Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T15:24:00.240Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Christianity and the Problem of Free Will

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 May 2023

Leigh Vicens
Affiliation:
Augustana University, South Dakota

Summary

Central to the teachings of Christianity is a puzzle: on the one hand, sin seems something that humans do not do freely and so cannot be not responsible for, since it is unavoidable; on the other hand, sin seems something that we must be responsible for and so do freely, since we are enjoined to repent of it, and since it makes us liable to divine condemnation and forgiveness. After laying out the puzzle in more depth, this Element considers three possible responses—libertarian, soft determinist, and free-will skeptic—and weighs the costs and benefits of each.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009270427
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 08 June 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, Marilyn McCord (1993). The Problem of Hell: A Problem of Evil for Christians. In Stump, Eleonore, ed., Reasoned Faith: Essays in Philosophical Theology in Honor of Norman Kretzmann. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 301327.Google Scholar
Adams, Marilyn McCord (1999). Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Adams, Robert Merrihew (1977). Middle Knowledge and the Problem of Evil. American Philosophical Quarterly 14, 109117.Google Scholar
Adams, Robert Merrihew (1999). Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Mark (2021). On Responsibility and Original Sin: A Molinist Suggestion. Faith and Philosophy 38(1), 525.Google Scholar
Ayer, A. J. (1954). Freedom and Necessity. In Philosophical Essays, New York: St. Martin’s Press: 320; reprinted in Watson (ed.), 1982, 1523.Google Scholar
Baker, Lynne Rudder (2003). Why Christians Should Not Be Libertarians: An Augustinian Challenge. Faith and Philosophy 20(4), 460478.Google Scholar
Burrell, David (2008). Creator/Creatures Relation: “The Distinction’ v. ‘Onto-theology’.” Faith and Philosophy, 25(2), 177189.Google Scholar
Byerly, T. Ryan (2017). Free Will Theodicies for Theological Determinists. Sophia, 56(2), 289310.Google Scholar
Byrne, Peter (2008). Helm’s God and the Authorship of Sin. In Stone, Martin W. F., ed., Reason, Faith and History: Philosophical Essays for Paul Helm. Aldershot: Ashgate, 193–203.Google Scholar
Capes, Justin (2022). Hard Theological Determinism and Divine Forgiveness are Incompatible. In Furlong, Peter and Vicens, Leigh, eds., Theological Determinism: New Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 165183.Google Scholar
Caruso, Gregg D. (2012). Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Couenhoven, Jesse (2007). Augustine’s Rejection of the Free-Will Defense: An Overview of the Late Augustine’s Theodicy. Religious Studies 43(3), 279298.Google Scholar
Cuneo, Terence (2016). Ritualized Faith: Essays on the Philosophy of Liturgy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, Oliver (2009). Original Sin and Atonement. In Flint, Thomas and Rea, Michael, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 430451.Google Scholar
Crisp, Oliver (2015). On Original Sin. International Journal of Systematic Theology 17(3), 252266.Google Scholar
Crisp, Oliver (2020). A Moderate Reformed View. In Stump, J. B. and Meister, Chad, eds., Original Sin and the Fall: Five Views. Intervarsity Press.Google Scholar
Demetriou, Kristen (2010). The Soft-Line Solution to Pereboom’s Four-Case Argument. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88, 595617.Google Scholar
Ekstrom, Laura (2000). Free Will: A Philosophical Study. Westview Press.Google Scholar
Ekstrom, Laura (2021). God, Suffering, and the Value of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finch, Alicia (2022). An Argument for Theological Incompatibilism. In Furlong, Peter and Vicens, Leigh, eds., Theological Determinism: New Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 133149.Google Scholar
Fischer, John Martin (1994). The Metaphysics of Free Will: An Essay on Control. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fischer, John Martin (2006). My Way: Essays on Moral Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, John Martin and Ravizza, Mark (1998). Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Flint, Thomas (1998). Divine Providence: The Molinist Account. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (1969). Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility. Journal of Philosophy 66, 829839.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry (1971). Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. Journal of Philosophy 68, 520.Google Scholar
Franks, W. Paul (2012). Original Sin and Broad Free-Will Defense. Philosophia Christi 14(2), 353371.Google Scholar
Freddoso, Alfred (1988). Introduction. In Freddoso, Alfred J., ed., On Divine Foreknowledge: Part IV of the Concordia. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 181.Google Scholar
Furlong, Peter (2019). The Challenges of Divine Determinism: A Philosophical Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Garrard, Eve and McNaughton, David (2010). Forgiveness. Durham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Grant, W. Matthews (2009). Aquinas on How God Causes the Act of Sin without Causing Sin Itself. The Thomist 73, 455496.Google Scholar
Hasker, William (1989). God, Time, and Knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Helm, Paul (1993). The Providence of God. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.Google Scholar
