Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T23:14:13.223Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Two Concepts of Conscience and their Implications for Conscience-Based Refusal in Healthcare

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 December 2016

Abstract:

Healthcare professionals are not currently obliged to justify conscientious objections. As a consequence, there are currently no practical limits on the scope of conscience-based refusals in healthcare. Recently, a number of bioethicists, including Christopher Meyers, Robert D. Woods, Robert Card, Lori Kantymir, and Carolyn McLeod, have raised concerns about this situation and have offered proposals to place principled limits on the scope of conscience-based refusals in healthcare. Here, I seek to adjudicate among their proposals. I argue that to adjudicate among them properly it is important to consider the theoretical bases for conscientious objection. I further argue that there are two such bases to be considered. Some conscientious objections are justified by appeal to all-things-considered moral judgments, and some are justified by appeal to the “dictates of conscience.” I argue that both of these bases are legitimate and that both should be accommodated in any principled scheme to limit the scope of conscientious refusals in healthcare.

Type
Special Section: Conscientious Objection in Healthcare: Problems and Perspectives
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Wicclair reports that he was unable to find any academic articles published prior to the 1960s that specifically addressed the topic of conscientious objection in healthcare. Wicclair, M. Conscientious Objection in Health Care: An Ethical Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2011:14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2. Cited by Wicclair 2011, at 16.

3. Gawande A. Whose body is it anyway? The New Yorker, October 4, 1999:84.

4. Clarke, S. Informed consent in medicine in comparison with consent in other areas of human activity. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 2001;39:173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5. Gawande, A. Complications: A Surgeon’s Notes on an Imperfect Science. London: Profile Books; 2002:210.Google Scholar

6. Wear, S. Informed Consent: Patient Autonomy and Physician Beneficence within Health Care, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1998.Google Scholar See Chapter Two in particular.

7. Guttmacher Institute. State Policies in Brief: Refusing to Provide Health Services, 2015; available at http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/spibs/spib_RPHS.pdf (last accessed 23 Oct 2015).

8. Meyers, C, Woods, RN. An obligation to provide abortion services: What happens when physicians refuse? Journal of Medical Ethics 1996;22:115–20.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

9. See note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996, at 115. In Italy, approximately 70 percent of gynecologists conscientiously object to abortion. For discussion of the difficulties this situation creates for Italian women who wish to have an abortion, see Minerva, F. Conscientious objection in Italy. Journal of Medical Ethics 2015;41:170–3.

10. See note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996, at 117.

11. The United Kingdom is another place where healthcare workers are not required to provide a justification for conscientious refusals. See Cowley C. Conscientious objection and healthcare in the UK: Why tribunals are not the answer. Journal of Medical Ethics 2016;42:69–72.

12. See note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996, at 116–7.

13. Strickland, SLM. Conscientious objection in medical students: A questionnaire survey. Journal of Medical Ethics 2012;38:23.

14. Kantymir, L, McLeod, C. Justification for conscience exemptions in healthcare. Bioethics 2014;28:16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15. Card, R. Conscientious objection and emergency contraception. American Journal of Bioethics 2007;7(6):814;CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Card, R. Conscientious objection, emergency contraception, and public policy. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 2011;36:5368.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed See also note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996, and note 14, Kantymir, McLeod 2014.

16. Salmon DA, Seigel, AW. Religious and philosophical exemptions from vaccination requirements and lessons learned from conscientious objectors from conscription. Public Health Reports 2001;116:293. The wording, cited by Salmon and Siegel, is from a 1970 Supreme Court decision: Welsh v. United States, 398 US 333.

17. Meyers, C, Woods, RN. Conscientious objection? Yes, but make sure it is genuine. American Journal of Bioethics 2007;7(6):20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18. See note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996. Meyers and Woods discuss cases in which physicians have objected to conducting abortions on the grounds that abortion services are not lucrative and that second trimester abortions are “complex and frankly ugly,” at 118. Minerva mentions the case of a conscientious objector to abortion who was caught conducing abortions in his private practice: See note 9, Minerva 2015, at 172. Presumably his motives were financial.

19. See note 17, Meyers, Woods 2007, at 20.

20. See note 14, Kantymir, McLeod 2014, at 16.

21. See note 15, Card 2007 and Card 2011.

22. This line of criticism of Card is developed further in Marsh J. Conscientious refusals and reason-giving. Bioethics 2014;28(6):313–9. For a response and elaboration of the reason requirement, see Card R. Reasonability and conscientious objection in medicine: A reply to Marsh and an elaboration of the reason-giving requirement Bioethics 2014;28(6):320–6.

