Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T17:07:12.188Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Heidegger on Realism and the Correspondence Theory of Truth

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

John Tietz
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University

Extract

In An Introduction to Metaphysics Heidegger asserted that “it wasnot German idealism that collapsed; rather, the age was no longer strong enough to sustain the greatness, breadth, and originality of that spiritual world, i.e., truly to realize it” (1961, p. 37). He was at this point launchinginto one of the major themes of his later work: the “darkening of the world” in the form of the materialism and “demonism” typified by the antitheses of the USSR and the USA, a polarity of seeming opposites obscuring an underlying fundamental similarity. This was the modernist faith of both cultures in the power of science to solve all of the problems that have plagued humanity for untold centuries, a faith in the power of science to tell us the absolute truth about the nature of reality. In 1955 Heidegger also characterized science and technology in “The Question Concerning Technology” as an “enframing” (Gestell), a particular dominant interpretation of reality dependent on the interest of control and which conceals far more than it reveals. For one thing, “the essence of technology isin a lofty sense ambiguous. Such ambiguity points to the mystery of all revealing, i.e., of truth” (1977a, p. 33). Although enframing “lets man endure,” only art (poiesis) as the successor of philosophy transcends techne by allowing us to see that “the essence of technologyis nothing technological” (1977a, p. 35). Much earlier, in Being and Time, he gave his first sustained account of science as the interpretationof reality driven by technological interests, and spoke of Being as the “transcendens” lying beyond “every possible character which an entity can possess” [p. 38]. It remains debatable whether this characterization of Being survived into Heidegger's later period, but despite his nostalgia for the spirituality of the early nineteenth century, the role of Beingin these earlier works might best be explained as some kind of realism.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Caputo, John 1985 “The Thought of Being and the Conversation of Mankind: The Case of Heidegger and Rorty.” 1983. Rpt. In Hermeneutics and Praxis, pp. 248–71. Edited by Hollinger, R.. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf 1956 Meaning and Necessity. 1947. Rpt. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1980 “Mental Events.” 1970. Rpt. In Donald Davidson, Essays in Actions and Events, pp. 207–27. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1984 “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.” 1974. Rpt. In Donald Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, pp. 183–98. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1986 “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge.”In Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Edited by LePore, Ernest. Oxford and New York: Blackwell, pp. 307–19.Google Scholar
Descartes, Rene 1969 Replies to the Second Objections. Translated by Wilson, Margaret. The Essential Descartes. New York: Mentor.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, Hubert 1991 Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger''s Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur 1986 The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, Eugene, and Rorty, Richard, eds. 1981 Heidegger and the History of Philosophy. The Monist, 64, 4.Google Scholar
Guignon, Charles 1983 Heidegger and the Problem of Knowledge. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1961 Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Manheim, Ralph. New York: Doubleday Anchor.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1962a Being and Time. Translated by Macquarrie, John and Robinson, Edward. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1962b “Letter on Humanism.” Translated by Lohner, E.. In Philosophy and the Twentieth Century: An Anthology, Vol. 3, pp. 270302. Edited by Barrett, William and Aiken, Henry. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1962c “Plato's Doctrine of Truth.” Translated by Barlow, John. In Philosophy and the Twentieth Century: An Anthology, Vol. 3, pp. 251–70. Edited by Barrett, William and Aiken, Henry. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1972 On Time and Being. Translated by Stambaugh, Joan. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1977a “The Question Concerning Technology.” In The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, pp. 349. Translated by Lovitt, William. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1977b “The Age of the World Picture.” In The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, pp. 115–54. Translated by Lovitt, William. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin 1984 The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Translated by Heim, Michael. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
LePore, Ernest, ed. 1986 Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford and New York: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1985 Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Okrent, Mark 1981 “The Truth of Being and the History of Philosophy.” In Freeman and Rorty (1981), pp. 500–17.Google Scholar
Okrent, Mark 1988 Heidegger's Pragmatism: Understanding, Being, and the Critique of Metaphysics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary 1978 Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1979 Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1982a Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1982b “The World Well Lost.” 1972. Rpt. In Richard Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism, pp. 318. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press (1982a).Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1982c “Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey.”1 1976. Rpt. In Richard Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism, pp. 3759. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press (1982a).Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1986 “Pragmatism, Davidson and Truth.” In Lepore (1986), pp. 333–55.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1991 “Is Natural Science a Natural Kind?” 1988. Rpt. In Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, pp. 4662. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1989 Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, Barr 1968Transcendental Arguments.” Journal of Philosophy, 65:241–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tietz, John 1980Davidson and Sellars on Persons and Science.” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 18, 2: 237–49.Google Scholar