Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T12:14:07.346Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘Marshall-ing’ Social and Political Citizenship: Towards a Unified Conception of Citizenship1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2014

Abstract

Marshall's work on citizenship has become a cornerstone of most contemporary discussions of citizenship. Yet, in this article, it is argued that his work is frequently misunderstood, or misinterpreted. I argue that Marshall presents a normative argument that citizenship should be seen as a unified but dynamic concept. The unified nature of citizenship should not, however, obscure the tensions within the concept. These tensions are negotiated, so that citizenship should be seen as a complex relationship where tensions and webs of interdependence co-exist. This, it is argued, is an important theoretical framework with which to consider a issues such as the impact of the restructuring of welfare.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2005.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

An earlier version of this paper was presented to the Council of European Studies 13th International Conference of Europeanists, Chicago, 14–16 March 2002. I am grateful for all the helpful comments I received there. I am also indebted to Daniel Wincott, David Marsh and two anonymous referees for their comments and suggestions. The usual disclaimers apply.

References

2 A. Giddens, Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory, London, Macmillan, 1982.Google Scholar

3 See J. Bussemaker, ‘Introduction’, in J. Bussemaker (ed.), Citizenship and Welfare State Reform in Europe, London, Routledge, 1999, pp. 1–11; G. Himmelfarb, The Idea of Poverty: England and the Early Industrial Age, New York, Alfred A. Knopf, 1984; Giddens, Profiles and Critiques; Mann, A., ‘Ruling Class Strategies and Citizenship’, Sociology, 21: 3 (1987), pp. 339–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 King, D. and Waldron, J., ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’, British Journal of Political Science, 18: 4 (1988), pp. 415–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 Mead, L. M., ‘Citizenship and Social Policy: T. H. Marshall and Poverty’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 14: 2 (1997), pp. 197230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 G. Esping-Andersen, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1990; Korpi, W., ‘Power Politics and State Autonomy in the Development of Social Citizenship’, American Sociological Review, 54: 3 (1989), pp. 309–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 H. M. Hernes, ‘Welfare State Citizenship of Scandinavian Women’, in K. Jones and A. Jonasdottir (eds), The Political Interests of Gender, London, Sage Publications, 1988; Orloff, A. S., ‘Gender and the Social Rights of Citizenship’, American Sociological Review, 58 (1993), pp. 303–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 Halsey, A. H., ‘T. H. Marshall: Past and Present’, Sociology, 18: 1 (1984), p. 13.Google Scholar

9 T. H. Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, in T. H. Marshall Sociology at the Crossroads, London, Heinemann, 1963, pp. 67–127; King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar

10 Roche, M., ‘Citizenship, Social Theory and Social Change’, Theory and Society, 16: 3 (1987), pp. 363–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 Taylor Gooby, P., ‘Welfare State Regimes and Welfare Citizenship’, Journal of European Social Policy, 1: 2 (1991), p. 94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’.Google Scholar

13 A. M. Rees, ‘T. H. Marshall and the Progress of Citizenship’, in M. Balmer and A. Rees (eds), Citizenship Today: The Contemporary Relevance of T. H. Marshall, London, UCL Press, 1996.Google Scholar

14 R. Dahrendorf, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, in Balmer and Rees, Citizenship Today.Google Scholar

15 King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar

16 Ibid., p. 423.Google Scholar

17 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 87.Google Scholar

18 Ibid., p. 85.Google Scholar

19 Ibid., p. 91.Google Scholar

20 Roche, ‘Citizenship, Social Theory and Social Change’, p. 369.Google Scholar

21 King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar

22 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 83.Google Scholar

23 Ibid., p. 84.Google Scholar

24 Ibid., p. 100.Google Scholar

25 Ibid., p. 90.Google Scholar

26 Ibid., p. 127.Google Scholar

27 T. H. Marshall, ‘Afterthought on “Value Problems of Welfare Capitalism”: The Hyphenated Society’, in T. H. Marshall, The Right to Welfare and Other Essays, London, Heinemann, 1981, p. 129.Google Scholar

