We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected]
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Classic international law holds that each State can choose the relationship between its domestic law and international law. Two – constitutional – theories thereby exist: monism and dualism. Monist States make international law part of their domestic legal order. International law will here directly apply as if it were domestic law. By contrast, dualist States consider international law separate from domestic law. International law is viewed as the law between States; national law is the law within a State. While international treaties are thus binding ‘on’ States, they cannot be binding ‘in’ States. International law needs to be ‘transposed’ or ‘incorporated’ into domestic law and will thus only have indirect effects through the medium of national law. The dualist theory is therefore based on a basic division of labour: international institutions apply international law, while national institutions apply national law.
Did the European Union leave the choice between monism and dualism to its Member States? For dualist States, all European law would need to be ‘incorporated’ into national law before it could have domestic effects. Here, there is no direct applicability of European law, as all European norms are mediated through national law and individuals will consequently never come into direct contact with European law. Where a Member State violates European law, this breach can only be established and remedied at the European level. The European Treaties indeed contained such an ‘international’ remedial machinery against recalcitrant Member States in the form of enforcement actions before the Court of Justice. Another Member State or the Commission – but not individuals – could here bring an action to enforce their rights.
Did this not signal that the European Treaties were international treaties that tolerated the dualist approach? Not necessarily, for the Treaties also contained strong signals against the ‘ordinary’ international law reading of the European legal order. Not only was the Union entitled to adopt legal acts that were to be ‘directly applicable in all Member States’, but from the very beginning, the Treaties also contained a judicial mechanism that envisaged the direct application of European law by the national courts. But even if a monist view had not been intended by the founding Member States, the European Court discarded any possible dualist readings of Union law in the most important case of European law: Van Gend en Loos.
The idea of European unification is as old as the European idea of the sovereign State. Yet the spectacular rise of the latter overshadowed the idea of European union for centuries. Within the twentieth century, two ruinous world wars and the social forces of globalisation have increasingly discredited the idea of the sovereign State. The decline of the monadic State found expression in the spread of inter-state cooperation. And the rise of international cooperation caused a fundamental transformation in the substance and structure of international law. The changed reality of international relations necessitated a change in the theory of international law.
The various efforts at European cooperation after the Second World War formed part of this general transition from an international law of coexistence to an international law of cooperation. ‘Europe was beginning to get organised.’ This development began with three international organisations. First: the Organisation for European Economic Cooperation (1948), which had been created after the Second World War by 16 European States to administer the international aid offered by the United States for European reconstruction. Secondly, the Western European Union (1948, 1954) that established a security alliance to prevent another war in Europe. Thirdly, the Council of Europe (1949), which had inter alia been founded to protect human rights and fundamental freedoms in Europe. None of these grand international organisations was to lead to the European Union. The birth of the latter was to take place in a much humbler sector.
The 1951 Treaty of Paris set up the European Coal and Steel Community (ECSC). Its original members were six European States: Belgium, France, Germany, Italy, Luxembourg and the Netherlands. The Community had been created to integrate one industrial sector; and the very concept of integration indicated the wish of the contracting States ‘to break with the ordinary forms of international treaties and organisations’.
The Treaty of Paris led to the 1957 Treaties of Rome. The latter created two additional Communities: the European Atomic Energy Community and the European (Economic) Community. The ‘three Communities’ were partly ‘merged’ in 1967, but continued to exist in relative independence. A major organisational leap was taken in 1993, when the Maastricht Treaty integrated the three Communities into the European Union. But for a decade, the Treaty on European Union was under constant constitutional construction.
Since European law is directly applicable in the Member States, it must be recognised alongside national law by national authorities. And since European law can have direct effect, it might come into conflict with national law in a specific situation. And where two legislative wills come into conflict, each legal order must determine when conflicts arise and how these conflicts are to be resolved.
For the Union legal order, these two dimensions have indeed been developed for the relationship between European and national law. In Europe's constitutionalism they have been described as, respectively, the principle of pre-emption and the principle of supremacy: ‘The problem of preemption consists in determining whether there exists a conflict between a national measure and a rule of [European] law. The problem of [supremacy] concerns the manner in which such a conflict, if it is found to exist, will be resolved.’ Pre-emption and supremacy thus represent ‘two sides of the same coin’. They are like Siamese twins: different though inseparable. There is no supremacy without pre-emption.
This chapter begins with an analysis of the supremacy doctrine. How supreme is European law? Will European law prevail over all national law? And what is the effect of the supremacy principle on national law? We shall see that there are two perspectives on the supremacy question. According to the European perspective, all Union law prevails over all national law. This ‘absolute’ view is not shared by the Member States. Indeed, according to the national perspective, the supremacy of European law is relative: some national law is considered to be beyond the supremacy of European law.