Helm, Paul (2010). God, Compatibilism, and the Authorship of Sin. Religious Studies: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 46(1), 115124.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, Pamela (2001). Articulating an Uncompromising Forgiveness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62, 529555.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, Pamela (2022). Review of Derk Pereboom’s Wrongdoing and the Moral Emotions. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/wrongdoing-and-the-moral-emotions/#_ednref10.Google Scholar
Kane, Robert (2005). A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, Neil (2011). Hard Luck: How Luck Undermines Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Louth, Andrew (2013). Introducing Eastern Orthodox Theology. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.Google Scholar
Madueme, Hans (2021). The Theological Problem with Evolution. Zygon, 56(2), 481499.Google Scholar
Marshall, Christopher (2001). Beyond Retribution: A New Testament Vision for Justice, Crime, and Punishment. Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
McBrayer, Justin (2010). Skeptical Theism. Philosophy Compass 5(7), 611623.Google Scholar
McCall, Thomas (2019). Against God and Nature: The Doctrine of Sin. Wheaton, IL: Crossway.Google Scholar
McCann, Hugh (1995). Divine Sovereignty and the Freedom of the Will. Faith and Philosophy 12(4), 582598.Google Scholar
McCann, Hugh (2005). The Author of Sin? Faith and Philosophy 22(2), 144159.Google Scholar
McCann, Hugh (2009). God, Sin, and Rogers on Anselm: A Reply. Faith and Philosophy 26(4), 420431.Google Scholar
McCann, Hugh and Johnson, Daniel (2017). Divine Providence. In Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman, eds., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/providence-divine/.Google Scholar
McKenna, Michael (2008). A Hard-line Reply to Pereboom’s Four-Case Manipulation Argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77(1), 142159.Google Scholar
Mele, Alfred (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moo, Douglas (2013). Sin in Paul. In Morgan, Christopher and Peterson, Robert, eds., Fallen: A Theology of Sin. Wheaton, IL: Crossway, 107130.Google Scholar
Morgan, Christopher (2013). Sin in the Biblical Story. In Morgan, Christopher and Peterson, Robert, eds., Fallen: A Theology of Sin. Wheaton, IL: Crossway, 131162.Google Scholar
Nahmias, Eddy, and Murray, Dylan (2010). Experimental Philosophy on Free Will: An Error Theory for Incompatibilist Intuitions. In Aguilar, Jesus, Buckareff, Andrei, and Frankish, Keith, eds., New Waves in Philosophy of Action. London: Palgrave-Macmillan, 189215.Google Scholar
O’Connor, Timothy (1995). Agent Causation. Reprinted in Watson, Gary, ed., Free Will: Second Edition (2003). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 257284.Google Scholar
O’Connor, Timothy (2016). Against Theological Determinism. In Timpe, Kevin and Speak, Daniel, eds., Free Will and Theism: Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 132141.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2001). Living without Free Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2014). Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2016). Libertarianism and Theological Determinism. In Timpe, Kevin and Speak, Daniel, eds., Free Will and Theism: Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 112129.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2017). Responsibility, Regret, and Protest. In Shoemaker, David, ed., Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility, Vol. 4, 121140. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (2021). Wrongdoing and the Moral Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (1974). The Nature of Necessity. New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Cornelius (1995). Not the Way It’s Supposed to Be: A Breviary of Sin. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Pruss, Alexander (2016). The First Sin: A Dilemma for Christian Determinists. In Alexander, David E. and Johnson, Daniel M., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 187199.Google Scholar
Quinn, Philip (2010). Sin and Original Sin. In Taliaferro, Charles, Draper, Paul, and Quinn, Philip, eds., A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, 2nd ed., Blackwell, 614621. West Sussex.Google Scholar
Rea, Michael (2007). The Metaphysics of Original Sin. In Zimmerman, Dean, ed., Persons: Human and Divine. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 319356.Google Scholar
Rhoda, Alan (2010). Gratuitous Evil and Divine Providence. Religious Studies, 46(3), 281302.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherin (2002). The Abolition of Sin: A Response to Adams in the Augustinian Tradition. Faith and Philosophy 19(1), 6984.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherin (2007). God is Not the Author of Sin: An Anselmian Response to McCann. Faith and Philosophy 24(3), 300310.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherin A. (2011). Anselm against McCann on God and Sin: Further Discussion. Faith and Philosophy 28(4), 397415.Google Scholar
