Article contents
Constitutional Interpretation and Institutional Perspectives: A Deliberative Proposal
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 03 August 2018
Abstract
Legal scholars generally consider the theorisation and constitutionalisation of constitutional interpretation as a matter for the courts. This article first challenges this tendency on conceptual grounds, showing that no institutional commitment follows from the nature of interpretation in law, constitutional law included. It then provides guidance for thinking about institutional perspectives according to two criteria: the nature and normative strength of the sources interpreted and the capacity of the interpreter to include and consider every possibility affected when her interpretation carries collective effects and is authoritatively final. The application of these criteria places the discussion on the grounds of democratic theory. The article thus reviews competing democratic theories and champions deliberative democracy as the alternative whose constitutive features best allow for the development of institutions capable of exercising constitutional interpretation when the imposition of meaning on the constitution is final and carries erga omnes effects.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2018
Footnotes
I thank Natalia Scavuzzo, Adrian Blau, Riccardo Guastini, Koldo Casla, Jeff King, Johan Olsthoorn, Lorenzo Zucca, and Sebastian Reyes. This article results from research at the Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales in Madrid and research at the Tarello Institute for Legal Philosophy in Genoa. It is part of a research project on Popular Constitutionalism funded by CONICYT (Becas Chile—Advanced Human Capital Program, 2013-2017).
References
1. Two caveats about the focus of this article are in order. First, I will not address problems unrelated to the relationships between the notion of interpretation, institutions and democracy when that meaning has effects over the whole society. For instance, I do not address here the likely objection that giving the final word in constitutional interpretation to the same agents who should be limited by the constitution raises a rule of law problem. This is a legitimate objection, but this is not the place to tackle it. Second, it is also necessary to reflect on the specific institutional mechanisms that would make my argument empirically feasible. This essay, however, is centred on theoretical consideration and does not offer concrete institutional proposals. This endeavour deserves separate examination.
2. E.g., Richard Fallon Jr, “A Constructivist Coherence Theory of Constitutional Interpretation” (1987) 100:6 Harv L Rev 1189; Joel Bakan, “Constitutional Arguments: Interpretation and Legitimacy in Canadian Constitutional Thought” (1989) 27:1 Osgoode LJ 123; Robert Post, “Theories of Constitutional Interpretation” (1990) 209 Faculty Scholarship Series 13; Frederick Schauer, “Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution” (2004) 92:34 Cal L Rev 1045; Comella, Victor Ferreres, The Constitution of Spain. A Contextual Analysis (Hart, 2013) at 210.Google Scholar For a full treatment of this sort of accounts, see Donald Bello Hutt, “Against Judicial Supremacy in Constitutional Interpretation” (2017) 31 Revus 7.
3. Dworkin, Ronald, “Law as Interpretation” (1982) 9:1 Critical Inquiry 179 at 179;Google Scholar Dworkin, Ronald, Law’s Empire (Fontana, 1986) at 50, 87.Google Scholar See also, Christie, George C, “Dworkin’s Empire” (1987) 157 at 159;Google Scholar Raz, Joseph, Between Authority and Interpretation (Oxford University Press, 2009) at 47–48;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Simmonds, Nigel, Central Issues in Jurisprudence (Sweet & Maxwell, 2013) at 209.Google Scholar
4. Marmor, Andrei, Interpretation and Legal Theory (Clarendon Press-Oxford University Press, 1992) at 3;Google Scholar Shapiro, Scott, “The ‘Hart-Dworkin’ Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed” in Ripstein, A, ed, Ronald Dworkin (Cambridge University Press, 2007) 22 at 22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
5. Dworkin, supra note 3 (1986) at 31-44; Raz, supra note 3 at 47-48.
6. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, 1978) at 22.