A third section then moves to the doctrine of pre-emption. This tells us to what extent European law ‘displaces’ national law; or, to put it the other way around: how much legislative space a European law still leaves to the Member States. The Union legislator is generally free to choose to what extent it wishes to pre-empt national law. However, there are two potential constitutional limits to this freedom. First, the type of instrument used – regulation, directive or international agreement – might limit the pre-emptive effect of Union law. And, secondly: the type of competence on which the Union act is based might determine the capacity of the Union legislator to pre-empt the Member States.
The rise of the modern State system after the seventeenth century was a celebration of political pluralism. Each State was entitled to its own ‘autonomous’ existence.
The rise of the absolute idea of State sovereignty led to an absolute denial of all supranational authority above the State. This way of thinking introduced a distinction that still structures our understanding of the legal world: the distinction between national and international law. The former was the sphere of subordination and compulsory law; while the latter constituted the sphere of coordination and voluntary contract. International law was thus not ‘real’ law – as it could not be enforced. From the perspective of classic international law, a ‘public law’ between sovereigns was thus a contradiction in terms since it required an authority above the States; but if sovereignty was the defining characteristic of the modern State, there could be no such higher authority. All relations between States must be voluntary and, as such, ‘beyond’ any public legal force.
From the very beginning, this traditional idea of State sovereignty blocked a proper understanding of the nature of the European Union. The latter was said to have been ‘established on the most advanced frontiers of the [international] law of peaceful cooperation’; and its principles of solidarity and integration had even taken it ‘to the boundaries of federalism’. But was the Union inside those federal boundaries or outside them? For while the European Union was not a Federal State, had it not assumed ‘statist’ features and combined – like a chemical compound – international and national elements? But how should one conceptualise this ‘middle ground’ between international and national law? In the absence of a federal theory beyond the State, European thought invented a new word – supranationalism – and proudly announced the European Union to be sui generis. The Union was declared to be ‘incomparable’; and the belief that Europe was incomparable ushered in the dark ages of European constitutional theory. Indeed, the sui generis idea is not a theory. It is an anti-theory, for it refuses to search for commonalities; yet, theory must search for what is common among different entities.
How, then, should we view and analyse the nature and structure of the European Union? This chapter presents two answers to this question by looking at two different constitutional traditions.
During its first decade, the single currency was a work in progress in more ways than one. Though the early years were difficult for Germany, France and Italy, which suffered particularly in the global slowdown from 2001 until mid 2003, the euro area as a whole made a promising start as the smaller economies in particular flourished, growing together at double the rate of the three big ones between 1999 and 2003. The ECB established both its authority and the effectiveness of a single monetary policy, passing several tricky tests such as the early slowdown and commodity price shocks. The new central bank could point to a respectable record in its first decade as growth in living standards in the euro area broadly matched that of the US, while inflation remained under control. More remarkably, when the financial crisis rocked western capitalism in 2008, the single-currency club appeared to protect its member states, whereas those outside looked vulnerable. Late that year, Buiter said that there was ‘a non-trivial risk of the UK becoming the next Iceland’ and that the pound's status as a ‘minor-league currency’ was now a ‘costly handicap’ for London's position as a global financial centre. Trichet's description of the euro as a shield in January 2009 (a term he had used before, for example in 2004) was not so obviously then the hostage to fortune that it became. In particular, although the euro itself fell against the dollar during the financial crisis it fared much better than the pound, which collapsed against both the dollar and the euro (at its nadir almost going through parity against the euro) due to fears about Britain's precarious banks.
But it was during the first decade of the single currency that the seeds of the euro crisis were sown, starting with the first and most important of them all, the admission of countries in southern Europe whose economies were ill-suited to the venture. The record for the euro area as a whole might have seemed broadly acceptable, but that overall picture disguised the emergence of economic imbalances both within and between members of the bloc. As a credit boom on the southern and western periphery gained momentum in the middle of the 2000s, these imbalances opened up on a scale matched only by the rapidity with which they emerged.
The idea of European monetary union was a distant dream when the Eagles released their album, ‘Hotel California’, in 1976. But the west-coast band's spaced-out lyrics turned out to be prescient for the euro thirty-five years later as the currency union stumbled into a crisis that threatened to tear it apart. Was the euro area, like the hotel, a place where you could check in but never leave? If that was the nightmare for a country like Greece as its citizens weighed the immediate pain of a ‘Grexit’ against an uncertain future gain as an economy unshackled from the euro, the existential nightmare for the euro area was that a country might indeed leave, and in the process destroy the single currency itself.
