Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T04:59:26.833Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Wellbeing as the Goal for Society

from Part I - The Case for Wellbeing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 May 2023

Richard Layard
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
Jan-Emmanuel De Neve
Affiliation:
University of Oxford

Summary

The wellbeing approach offers a clear solution to the basic questions in political philosophy and moral philosophy. Crucially, it provides a single overarching goal. Coherent decisions require an overarching goal, for if you have multiple goals, they may point in different directions. Aristotle recognised this but modern ’utilitarianism’ dates back to Jeremy Bentham. According to the Benthamite approach, decisions should aim to maximise the discounted sum of future wellbeing.

This is already the approach of many health policy-makers. However others believe that it is especially important to raise the wellbeing of those whose wellbeing is low. This ’prioritarian’ approach suggests looking for new policies especially in those areas which account for the most misery (on which evidence exists), and giving especial weight to the reduction of misery.

There have been many criticisms of the wellbeing approach, which the chapter discusses and tries to answer – consequentialism and rights, the experience machine, adaptation, and the nanny state. Readers who accept those criticisms are challenged to come up with an alternative philosophy that is operational.

Type
Chapter
Information
Wellbeing
Science and Policy
, pp. 38 - 52
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

Create all the happiness you are able to create: remove all the misery you are able to remove.

Jeremy Bentham

Some History

How would we recognise a good society? The idea that it is defined by the wellbeing of the citizens goes back at least to the ancient Greeks.Footnote 1 In this chapter, we shall see how this idea developed from then until now. We shall then provide a rigorous modern formulation of the idea. And finally, we shall discuss some of the main objections that people have made to it.

Greece and Rome

We can begin with the great Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 bc). He, more than anyone, is responsible for the idea that there must be some ultimate end that we should aim at – with other things like wealth, health and good relationships being good because of how they contribute to that end. That is the hierarchical idea we already displayed in Figure I.1. The ultimate end he called ‘eudaimonia’, which he envisaged as a balanced, rational and virtuous state of being. He especially emphasised virtue, which he considered essential if your experience of life is to be truly fulfilling. He did not define virtue exactly as this book does, but he had a realistic modern empiricist view on how it should be acquired – by constant repetition and habit-formation.

Greek philosophers who came after Aristotle emphasised different aspects of his message. Epicurus (341–270 bc) emphasised the importance of a simple life, focused on things you really enjoy, like friendship and family life. Zeno the Stoic (333–264 bc) emphasised civic virtue and the ability to calm your mind whatever adversity befell you. The ideas of these two thinkers spread widely through the Roman world. Eventually, it was Stoicism that became the philosophy of much of the Roman middle class – and of the emperor Marcus Aurelius (ad 121–180), who wrote much about the secrets of happiness. Similar ideas had already been developed in China by Confucius and in India by the Buddha.

However, in the centuries that followed, Christianity brought in a quite different perspective. Happiness was still to be sought but only in the afterlife. In this world, the aim was virtue alone and this would bring happiness after death.Footnote 2

The eighteenth-century Enlightenment

It was only in the late seventeenth century that philosophers dared to re-establish happiness on earth as the goal of life. The great English philosopher John Locke (1632–1704) took it as axiomatic that people wanted to feel good and that to acquire that feeling was their principal motivation. But it was a Scotsman, Francis Hutcheson (1694–1746), who took the first huge step towards establishing happiness as the goal for society, rather than just for the individual. He taught that the moral thing to do was whatever produced ‘the greatest happiness for the greatest number’Footnote 3 – or, more precisely, what produced the greatest total happiness. And he argued that this is what any ‘impartial spectator’ would think.

From the wellbeing point of view, this idea was probably the greatest idea of modern times. It has three key implications.

  1. (1) For judgements: If we want to compare two different situations and to say which is better, we should use the happiness of the people as the test. This would be so, for example, if we were asking which country is doing better, or whether the present is better than the past or which is the best way to spend public money.

  2. (2) For individual action: If we ask, ‘What is the ethical thing to do?’, the answer is, ‘Whatever produces the greatest overall happiness’.

  3. (3) For government policy: When we ask, ‘What should the government be trying to achieve?’, the answer is, ‘The greatest possible happiness for the people’.

As the eighteenth century progressed, these ideas took a firm hold among the educated classes in the English-speaking world, including in North America.Footnote 4 Thomas Jefferson, who drafted the US constitution, would write, ‘The life and happiness of the people is the first and only object of good government.’ But the writer who immortalised these ideas was the Englishman Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) in The Principle of Morals and Legislation. In this book, Bentham argued that all actions should be judged by their consequences – by their impact on the happiness of everyone. In other words, actions should be judged by their ‘utility’. Thus Bentham’s concept of ethics, which is so humane, became known as ‘utilitarianism’, which makes it sound quite the opposite. (Similarly economics, which was founded by Adam Smith (1723–1790) to study the economic conditions for the greatest happiness, chose the word ‘utility’ to describe individual wellbeing rather than the word ‘happiness’).