7. Ibid at 22, 44-47; Genaro Carrió, “Professor Dworkin’s Views on Legal Positivism” (1979) 55:2 Ind LJ 209 at 235.
8. Simmonds, supra note 3 at 210.
9. Mandel, Michael, “Dworkin, Hart, and the Problem of Theoretical Perspective” (1979) 14:1 JL & Soc’y 57 at 61;Google Scholar Dworkin, supra note 3 (1986) at 14-15, 64; Levin, Avner, “The Participant Perspective” (2002) 21 Law & Phil 567 at 569.Google Scholar
10. Dworkin, supra note 3 (1986) at 90.
11. Wróbleski, Jan, “Legal Language and Legal Interpretation” (1985) 4:2 Law & Phil 239 at 246.Google Scholar
12. Marmor, supra note 4 at 44.
13. Fish, Stanley, “Working on the Chain Gang: Interpretation in The Law and in Literary Criticism” (1982) 9:1 Critical Inquiry 201 at 211;Google Scholar Dascal, Marcelo & Wróblewski, Jan, “Transparency and Doubt: Understanding and Interpretation in Pragmatics and in Law” (1988) 7 Law & Phil 203 at 203–04;Google Scholar Dworkin, supra note 3 (1986) at 52-53; Marmor, supra note 4 at 14, 32; Raz, supra note 4 at 250, 268; Guastini, Riccardo, “A Realistic View on Law and Legal Cognition” (2015) 27 Revus 45 at 46.Google Scholar
14. Fish, supra note 13 at 211-12; Dworkin, Freedom’s Law (Harvard University Press, 1986) at 52; Endicott, Timothy, “Putting Interpretation in its Place” (1994) 13 Law & Phil 451 at 451;Google Scholar Goldsworthy, Jeffrey, “Raz on Constitutional Interpretation” (2003) 22 Law & Phil 167 at 190;Google Scholar Guastini, supra note 13 at 47.
15. For taxonomies of these sort of mechanisms, see Bobbit, Philip, Constitutional Fate: Theory of the Constitution (Oxford University Press, 1982);Google Scholar Fallon Jr, supra note 2; Tribe, Lawrence, American Constitutional Law (The Foundation Press, 1988);Google Scholar Bakan, supra note 2 at 123-27; Post, supra note 2; Jakab, András, “Judicial Reasoning in Constitutional Courts: A European Perspective” (2013) 8 German LJ 1215.Google Scholar
16. Fish, supra note 13 at 211; Dworkin, “Law as Interpretation”, supra note 3 at 68; Wróbleski, supra note 11 at 243; Dascal & Wróblesky, supra note 13 at 210-21; Marmor, supra note 4 at 22, 154; Marmor, Andrei, The Language of Law (Oxford University Press, 2014) at 146–54;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Barnett, Randy, “Interpretation and Construction” (2011) 34 Harv J L & Pub Pol’y 65 at 66;Google Scholar Guastini, supra note 13 at 46-47.
17. Lawrence Solum, “The Unity of Interpretation” (2010) 92 Boston L Rev 551 at 568.
18. Ibid at 572.
19. Ibid at 568-69.
20. Fallon, Richard Jr, “The Meaning of Legal “Meaning” and Its Implications for Theories of Legal Interpretation” (2015) 82 U Chicago L Rev 1235 at 1272.Google Scholar
21. Ibid at 1255.
22. Ibid at 1307.
23. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, 4th ed, translated by Anscombe, G, Hacker, P & Schulte, J (Wiley-Blackwell, 2009) at §139 [emphasis in original].Google Scholar
24. Ibid at §140.
25. Ibid at 2009, §28, §32, §85.
26. Hereinafter, I use ‘decisional’ in a Schmittian sense, i.e., as unconstrained by rules/norms.
27. Marmor, supra note 4 at 44.
28. Marmor, supra note 16 at 149.
29. Ibid at 149.
30. Ibid.
31. Sunstein, Cass & Vermeule, Adrian, “Interpretation and Institutions” (2002) John M. Olin Law & Economics Working Paper 1 at 2.Google Scholar
32. My use of the term pragmatic does not refer to the philosophical construct pragmatism, understood as an alternative to realism, idealism, transcendentalism, utilitarianism, positivism, etc. Here I use the term in the way Posner does when discussing what he calls “applied pragmatism”. See Richard Posner, “Pragmatic Adjudication” (1996) 18:1 Cardozo L Rev 1 at 1. I express this caveat to anticipate the likely objection that pragmatism, understood in the first of these two senses, is also a principled alternative.
33. Ibid at 5.
34. I put aside the question of who determines which social facts count as legal sources. Judges are traditionally seen as members of what Adler calls ‘recognitional community’. See Matthew Adler, “Popular Constitutionalism and the Rule of Recognition: Whose Practices Ground U.S. Law?” (2006) 100 Nw UL Rev 719 at 726. That is, a certain group of people whose patterns of thought and behaviour ground the ultimate criteria of validity of a legal system. Hence, judges’ mental states and patterns of behaviour also count to determine which sources bind them and which do not. This problem needs more attention, however, than the one I can offer here.