23. Card defends his proposal against similar objections. See Card, R. In defence of medical tribunals and the reasonability standard for conscientious objection in medicine. Journal of Medical Ethics 2016;42:73–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24. The issue of even-handedness looms large in historians’ discussions of military tribunals. In the United Kingdom, the tribunals set up during the First World War were generally regarded as hostile to conscientious objectors. However, there were exceptions. According to McDermott, even the No Conscription Fellowship, an organization which, as its name suggests, opposed conscription, acknowledged that some tribunals attempted to adjudicate cases of conscience fairly. See McDermott J. Conscience and the military service tribunals during the First World War: Experiences in Northamptonshire War in History 2010;17:74. Harries-Jenkins suggests that most First World War tribunals were composed solely of members who were unsympathetic to conscientious objects, but that Second World War tribunals were more evenly balanced and exercised a “positive, if less Draconian jurisdiction.” See Harries-Jenkins G. Britain: From individual conscience to social movement. In: Moskos CC, Chambers JW II, eds. The New Conscientious Objection: From Sacred to Secular Resistance. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1993 69.

25. See note 14, Kantymir, McLeod 2014.

26. Kantymir and Mcleod argue that if conscientious objectors opt for the latter course of action, they should be required to do slightly more than meet Meyers and Woods’ genuineness criterion. They should also be required to demonstrate that “patients will still get care the care they need in a respectful and timely fashion, any empirical beliefs on which the objection rests are not baseless, and the moral or religious beliefs on which it rests are not discriminatory” (See note 14, Kantymir, McLeod 2014, at 21). Discussion of whether or not these additional requirements are warranted is beyond the scope of this article.

27. Sorabji, R. Moral Conscience through the Ages. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014:12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28. See note 27, Sorabji 2014, at 169–75.

29. Lyons, W. Conscience – An essay in moral psychology. Philosophy 2009;84(4):478–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

30. John, Paul II. Evangelium Vitae. Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana; 1995:I 23.Google Scholar

31. Thagard, P, Finn, T. Conscience: What is Moral Intuition? In: Bagnoli, C, ed. Morality and the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015:150–69.Google Scholar

32. Haidt, J. The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 2001;108:814–34;CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed Haidt, J. The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion. New York: Pantheon; 2012.Google Scholar Haidt does not equate the dictates of moral intuition with conscience. He does not discuss conscience.

33. The cited text is from the abstract for Thagard, Finn 2015 (see note 31).

34. See note 31, Thagard, Finn 2015, at 150.

35. See note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996; see also note 17, Meyers, Woods 2007.

36. See note 31, Thagard, Finn 2015.

37. See note 32 Haidt 2012; see also Greene, J. Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason and the Gap between Us and Them. New York: Penguin; 2014.Google Scholar

38. It is possible that there are some people who are psychologically unusual and who do not experience the powerful emotions that are usually associated with moral intuition. This may be the case for some severely autistic people. If such psychological unusualness can be demonstrated, then decisionmakers should be willing to make exceptions.

39. See note 15, Card 2007 and Card 2011; see also note 8, Meyers, Woods 1996 and note 17 Meyers, Woods, 2007.

40. See note 14, Kantymir, McLeod 2014.

41. Sulmasy D. What is conscience and why is respect for it so important? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 2008;29:137.

42. See note 32,Haidt 2001 and Haidt 2012.

43. See note 41, Sulmasy 2008.

44. See note 27, Sorabji 2014, at 170.

45. See, for example, Audi R. The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2004; and Huemer M. Ethical Intuitionism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan; 2005.

46. See note 41, Sulmasy 2008. Sulmasy appears to accept that epistemic modesty is important. He discusses the topic under the broader heading of tolerance, and he is not wrong to do so. There is a tradition, going back to Pierre Bayle (see Bayle P [Tannenbaum AG, ed. and trans.] Philosophical Commentary. New York: Lang, 1685 [1987]) of grounding the value of tolerance of differences of opinion, especially differences of religious opinion, on the virtue of epistemic modesty.

47. Twain, M. The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn. London: Penguin Classics; 1884 [2012].CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48. See note 32, Haidt 2001 and Haidt 2012.