That prospect looked most threatening in 2012. Yet three years later, Greece went even further to the edge. The potential economic harm to the rest of the euro area in 2015 appeared to be much more contained than in 2012, although no one could be entirely sure about this in practice. By contrast, the political damage of the clash among euro-zone leaders at their weekend summit in July as Greece desperately sought to remain a member while Germany openly pressed for an enforced exit was profound. The disharmony caused soul-searching about a project that was dividing the peoples of Europe rather than bringing them together.
The history of currency unions cast a sobering shadow. If the European version were to survive, it would be the exception to the rule. Shortly before the financial crisis erupted, Andrew Rose, an economist at the University of California, Berkeley, estimated that sixty-nine countries (or other territorial entities) had left currency unions since the Second World War. In fact, this was an underestimate because Rose's figures did not include the break-ups following the collapse of the Soviet Union and of Yugoslavia. The exits generally occurred as the former imperial powers shed their colonies and newly independent countries adopted a new currency. The departures peaked in the 1960s and 1970s; by the end of the latter decade, sixty-two out of the sixty-nine noted by Rose had taken place.
The protection of human rights is a central task of many modern judiciaries. Judicial review may thereby be limited to the review of the executive; yet in its expansive form, it includes the judicial review of legislative acts. The European Union follows this second tradition. Fundamental rights thus set substantive – judicial – limits to all governmental powers and processes within the Union. They indeed constitute one of the most popular grounds of review in actions challenging the validity of European Union law.
What are the sources of human rights in the Union legal order? Despite the absence of a ‘bill of rights’ in the original Treaties, three sources for EU fundamental rights were subsequently developed. The European Court first began distilling fundamental rights from the constitutional traditions of the Member States. This unwritten bill of rights was inspired and informed by a second bill of rights: the European Convention on Human Rights. This external bill of rights was, decades later, matched by a written bill of rights specifically drafted for the European Union: the Charter of Fundamental Rights.
These three sources of EU fundamental rights are now expressly referred to – in reverse order – in Article 6 of the Treaty on European Union. The provision reads:
1. The Union recognises the rights, freedoms and principles set out in the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union of 7 December 2000, as adopted at Strasbourg, on 12 December 2007, which shall have the same legal value as the Treaties …
2. The Union shall accede to the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms. Such accession shall not affect the Union's competences as defined in the Treaties.
3. Fundamental rights, as guaranteed by the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms and as they result from the constitutional traditions common to the Member States, shall constitute general principles of the Union's law.
This chapter investigates each of the Union's three bills of rights and the constitutional principles that govern them. Section 1 starts with the discovery of an ‘unwritten’ bill of rights in the form of general principles of European law. Section 2 analyses the Union's own ‘written’ bill of rights: the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights.
National courts are the principal judicial enforcers of European law. ‘Ever since Van Gend en Loos the Court has maintained that it is the task of the national courts to protect the rights of individuals under [Union] law and to give full effect to [Union] law provisions.’ Indeed, whenever European law is directly effective, national courts must apply it; and wherever a Union norm comes into conflict with national law, each national court must disapply the latter. The Union legal order thereby insists that nothing within the national judicial system must prevent national courts from exercising their functions as ‘guardians’ of the European judicial order. In Simmenthal, the Court thus held that each national court must be able to disapply national law – even where the national judicial system traditionally reserves that power to a central constitutional court:
[E]very national court must, in a case within its jurisdiction, apply [Union] law in its entirety and protect rights which the latter confers on individuals and must accordingly set aside any provision of national law which may conflict with it, whether prior or subsequent to the [Union] rule. Accordingly any provision of a national legal system and any legislative, administrative or judicial practice which might impair the effectiveness of [European] law by withholding from the national court having jurisdiction to apply such law the power to do everything necessary at the moment of its application to set aside national legislative provisions which might prevent [Union] rules from having full force and effect are incompatible with those requirements which are the very essence of [Union] law.
Functionally, the direct effect (and supremacy) of European law transform every single national court into a ‘European’ court. This decentralised system differs from the judicial system in the United States in which the application of federal law is principally left to ‘federal’ courts. Federal courts here apply federal law, while state courts apply state law. The European system, by contrast, is based on a philosophy of cooperative federalism: all national courts are entitled and obliged to apply European law to disputes before them. National courts are however not full European courts. For while they must interpret and apply European law, they are not empowered to annul a Union act.
When compared to the legislative and executive branches, the judiciary looks like a poor relation. For the classic civil law tradition reduces courts to ‘the mouth that pronounces the words of the law, mere passive beings that can moderate neither its force nor its rigour’. And even the common law tradition finds that ‘[w]hoever attentively considers the different departments of power must perceive, that in a government in which they are separated from each other, the judiciary, from the nature of its functions, will always be the least dangerous to the political rights of the constitution; because it will be least in a capacity to annoy or injure them’. In the eyes of both traditions, the judiciary is thus ‘the least dangerous branch’. This traditional view originated in the eighteenth century and reduced the judiciary to its adjudicatory function. The sole function of courts is here to decide disputes between private or public parties.