35. Waldron, Jeremy, Law and Disagreement (Oxford University Press, 1999);CrossRefGoogle Scholar Waldron, Jeremy, The Dignity of Legislation (Cambridge University Press, 1999a);CrossRefGoogle Scholar Waldron, Jeremy, “Do Judges Reason Morally?” in Huscroft, G, ed, Expounding the Constitution: Essays in Constitutional Theory (Cambridge University Press, 2011) 38.Google Scholar
36. Cappelletti, Mauro, “Judicial Review in Comparative Perspective” (1970) 58:5 Cal L Rev 1017 at 1034;Google Scholar Finck, Danielle E, “Judicial Review: The United States Supreme Court versus the German Constitutional Court” (1997) 20:1 BC Int’l & Comp L Rev 123 at 126;Google Scholar de Andrade, Gustavo Fernandes, “Comparative Constitutional Law: Judicial Review” (2002) 3:3 U Pa J Const L 977.Google Scholar
37. Schor, Miguel, “Mapping Comparative Judicial Review” (2008) 7:2 Wash U Global Stud L Rev 257 at 263.Google Scholar See, e.g., Article 138 Peruvian Constitution, Article 133 Mexican Constitution, Article 266 Guatemalan Constitution, Article 185 Salvadoran Constitution, Article 4 Colombian Constitution, Article 20 Chilean Constitution. The case is similar in Canada, Australia, Ireland and South Africa. See Pegoraro, Luigi, La justicia constitucional. Una perspectiva comparada, translated by León Alonso, M, Salvador Crespo, M & Zamora Crespo, M (Dyckinson, 2004) at 69–75.Google Scholar
38. For example, the following countries’ constitutional courts: Bolivia (Article 58 of the Ley del Tribunal Constitucional), Colombia (Article 47 of the Ley Estatutaria de Administración de Justicia 1996, and article 21 of the Decreto 2067/1991), Ecuador (Article 22 of the Ley de control constitucional 1997), Peru (Article 204 of the Peruvian Constitution), Venezuela (Article 336 of the Venezuelan Constitution), Germany, Spain, among others. Rodríguez, José Fernández, La justicia constitucional europea ante el siglo XXI (Tecnos, 2007) at 110–11.Google Scholar
39. See Nogueira, Humberto, “Consideraciones sobre las sentencias de los Tribunales Constitutionales y sus efectos en América del Sur” (2004) 10:1 Ius et Praxis 113.Google Scholar In principle, this is why the US Supreme Court was given the faculty to grant writs of certiorari. See Taft, William H, “Three Needed Steps of Progress” (1922) 8:1 ABA J34 at 35;Google Scholar Sternberg, Jonathan, “Deciding Not to Decide: The Judiciary Act of 1925 and the Discretionary Court” (2008) 33:1 JSCH 1 at 9.Google Scholar Litigants before the Spanish Constitutional Court also have to prove that their claims (amparos) may “involve a legal issue of social and economic repercussion” before the court hears the complaint (Article 49 of the Ley del Tribunal Constitucional). In practice, however, these mechanisms were introduced to reduce the courts’ dockets.
40. Waldron, Jeremy, “The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review” (2006) 115 Yale LJ 1346 at 1375, 1376–86.Google Scholar
41. For example, in the United States (US Supreme Court Rule 37), Argentine (Autoacordada 28/2004), Colombia (Article 13, Decree number 2067/1991; Constitutional Court C-513/1992), Brazil (Article 2.2., Act number 9868/1999; Article 103-A Federal Constitution and Article 3.2, Act number 11417/ 2006), South-Africa (Article 10 South-African Constitution; Rule 10 South-African Constitutional Court, Promulgated under Government Notice R1675 in Government Gazette 25726 of 31 October 2003), Canada (Subrule 61(4) of the Rules of the Supreme Court).
