1998) ‘Arts and Money: Constitutional Rights in the Private Sphere?’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18/1: 6173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H.L.A (1961/1994) The Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Horwitz, Morton J. (1992) The Transformation of American Law 1870–1960: The Crisis of Legal Orthodoxy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, Michael (2001) ‘The Construction and Demolition of the Luhmann Heresy’, Law and Critique 12(1): 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, Michael (2006) ‘What's the Use of Luhmann's Theory?’ in King, M. and Thornhill, C. (eds) Luhmann on Law and Politics: Critical Appraisals and Applications. Oxford: Hart, 3752.Google Scholar
Klatt, Matthias and Meister, Moritz (2012) The Constitutional Structure of Proportionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laswell, Harold and Mcdougal, Myers (1992) Jurisprudence for a Free Society. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Leiter, Brian (2007) Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Essays on American Legal Realism and Naturalism in Legal Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (1982) The Differentiation of Society, trans. Holmes, S. and Larmore, C.. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (1990) Essays on Self-Reference. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (2004) Law as a Social System, trans. Ziegert, K.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (2013) Theory of Society Volume Two, trans. Barrett, Rhodes. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Mcbride, Jeremy (1999) ‘Proportionality and the European Convention on Human Rights’ in Ellis, E. (ed.) The Principle of Proportionality in the Laws of Europe. Oxford: Hart, 2336.Google Scholar
Nelken, David (1993) ‘The Truth about Law's Truth’ in Febbrajo, A. and Nelken, D. (eds) European Yearbook for the Sociology of Law. Milan: Giuffre, 87163.Google Scholar
Nelken, David (1998) ‘“Blinding Insights”: The Limits of a Reflexive Sociology of Law’, Journal of Law and Society 25: 407426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelken, David (2009) ‘Changing Paradigms in the Sociology of Law’ in Beyond Law in Context: Developing a Sociological Understanding of Law. Farnham: Ashgate, Chapter 6, originally in Teubner, G. (ed.) (1988) Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society. Berlin: de Gruyter, 191296.Google Scholar
Nelken, David (2014) ‘Why Must Legal Ideas be Interpreted Sociologically? Roger Cotterrell and the Vocation of Sociology of Law’ in Nobles, R. and Schiff, D. (eds) Law, Society and Community: Socio-Legal Essays in Honour of Roger Cotterrell. Farnham: Ashgate, 2338.Google Scholar
Nobles, Richard (2012) ‘Review of Chris Thornhill: A Sociology of Constitutions’, The Modern Law Review 75(2): 290295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nobles, Richard and Schiff, David (2013) ‘Pulling Back from the Edge?’, The Modern Law Review 76(3): 620638.Google Scholar
Tamanaha, Brian Z. (1997) Realistic Socio-Legal Theory: Pragmatism and a Social Theory of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Teubner, Gunther (1997) ‘Altera Pars Audiaur: Law in the Collision of Discourses’ in Rawlings, R. (ed.) Law, Society, and Economy: Centenary Essays for the London School of Economics and Political Science 1895–1995. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 149176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teubner, Gunther (2012) Constitutional Fragments: Societal Fragments: Societal Constitutionalism and Globalization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thornhill, Chris (2011) A Sociology of Constitutions: Constitutions and State Legitimacy in Historical-Sociological Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Twining, William (2012) Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement, 2nd edn. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Verschraegen, Gert (2002) ‘Human Rights and Modern Society: A Sociological Analysis from the Perspective of Social Theory’, Journal of Law and Society 29: 258281.Google Scholar
Verschraegen, Gert (2013) ‘Differentiation and Inclusion: A Neglected Sociological Approach to Fundamental Rights’ in Madsen, M.R. and Verschraegen, G. (eds) Making Human Rights Intelligible: Towards a Sociology of Human Rights. Oxford: Hart, Chapter 3.Google Scholar