Yet this view was to change dramatically in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Courts not only succeeded in imposing their control over the executive branch. Some States would even allow for the constitutional review of legislation. In Marbury v. Madison, the American Supreme Court thus claimed the power to ‘un-make’ a law adopted by the legislature. It justified its annulment power as follows: ‘all those who have framed written constitutions contemplate them as forming the fundamental and paramount law of the nation, and consequently the theory of every such government must be that an act of the legislature, repugnant of the constitution is void’.
These judicial ‘victories’ over the executive and legislative branch were inspired by the idea that a State should be governed by the ‘rule of law’, that is: a legal order should provide for judicial mechanisms to review the ‘legality’ of all governmental acts. And this idea would, in some legal orders, include the sanctioning power of the judiciary to order a State to make good damage caused by a public ‘wrong’.
A modern definition of the judicial function will therefore need to include three core powers, which – in descending order – are: the power to annul legislative or executive acts, the power to remedy public wrongs through governmental liability, and the power to adjudicate legal disputes between parties.
Throughout the crisis there was a Faustian battle for the soul of the ECB. That struggle was most earnest in Germany, coming close to parody when Weidmann invoked Goethe's drama as a warning against succumbing to the temptation of unbridled money creation. Should the ECB stay faithful to its first incarnation, the circumscribed conception of a doughtily independent central bank that was essentially the Bundesbank writ large on the European stage? Or did it have to shed that skin and assume a more ambitious and expansive role akin to that of the Fed or the Bank of England, even though unlike such traditional institutions embedded in their sovereign states it was uniquely a supranational monetary authority? As the euro crisis itself metamorphosed from a trial in the markets to a broader economic failure of stalling growth and protracted low inflation, the ECB was called upon to reinvent itself again, by adopting a programme of quantitative easing that would involve large-scale purchases of sovereign bonds, a policy shift as fraught for a central bank lacking a single state as the decisions it took in the heat of the crisis between 2010 and 2012.
A change of leadership in late 2011 was almost certainly pivotal in determining the outcome of the ECB's identity crisis. Under Trichet, who had taken charge in November 2003, the central bank repeatedly crossed lines it had drawn in the sands, but its French leader sought to build and to represent a consensus on the council. Since that was generally lacking during the euro crisis it was hard to widen the ECB's remit beyond the bare minimum needed to sustain the currency union. The central bank's approach in combating the euro crisis in 2010 and most of 2011 was accordingly reactive and hesitant rather than proactive and decisive.
When he was campaigning for the top job, Draghi paid homage to Germany as an economic role model for pushing through structural reforms to improve its competitiveness; and he went out of his way to praise the Bundesbank at his first press conference, in November 2011, expressing ‘great admiration’ for the institution and its tradition. His wooing of the German public earlier that year paid off when Bild backed him.
‘The life of the law has not been logic; it has been experience.’ But if it is the fate of the common law to ‘stumbl[e] into wisdom’, this should be less true of the civil law. For it is the task of legal codes to order experiences into a logical system of norms. Constitutional law is – more often than not – codified law. Most constitutional orders are based on a written constitution; and this written constitution is designed to establish a system of rules that provide the ‘grammar of politics’. Learning constitutional law is thus like learning a language. One cannot only learn the words expressing different experiences. One also needs to study the grammatical system that binds these words together. Yet constitutional law is of course not all about logical rules. As in a language, there exist exceptions and next to the exceptions exist absurdities! These are often the result of historical experiences; and constitutional law will therefore always be about logic and experience. It is the place where political theory meets historical reality.
The object of constitutional law is the ‘constitution’. But what is a ‘constitution’? From a purely descriptive point of view, constitutions simply reflect the institutions and powers of government. From a normative perspective, on the other hand, constitutions are to ‘order’ societies according to a particular political philosophy. Normative constitutions thus do not merely reflect the existing ‘government’ but prescribe its composition and powers. Yet in order to be able to set normative limits to a government, the constitution must be above the government. The normative definition of constitution therefore defines it as the highest law within a society. The constitution has an elevated position above the ordinary law governing a society. (Its higher status is often achieved by prohibiting constitutional changes through simple legislation. Constitutions can here only be amended by ‘constitutional’ amendment.) Formally, then, a constitution is best defined as the collection of those norms that ‘constitute’ a society's highest laws. Within the last two hundred years, this formal definition has however competed with a material understanding of what a constitution ought to be. This second definition links the concept of constitution to particular political principles. Following the ‘liberal’ principle, a constitution should thus establish the rule of law and a separation of powers.