42. Fishkin, James, “Deliberative Democracy and Constitutions” in Frankel Paul, E, Miller, F & Paul, J, eds, What Should Constitutions do? (Cambridge University Press, 2011) 242 at 251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
43. I thank Jeff King for his suggestion to address this point.
44. Finck, supra note 36 at 126-27.
45. Ibid at 125-26; Cappelletti, supra note 36 at 137.
46. This, pace, Robert Alexy, “Balancing, constitutional review, and representation” (2005) 3:4 Int’l J Const L 572 at 579, and Pierre Rosanvallon, Democratic Legitimacy: Impartiality, Reflexivity, Proximity (Princeton University Press, 2011) at 121-68. Similarly, Ely justified judicial review as a safeguard of the representative process. His view has been criticised, however, on grounds similar to the ones I here defend. Judith Koffler, “Constitutional Catarrh: Democracy and Distrust, by John Hart Ely” (1981) 1:2 Pace L Rev 403; Tribe, supra note 15 at 28; Gargarella, Roberto, La justicia frente al gobierno. Sobre el carácter contramayoritario del poder judicial (Ariel, 1996) at 154–57;Google Scholar Posner, Richard, Law, Pragmatism and Democracy (Harvard University Press, 2005) at 233.Google Scholar
47. See, e.g., the constitutions of Chile (Articles 93.1 and 93.4), France (Articles 61, paragraph 1 and 2, and 62 final paragraph), Bolivia (Articles 196 and 202.1), Colombia (Article 241.8 second paragraph).
48. Elster, Jon, “The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory” in Bohman, J & Regh, W, eds, Deliberative Democracy (MIT, 1997);Google Scholar Martí, José Luis, La República Deliberativa (Marcial Pons, 2006) at 66–73.Google Scholar
49. Of course, definitions of democracy vary. E.g., Aristotle, The Politics, translated by T Sinclair (Penguin, 1992) at 245, 1290b7; Weale, Albert, Democracy (Macmillan Press, 1999) at 19, 25;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Dahl, Robert, On Democracy (Yale University Press, 2000) at 37–43;Google Scholar Schmidt, Manfred, “Political Performance and types of democracy: Findings from comparative studies” (2002) 41 EJPR 147 at 147;Google Scholar Beetham, David, Democracy. A Beginner’s Guide (Oneworld, 2005) at 2.Google Scholar I here follow Elster, supra note 48 and Martí, supra note 48 at 66-73. For examples of typologies based on alternative criteria, see Lijphart, Arend, “Typologies of Democratic Systems” 1:1 (1968) Comparative Political Studies 3;Google Scholar Weale, ibid at 24-36; Held, David, Models of Democracy (Polity Press, 2006);Google Scholar Fishkin, supra note 42 at 245.
50. Manin, Bernard, “On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation” (1987) 15:3 Political Theory 338 at 349-53, 359;Google Scholar Miller, David, “Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice” (1992) 40:1 Political Studies 54 at 55;Google Scholar Cohen, Joshua, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy” in Bohman, J & Rehg, W, eds, Deliberative Democracy (MIT Press, 1997) 67 at 67;Google Scholar Cohen, Joshua, “Reflections on Deliberative Democracy” in Christiano, T & Christman, J, eds, Contemporary Debates in Political Philosophy (Wiley-Blackwell, 2009) 247 at 248;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Cohen, Joshua, “Democracy and Liberty” in Elster, J, ed, Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 1998) 185 at 185;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Bohman, James, “Survey Article: The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy” (1998) 6:4 J Political Philosophy 400 at 400;Google Scholar Elster, Jon, “Introduction” in Elster, J, ed, Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 1998) 1 at 5-6;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Martí, supra note 48 at 39.
51. Elster, ibid at 8.
52. Manin, supra note 50 at 359; Gutmann, Amy & Thompson, Dennis, Democracy and Disagreement (Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1996) at 4;Google Scholar Bohman, James, Public Deliberation. Pluralism, Complexity, and Democracy (MIT Press, 1996) at 4;Google Scholar Bohman, supra note 50 at 401, 402; Bohman, James, “Epistemic Value and Deliberative Democracy” (2009) 18:2 The Good Society 28 at 28;Google Scholar Cohen, supra note 50 (1997) at 67; Chambers, Simone, “Deliberative Democratic Theory” (2003) 6 Annual Review of Political Science 307 at 308;Google Scholar Martí, supra note 48 at 22.
53. Manin, supra note 48 at 359; Martí, supra note 48 at 52.
54. Schumpeter, Joseph, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (Routledge, 2003) at 269–302;Google Scholar Held, supra note 49, ch 5.
