Article contents
‘Marshall-ing’ Social and Political Citizenship: Towards a Unified Conception of Citizenship1
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 28 March 2014
Abstract
Marshall's work on citizenship has become a cornerstone of most contemporary discussions of citizenship. Yet, in this article, it is argued that his work is frequently misunderstood, or misinterpreted. I argue that Marshall presents a normative argument that citizenship should be seen as a unified but dynamic concept. The unified nature of citizenship should not, however, obscure the tensions within the concept. These tensions are negotiated, so that citizenship should be seen as a complex relationship where tensions and webs of interdependence co-exist. This, it is argued, is an important theoretical framework with which to consider a issues such as the impact of the restructuring of welfare.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Author(s) 2005.
Footnotes
An earlier version of this paper was presented to the Council of European Studies 13th International Conference of Europeanists, Chicago, 14–16 March 2002. I am grateful for all the helpful comments I received there. I am also indebted to Daniel Wincott, David Marsh and two anonymous referees for their comments and suggestions. The usual disclaimers apply.
References
2 A. Giddens, Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory, London, Macmillan, 1982.Google Scholar
3 See J. Bussemaker, ‘Introduction’, in J. Bussemaker (ed.), Citizenship and Welfare State Reform in Europe, London, Routledge, 1999, pp. 1–11; G. Himmelfarb, The Idea of Poverty: England and the Early Industrial Age, New York, Alfred A. Knopf, 1984; Giddens, Profiles and Critiques; Mann, A., ‘Ruling Class Strategies and Citizenship’, Sociology, 21: 3 (1987), pp. 339–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4 King, D. and Waldron, J., ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’, British Journal of Political Science, 18: 4 (1988), pp. 415–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
5 Mead, L. M., ‘Citizenship and Social Policy: T. H. Marshall and Poverty’, Social Philosophy and Policy, 14: 2 (1997), pp. 197–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6 G. Esping-Andersen, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1990; Korpi, W., ‘Power Politics and State Autonomy in the Development of Social Citizenship’, American Sociological Review, 54: 3 (1989), pp. 309–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
7 H. M. Hernes, ‘Welfare State Citizenship of Scandinavian Women’, in K. Jones and A. Jonasdottir (eds), The Political Interests of Gender, London, Sage Publications, 1988; Orloff, A. S., ‘Gender and the Social Rights of Citizenship’, American Sociological Review, 58 (1993), pp. 303–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
8 Halsey, A. H., ‘T. H. Marshall: Past and Present’, Sociology, 18: 1 (1984), p. 13.Google Scholar
9 T. H. Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, in T. H. Marshall Sociology at the Crossroads, London, Heinemann, 1963, pp. 67–127; King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar
10 Roche, M., ‘Citizenship, Social Theory and Social Change’, Theory and Society, 16: 3 (1987), pp. 363–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
11 Taylor Gooby, P., ‘Welfare State Regimes and Welfare Citizenship’, Journal of European Social Policy, 1: 2 (1991), p. 94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’.Google Scholar
13 A. M. Rees, ‘T. H. Marshall and the Progress of Citizenship’, in M. Balmer and A. Rees (eds), Citizenship Today: The Contemporary Relevance of T. H. Marshall, London, UCL Press, 1996.Google Scholar
14 R. Dahrendorf, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, in Balmer and Rees, Citizenship Today.Google Scholar
15 King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar
16 Ibid., p. 423.Google Scholar
17 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 87.Google Scholar
18 Ibid., p. 85.Google Scholar
19 Ibid., p. 91.Google Scholar
20 Roche, ‘Citizenship, Social Theory and Social Change’, p. 369.Google Scholar
21 King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar
22 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 83.Google Scholar
23 Ibid., p. 84.Google Scholar
24 Ibid., p. 100.Google Scholar
25 Ibid., p. 90.Google Scholar
26 Ibid., p. 127.Google Scholar
27 T. H. Marshall, ‘Afterthought on “Value Problems of Welfare Capitalism”: The Hyphenated Society’, in T. H. Marshall, The Right to Welfare and Other Essays, London, Heinemann, 1981, p. 129.Google Scholar
28 Halsey, A. H., ‘T. H. Marshall: Past and Present’, Sociology, 18: 1 (1984), p. 13.Google Scholar
29 King and Waldron, ‘Citizenship, Social Citizenship and the Defence of Welfare Provision’.Google Scholar
30 J. M. Barbalet, Citizenship, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1988, p. 19.Google Scholar
31 See also Roche, ‘Citizenship, Social Theory and Social Change’, for a similar line.Google Scholar