28 Halsey, A. H., ‘T. H. Marshall: Past and Present’, Sociology, 18: 1 (1984), p. 13.Google Scholar

29 King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar

30 J. M. Barbalet, Citizenship, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1988, p. 19.Google Scholar

31 See also Roche, ‘Citizenship, Social Theory and Social Change’, for a similar line.Google Scholar

32 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 73.Google Scholar

33 Ibid., p. 88.Google Scholar

34 Ibid., p. 100.Google Scholar

35 Giddens, Profiles and Critiques, p. 171.Google Scholar

36 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 127.Google Scholar

37 Ibid., p. 109.Google Scholar

38 T. H. Marshall, ‘The Right to Welfare’, in Marshall, The Right to Welfare, p. 93.Google Scholar

39 Esping Andersen, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism; Korpi, ‘Power Politics and State Autonomy’.Google Scholar

40 Lockwood, D., ‘For T. H. Marshall’, Sociology, 8: 3 (1974), p. 365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

41 Barbalet, Citizenship, p. 109.Google Scholar

42 Orloff, ‘Gender and the Social Rights of Citizenship’; C. Pateman, ‘The Patriarchal Welfare State’, in A. Gutmann (ed.), Democracy and the Welfare State, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1988, pp. 231–60.Google Scholar

43 Kymlicka, W. and Norman, W., ‘Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory’, Ethics, 104: 2 (1994), p. 370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

44 Young, I. M., ‘Polity and Group Difference: A Critique of the Ideal of Universal Citizenship’, Ethics, 99: 2 (1989), pp. 250–74;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Pateman, ‘The Patriarchal Welfare State’.

45 Kymlicka and Norman, ‘Return of the Citizen’, p. 372.Google Scholar

46 Kymlicka and Norman note that self-government rights are somewhat different and more problematic as they serve to question and weaken the bonds of the larger community.Google Scholar

47 B. Barry, Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism, Oxford, Polity Press, 2001, p. 13. It must be noted that Barry has grave reservations about rights derived from the specificities of culture.Google Scholar

48 D. King, In the Name of Liberalism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 232–3.Google Scholar

49 Mead argues: ‘There is no clear economic limit to the welfare state, only political limits to society's willingness to tax itself.’ Mead, ‘Citizenship and Social Policy’, p. 200.Google Scholar

50 Ibid., p. 203.Google Scholar

51 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 117.Google Scholar

52 King, In the Name of Liberalism, p. 249.Google Scholar

53 Mead, ‘Citizenship and Social Policy’, p. 203.Google Scholar

54 It is interesting to consider whether such criteria mean that Scandinavian countries are also lacking in their social citizenship provision, as elements of conditionality have long operated in active labour market policies. Yet there is a distinction to be drawn between what we might at one end of a spectrum term workfare and at the other end, active labour market policies. For the latter, workfare elements are present, but the programme is broader. Active labour market policies, it might be argued, see unemployment as a structural problem requiring a mixture of state policies (such as retraining, as well as job creation programmes and subsidies), and might be seen as realizing the right to work. See J. A. Drøpping, B. Hvinden and K. Vik, ‘Activation policies in the Nordic countries’, in M. Kautto, M. Heikkilä, B. Hvinden, S. Marklund and N. Ploug (eds), Nordic Social Policy: Changing Welfare States, London, Routledge, 1999, p. 138. Workfare might be characterized as a much more market-based solution, which sees unemployment as a problem of individual motivations and its focus is reducing the claimant roles. Such policies are conditional and stigmatizing. Clearly, this dichotomy is somewhat stylized. However, the closer social policy approximates to the former, the more compatible it is with the notion of social citizenship rights, and equally, the more a policy approximates the latter, the less it corresponds to what Marshall saw as a good conception of citizenship.Google Scholar

55 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 123.Google Scholar

56 Also interesting to note is that Marshall viewed the work obligation in a specific way. ‘[T]he essential duty is not to have a job and hold it, since that is relatively simple in conditions of full employment, but to put one's heart into one's job and work hard.’ Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 123. Such a view is much more consistent with the principle of equality of status as it places the work obligation, to work hard, on all, and not simply on the indigent to find work.Google Scholar

57 Radcliff, B., ‘The Welfare State, Turnout, and the Economy: A Comparative Analysis’, American Political Science Review, 86: 2 (1992), pp. 444–54; B. Rothstein, ‘Social Capital in the Social Democratic Welfare State’, Politics and Society, 29: 2 (2001), pp. 206–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Both these authors suggest that the welfare state seems to impact upon other aspects of citizenship, such as voter turnout, more general political participation and levels of social trust.