55. Downs, Anthony, An Economic Theory of Democracy (Addison Wesley, 1997).Google Scholar
56. E.g., Buchanan, James, “Social Choice, Democracy, and Free Markets” (1954) 62:2 J Political Economy 114;Google Scholar Hayek, Friedrich, The Road to Serfdom (Routledge, 1944);Google Scholar Riker, William, Liberalism against Populism. A Confrontation between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice (Freeman, 1982);Google Scholar Buchanan, James & Tullock, Gordon, The Calculus of Consent. Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy (Liberty Fund, 2004);Google Scholar Posner, supra note 46.
57. Buchanan, ibid at 117; Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Basic Books, 1974) at 33;Google Scholar Elster, supra note 48 at 3.
58. Arrow, Kenneth, Social Choice and Individual Values (Yale University Press, 2012) at 5Google Scholar See also the literature cited by Arrow at 5-6.
59. Cass Sunstein, “Interest Groups in American Public Law” (1985) 38:1 Stan L Rev 29 at 32; Martí, supra note 48 at 68.
60. Sunstein, ibid at 32; Truman, David, The Governmental Process: Political Interests and Public Opinion (Alfred A Knopf, 1951) at 15.Google Scholar
61. Martí, supra note 48 at 68; Held, supra note 49 at 170.
62. Madison, James, “The Federalist X” in Madison, J, Hamilton, A & Jay, J, The Federalist, or the New Constitution (Basil Blackwell, 1948) 41.Google Scholar
63. See Dahl, Robert, Pluralist Democracy in the United States: Conflict and Consent (Rand McNally, 1967) at 24, 365;Google Scholar Dahl, Robert, Democracy and its Critics (Yale University Press, 1989) at 221;Google Scholar Dahl, supra note 49 at 85, 113-14. Dahl’s position, however, changed over the years. For example, the criteria set on Dahl 1989 and Dahl 2000 are more demanding in normative terms than in Dahl 1967. In favour of this assertion, Martí, supra note 48 at 68 and Held, supra note 49 at 170. Moreover, in “On Deliberative Democracy: Citizens Panels and Medicare Reform” (Summer 1997), Dahl championed a model that is highly compatible with deliberative democratic theory.
64. Martí, supra note 48 at 65.
65. Ibid at 71.
66. E.g., Shapiro, Ian, “Enough of Deliberation: Politics is about Interests and Power” in Macedo, S, ed, Deliberative Politics. Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford University Press, 1999) 28Google Scholar, and Walzer, Michael, “Deliberation and What Else?” in Macedo, S, ed, Deliberative Politics. Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford University Press, 1999) 58.Google Scholar
67. Mouffe, Chantal, The Democratic Paradox (Verso, 1993) at 2;Google Scholar Martí, supra note 48 at 71.
68. Mouffe, ibid at 100.
69. With few exceptions. E.g., Hayek, Friedrich, New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics, and the History of Ideas (Routledge, 1978) at 160–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Van Parijs, Philippe, “The Disenfranchisement of the Elderly, and Other Attempts to Secure Intergenerational Justice” (1998) 27:4 Philosophy and Public Affairs 292.Google Scholar
70. Manin, supra note 50 at 352; Cohen, supra note 50, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy” at 74; Bohman, “Public Deliberation. Pluralism…”, supra note 52 at 7, 9; Bohman, supra note 50 at 400, 408-10; Nino, Carlos S, The Constitution of Deliberative Democracy (Yale University Press, 1996) at 144, 180–86;Google Scholar Martí, supra note 48 at 92-93, 211; Waldron, Law and Disagreement, supra note 35 at 105-06.
71. Habermas, Jürgen, Theory of Communicative Action. Reason and the Rationalization of Society, translated by McCarthy, Thomas (Beacon Press, 1981) at 19;Google Scholar Habermas, Jürgen, Between Facts and Norms (MIT Press, 1996) at 127.Google Scholar
72. Manin, supra note 50 at 352 [emphasis in original].
73. Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”, supra note 50 at 74; Cohen, “Democracy and Liberty”, supra note 50 at 203; Bohman, “Public Deliberation. Pluralism…”, supra note 52 at 7, 9; Bohman, supra note 50 at 400, 408-10; Elster, supra note 50 at 8; Martí, supra note 48 at 42.