During the nineteenth century, the principle of the greatest happiness inspired many major social reforms. It was forcefully presented by John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) in his book Utilitarianism and in his essay ‘The Subjection of Women’. However, he also proposed that some pleasures are intrinsically better than others (for example, poetry was better than the game of pushpin). This was in our view a confusion of means with ends. You will certainly be happier in general if you have a clear purpose in life (as we show clearly in Chapter 4). And you will make others happier if you are virtuous. But the ultimate test of a society is how happy people are (irrespective of how they became so).

During the nineteenth century, economists continued to focus on happiness as the ultimate test of economic arrangements, and the economist Edgeworth (1845–1926) foreshadowed the modern science of wellbeing when he talked about the need for a ‘hedonimeter’ – a technique to measure happiness in a cardinal fashion. In the nineteenth century, most economists believed that an extra dollar gives more extra happiness to a poor person than to someone who is better off. Similarly, in psychology, the great psychologist William James was primarily concerned with life as people experienced it from the inside.

Behaviourism

But then in the twentieth century, psychology turned away from the study of wellbeing – to behaviourism. Scholars like Ivan Pavlov and John B. Watson argued that we could not know what occurred inside people or how they felt. One could only study how they behaved and how this was affected by external stimuli. This doctrine soon impacted on economics, and in 1932, the economist Lionel Robbins asserted that we could not compare the happiness of one person with another.Footnote 5 Even for the same person, he argued, we could only rank different situations, A, B and C, in order; we could not say whether going from A to B gave more (or less) extra happiness than going from B to C.

The consequences for economics were serious. It became impossible to evaluate any issue involving income distribution. We could not say whether it was better if two people had $50,000 dollars each or if one had $20,000 and the other had $80,000. All that could be claimed was that a change was good if some people gained and no one lost (a so-called Pareto improvement). When, as generally happens, a change involves some gainers and some losers, economists, according to Robbins, could say nothing. But in fact, this did not stop them from pronouncing in such cases, and John Hicks and Nicholas Kaldor quickly provided what they considered a justification. They argued that, even if some people lose, a change is good if the gainers could have compensated the losers – even if they actually didn’t.Footnote 6 This was the so-called Hicks–Kaldor criterion for a welfare improvement.

This criterion also justified a second dubious practice: the use of national income (or gross domestic product, GDP) as a measure of national wellbeing. GDP is a measure of the scale of economic activity, the things that happen for which people get paid. In the national income, everybody’s dollars are added up regardless of who has them; and, if the national income increases, that is a Hicks–Kaldor improvement, even if many poor people have become worse off. But GDP was invented for a quite different purpose – by Simon Kuznets – as a way of analysing the business cycle and the fluctuations of unemployment. It was not meant to measure wellbeing. As Kuznets himself said, ‘The welfare of a nation can scarcely be inferred from a measurement of national income.’Footnote 7 There are two obvious reasons for this view:

  • GDP adds up the dollars of rich and poor as if they are of equal value.

  • GDP fails to include any source of wellbeing other than things you can buy. As Robert Kennedy put it, ‘GDP does not allow for the health of our children, the quality of their education, or the joy of their play.’Footnote 8

But despite all this, GDP per head became the totem of national success in the post-WWII period.

In recent years, there has, however, been a massive pushback against the idea that GDP is an adequate measure of national progress. In 1974, the economist Richard Easterlin used psychological surveys to show that wellbeing in the United States had not risen since WWII, despite massive economic growth.Footnote 9 And subsequent research has shown that economic growth is no guarantee of increased wellbeing (see Chapter 13). So it is not surprising that even before the economic slowdown in the West from 2008 onwards, there was increased public demand for a wider goal than economic growth.

Taking feelings seriously again

But key to the demand for a new approach has been our increased ability to measure wellbeing and to understand its causes. The key figure here has been Edward Diener (1946–2021). Beginning in the early 1980s, he showed that wellbeing could be effectively measured and explained.Footnote 10 As time went on, more and more psychologists joined this enterprise, including Daniel Kahneman who in 2002 won the Nobel Prize for Economics. Economists also joined in, using large population surveys to throw light on the effect of different experiences upon individual wellbeing.

At the same time, ordinary citizens have become increasingly aware of their own mental states and interested in how to improve their own feelings. Two forces are at work here. The first is cognitive psychology (embodied in cognitive-behavioural therapy) and the second is mind-training techniques imported from the East. We discuss both at length in Chapter 4.

The Definition of Social Welfare

So it is time to lay out somewhat more formally a view of ethics based on the wellbeing of society as the goal.Footnote 11 The overall objective is called ‘social welfare(S). Social welfare is the concept we use when comparing one situation with another, to find out which is best. Any formula for social welfare must obviously satisfy some basic principles including these:

  • Everybody’s wellbeing is of equal importance. So every person’s wellbeing should be treated in the same way when we compute social welfare.Footnote 12

  • Social welfare must be higher if one person’s wellbeing increases and no one else’s falls.