32 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 73.Google Scholar
33 Ibid., p. 88.Google Scholar
34 Ibid., p. 100.Google Scholar
35 Giddens, Profiles and Critiques, p. 171.Google Scholar
36 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 127.Google Scholar
37 Ibid., p. 109.Google Scholar
38 T. H. Marshall, ‘The Right to Welfare’, in Marshall, The Right to Welfare, p. 93.Google Scholar
39 Esping Andersen, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism; Korpi, ‘Power Politics and State Autonomy’.Google Scholar
40 Lockwood, D., ‘For T. H. Marshall’, Sociology, 8: 3 (1974), p. 365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
41 Barbalet, Citizenship, p. 109.Google Scholar
42 Orloff, ‘Gender and the Social Rights of Citizenship’; C. Pateman, ‘The Patriarchal Welfare State’, in A. Gutmann (ed.), Democracy and the Welfare State, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1988, pp. 231–60.Google Scholar
43 Kymlicka, W. and Norman, W., ‘Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory’, Ethics, 104: 2 (1994), p. 370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
44 Young, I. M., ‘Polity and Group Difference: A Critique of the Ideal of Universal Citizenship’, Ethics, 99: 2 (1989), pp. 250–74;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Pateman, ‘The Patriarchal Welfare State’.
45 Kymlicka and Norman, ‘Return of the Citizen’, p. 372.Google Scholar
46 Kymlicka and Norman note that self-government rights are somewhat different and more problematic as they serve to question and weaken the bonds of the larger community.Google Scholar
47 B. Barry, Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism, Oxford, Polity Press, 2001, p. 13. It must be noted that Barry has grave reservations about rights derived from the specificities of culture.Google Scholar
48 D. King, In the Name of Liberalism, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 232–3.Google Scholar
49 Mead argues: ‘There is no clear economic limit to the welfare state, only political limits to society's willingness to tax itself.’ Mead, ‘Citizenship and Social Policy’, p. 200.Google Scholar
50 Ibid., p. 203.Google Scholar
51 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 117.Google Scholar
52 King, In the Name of Liberalism, p. 249.Google Scholar
53 Mead, ‘Citizenship and Social Policy’, p. 203.Google Scholar
54 It is interesting to consider whether such criteria mean that Scandinavian countries are also lacking in their social citizenship provision, as elements of conditionality have long operated in active labour market policies. Yet there is a distinction to be drawn between what we might at one end of a spectrum term workfare and at the other end, active labour market policies. For the latter, workfare elements are present, but the programme is broader. Active labour market policies, it might be argued, see unemployment as a structural problem requiring a mixture of state policies (such as retraining, as well as job creation programmes and subsidies), and might be seen as realizing the right to work. See J. A. Drøpping, B. Hvinden and K. Vik, ‘Activation policies in the Nordic countries’, in M. Kautto, M. Heikkilä, B. Hvinden, S. Marklund and N. Ploug (eds), Nordic Social Policy: Changing Welfare States, London, Routledge, 1999, p. 138. Workfare might be characterized as a much more market-based solution, which sees unemployment as a problem of individual motivations and its focus is reducing the claimant roles. Such policies are conditional and stigmatizing. Clearly, this dichotomy is somewhat stylized. However, the closer social policy approximates to the former, the more compatible it is with the notion of social citizenship rights, and equally, the more a policy approximates the latter, the less it corresponds to what Marshall saw as a good conception of citizenship.Google Scholar
55 Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 123.Google Scholar
56 Also interesting to note is that Marshall viewed the work obligation in a specific way. ‘[T]he essential duty is not to have a job and hold it, since that is relatively simple in conditions of full employment, but to put one's heart into one's job and work hard.’ Marshall, ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, p. 123. Such a view is much more consistent with the principle of equality of status as it places the work obligation, to work hard, on all, and not simply on the indigent to find work.Google Scholar
57 Radcliff, B., ‘The Welfare State, Turnout, and the Economy: A Comparative Analysis’, American Political Science Review, 86: 2 (1992), pp. 444–54; B. Rothstein, ‘Social Capital in the Social Democratic Welfare State’, Politics and Society, 29: 2 (2001), pp. 206–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Both these authors suggest that the welfare state seems to impact upon other aspects of citizenship, such as voter turnout, more general political participation and levels of social trust.
- 38
- Cited by