74. Cohen, “Democracy and Liberty”, supra note 50 at 187; Manin, supra note 50 at 352-57; Gutmann & Thompson, supra note 52 at 43; Christiano, Thomas, The Rule of the Many. Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory (Westview Press, 1997) at 249–50.Google Scholar
75. Habermas, Between Facts, supra note 71 at 106; Bohman, supra note 50 at 400; Robert Goodin & John Dryzek, “Deliberative Impacts: The Macro-Political Uptake of Mini-Publics” (2006) 34:2 Politics and Society 219 at 20; Cohen, “Reflections…”, supra note 50 at 257; John Dryzek, “Rhetoric in Democracy: A Systemic Appreciation” (2010) 38:3 Political Theory 319 at 326; Parkinson, John, “Democratizing Deliberative Systems” in Parkinson, J & Mansbridge, J, eds, Deliberative Systems. Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale (Cambridge University Press, 2012) 151 at 152;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Cristina Lafont, “Deliberation, Participation, and Democratic Legitimacy: Should Deliberative Mini-publics Shape Public Policy?” (2015) 23:1 J Political Philosophy 40 at 42-43.
76. Young, Iris Marion, “Justice, Inclusion, and Deliberative Democracy” in Macedo, S, ed, Deliberative Politics. Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford University Press, 1999);Google Scholar Lafont, ibid.
77. Fishkin, James, When the People Speak (Oxford University Press, 2009) at 98, 191.Google Scholar
78. Ibid at 96.
79. As some debates among deliberativists show. For example, Young has criticised Gutmann & Thompson for not emphasising enough the principle of inclusion. See supra note 76 at 155. Gutmann and Thompson replied that making inclusion explicit is not necessary, for they consider that their conception “already incorporates the basic values of inclusion in the principles of reciprocity, liberty and opportunity”. See supra note 52 at 263. See also Martí, supra note 48 at 265.
80. Young, supra note 76 at 155.
81. Manin, supra note 50 at 358; Schumpeter, supra note 54 at 269; Richard Posner, “Smooth Sailing. Democracy doesn’t need Deliberation Day” (January-February 2004) Legal Affairs; Fishkin, supra note 42 at 246.
82. See Félix Ovejero Lucas, La libertad inhóspita. Modelos humanos y democracia liberal (Paidós, 2002) at 165, and Buchanan’s criticism of Arrow in supra note 56 at 121.
83. Ovejero Lucas, ibid at 167-70; Martí, supra note 48 at 67-68.
84. Young, supra note 76 at 155; Sen, Amartya, Social Exclusion: Concept, Application, and Scrutiny (Asian Development Bank, 2000) at 15.Google Scholar
85. Martí, supra note 48 at 69.
86. Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”, supra note 50 at 76-77, 78; Parkinson, supra note 75 at 159.
87. Martí, supra note 48 at 46.
88. Habermas, Jürgen, Legitimation Crisis, translated by McCarthy, Thomas (Polity Press, 1988) at 108;Google Scholar Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, supra note 71 at 107-08; Cohen, “Reflections on …”, supra note 48 at 249.
89. Elster, supra note 48 at 4, 6; Stokes, Susan, “Pathologies of Deliberation” in Elster, J, ed, Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 1998) 123 at 126;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Cohen, “Democracy and Liberty”, supra note 50 at 199; Martí, supra note 48 at 50, 90-92.
90. Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”, supra note 50 at 73.
91. Bruce Ackerman & James Fishkin, Deliberation Day (Yale University Press, 2004) at 47.
92. Ibid at 48.
93. Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”, supra note 50 at 77.
94. Elster and Making”, 1998 Elster, Jon, “Deliberation and Constitution Making” in Elster, J, ed, Deliberative Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 1998) at 102–04.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
95. Elster, supra note 50 at 8.
96. Manin, supra note 50 at 358; Bohman, supra note 50 at 405.
97. Nozick, supra note 57 at 325; Held, supra note 49 at 213; Martí, supra note 48 at 65-66.
98. Martí, ibid at 75.
99. Gutmann & Thompson, supra note 52 at 128-64; Habermas, Between Facts and Norms, supra note 71 at 183; Bohman, supra note 50 at 402; Martí, ibid at 93.
100. List, Christian & Spiekermann, Kai, “Methodological Individualism and Holism in Political Science: A Reconciliation” (2013) 107:4 American Political Science Rev 629 at 629.Google Scholar
101. Habermas, Jürgen, “Reconciliation Through the Public use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’ Political Liberalism” (1995) 92:3 J Philosophy 109 at 112–13.Google Scholar
- 4
- Cited by