Searle, John (1984). Minds, Brains, and Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Strabbing, Jada (2017). Divine Forgiveness and Reconciliation. Faith and Philosophy 34(3), 272297.Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. (1963). Freedom and Resentment. Reprinted in Watson, Gary. ed., Free Will, 2nd ed. (2003). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter (1994). The Impossibility of Moral Responsibility. Philosophical Studies 75(1–2), 524.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (1985). The Problem of Evil. Faith and Philosophy 2(4), 392423.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (1988). Sanctification, Hardening of the Heart, and Frankfurt’s Concept of Free Will. The Journal of Philosophy 85(8), 395420.Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (2008). The Problem of Evil and the Desires of the Heart. In Rea, Michael and Pojman, Louis, eds., Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology. Cengage, 338–350.Google Scholar
Swenson, Philip (2021). Equal Moral Opportunity: A Solution to the Problem of Moral Luck. Australian Journal of Philosophy100(2), 386–404.Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1989). Responsibility and Atonement. New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Talbott, Thomas (1999). The Inescapable Love of God. Universal Publishers.Google Scholar
Talbott, Thomas (2008). Why Christians Should not be Determinists: Reflections on the Origin of Human Sin. Faith and Philosophy 25(3), 300316.Google Scholar
Tanner, Kathryn. (1994). Human Freedom, Human Sin, and God the Creator. In Tracy, T., ed., The God Who Acts: Philosophical and Theological Explorations. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 111135.Google Scholar
Timpe, Kevin (2007). Source Incompatibilism and Its Alternatives. American Philosophical Quarterly 44(2), 143155.Google Scholar
Timpe, Kevin (2021). Sin in Christian Thought. In Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/sin-christian/.Google Scholar
Todd, Patrick (2012). Manipulation and Moral Standing. Philosophers’ Imprint 12(7), 118.Google Scholar
Tognazzini, Neil (2011). Understanding Source Incompatibilism. The Modern Schoolman 88(1–2), 7388.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, Peter (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Peter, Van Inwagen (2008). How to Think about the Problem of Free Will. The Journal of Ethics 12, 327341.Google Scholar
Leigh, Vicens (2012a). Divine Determinism: A Critical Consideration. PhD Dissertation, University of Wisconsin-Madison.https://depot.library.wisc.edu/repository/fedora/1711.dl:YABHRJWC6G4NO8I/datastreams/REF/contentGoogle Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (2012b). Divine Determinism, Human Freedom, and the Consequence Argument. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71, 145155.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (2014). Theological Determinism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/theo-det/.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (2018). Sin and Implicit Bias. Journal of Analytic Theology 6, 100111.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (2022a). Free Will Skeptics Can Have their Basic Desert and Eat It Too. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 112. www.cambridge.org/core/journals/journal-of-the-american-philosophical-association/article/abs/free-will-skeptics-can-have-their-basic-desert-and-eat-it-too/DF94843190B570B6119537F0C64FA587.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (2022b). Human Freedom and the Inevitability of Sin. In Furlong, Peter and Vicens, Leigh, eds., Theological Determinism: New Perspectives150–164. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (2022c). Sin and the Faces of Responsibility. In Knight, John Allan and Markham, Ian, eds., The Craft of Innovative Theology: Argument & Practice. Wiley Blackwell, 99113 Hoboken, NJ.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh (forthcoming). Can the Unfree Person Have a Deep Self? In Visala, Aku and Vainio, Olli-Pekka, eds., Theological Perspectives on Free Will: Compatibility, Christology, Community. Routledge.Google Scholar
Vicens, Leigh and Kittle, Simon (2019). God and Human Freedom. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Visala, Aku (2021). How the Cognitive Sciences Might Contribute to the Theological Debate about Free Will. Modern Theology 37(2), 362381.Google Scholar
Visala, Aku and Vainio, Olli-Pekka (2020). Erasmus versus Luther: A Contemporary Analysis of the Debate on Free Will. Neue Zeitschrift für systematische Theologie und Religionsphilosophie 62(3), 311335.Google Scholar
Warmke, Brandon, Nelkin, Dana Kay, and McKenna, Michael (2021). Forgiveness and its Moral Dimensions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, Gary (1975). Free Agency. Journal of Philosophy 72(8), 205220.Google Scholar
White, Heath (2016). Theological Determinism and the “Authoring of Sin” Objection. In Alexander, David and Johnson, Daniel, eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 7895.Google Scholar
Witherington III, Ben (2005). The Problem with Evangelical Theology: Testing the Exegetical Foundations of Calvinism, Dispensationalism, and Wesleyanism. Waco, TX: Baylor University Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan (1990). Freedom within Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yandell, Keith (1999). Philosophy of Religion: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Christianity and the Problem of Free Will
  • Leigh Vicens, Augustana University, South Dakota
  • Online ISBN: 9781009270427
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Christianity and the Problem of Free Will
  • Leigh Vicens, Augustana University, South Dakota
  • Online ISBN: 9781009270427
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Christianity and the Problem of Free Will
  • Leigh Vicens, Augustana University, South Dakota
  • Online ISBN: 9781009270427
Available formats
×