But we need to be more specific than this. The measure of social welfare that Hutcheson, and then Bentham, proposed was the simple sum of wellbeing (W) across all the members of the population. In other words, if Wi is the wellbeing of the ‘i’th person and ∑ means the sum across all members of the population, then at any point in time social welfare is

Current Social Welfare=S=ΣiWi(1)

This is the classic utilitarian approach. Later in this chapter, we shall consider a more egalitarian or ‘prioritarian’ approach. But the classic utilitarian approach is a good starting point.

Wellbeing over time and WELLBYs

Of course, most decisions affect wellbeing over a period of time. For example, decisions affecting the climate will affect generations yet unborn. So we need a social welfare function that enables us to find the best path of wellbeing over the future and not just in the current period. So how should we value future wellbeing?

An obvious starting point is that the wellbeing of every human being in every year matters equally. However, since there is major uncertainty about the future, we should slightly discount the wellbeing that could be expected in future years – by multiplying wellbeing in t years hence by 1δt where δ is the discount rate per annum. (In Britain, the official value of this ‘pure time preference rate’ is 1.5% per annum).Footnote 13 In proceeding in this way, we are assuming that a person’s suffering in any one year is equally important, whether or not the rest of their life is happy.

On this basis, intertemporal social welfare (S*) becomes simply the discounted sum of all future wellbeing, whoever is experiencing it:

Future Social Welfare=S=ΣiΣt1δtWit(2)

So if we want to decide whether a policy change is desirable, we should evaluate whether the following expression is positive:

ΔS=ΣiΣt1δtΔWit(3)

To make this practical, we have to decide on the length of each period. If we take it as a year, ΔWit would be the change in wellbeing for person i in year t. In other words, it is a change in Wellbeing-Years (or WELLBYs). So when we come to methods of policy evaluation in Chapter 18, the key issue will be how a policy affects the number of (discounted) WELLBYs.

Sustainability and climate change

Thus the wellbeing approach provides a comprehensive framework for considering the future of our society from the smallest choices to the biggest. Of these, the biggest of all is the future of the planet. A central issue here is the wellbeing of future generations.Footnote 14

Wellbeing science favours a low discount rate, so that what happens to future generations is really important when we decide what to do now. The only legitimate reason for discounting future wellbeing is ‘pure time preference’, based on uncertainty about the future. Typical rates of pure time preference are 1.5% a year. By contrast economists mainly analyse the future in terms of levels of real income. They generally assume that real incomes will rise steadily, which will reduce the impact of extra future income on future wellbeing. They therefore discount future income by at least 3.5% a year – making the future appear much less important relative to the present.Footnote 15 So it is not surprising that those who want everything analysed in terms of wellbeing find strong allies among those who want more attention to the future of the planet. For both groups, sustainability is crucial.

Length of life and the birth rate

There is one further issue – the issue of life and death. One way to increase future social welfare (as in equation 2) is to help people live longer. If someone lives longer and has wellbeing greater than zero, that increases social welfare.Footnote 16

But can we also increase future social welfare by increasing the birth rate? If we could, it would be one of the least expensive ways of increasing future social welfare, and we would therefore choose to do it even if it decreased the number of Wellbeing-Years (or WELLBYs) per person born. John Stuart Mill rejected the idea that social welfare depended on the size of the population, and we shall focus instead on the number of WELLBYs per person born.

Today’s medical policy-makers have adopted the same approach. Their aim is to produce the highest possible number of Quality-Adjusted Life Years (suitably discounted) for each person born.Footnote 17 We shall follow this approach. So when we use equation (3) to evaluate a policy change, we do not include in our evaluation any effect of the policy change upon the number of people born.

How egalitarian should we be?

We have thus far adopted the stand of classic utilitarianism – that all that matters is average lifetime wellbeing, regardless of how unequally it is distributed. This means that the following distributions of wellbeing are of equal value:

Situation 1Situation 2
Person A85
Person B25

But today many people are more egalitarian than Hutcheson and Bentham were and believe that it is more important to raise the wellbeing of the least happy people than to raise by an equal amount the wellbeing of those who are already quite happy.Footnote 18 In other words, the social value of i’s wellbeing is not identical to Wi. Instead, it rises with Wi but it rises at a declining rate. So the social value of Wi is a ‘function’ of Wi, f (Wi), which has the property we have just described.Footnote 19 And social welfare is the sum of f (Wi) added up across all members of society. Thus,

Foregalitarians:S=ΣifWif>0f<0(4)

There are thus two alternative concepts of social welfare that we could use to decide whether one situation is better than another. Which of them should we use? In choosing between the Benthamite (or strictly ‘utilitarian’) view and the more egalitarian (or ‘prioritarian’) view, a good approach is the one pioneered after WWII by Jan Harsanyi and John Rawls.Footnote 20 In this approach, we imagine ourselves in an ‘original position’ behind a ‘veil of ignorance’, not knowing which actual human being we are going to be. We then ask ourselves to choose between different situations, not knowing who we will be in each situation.

So how would we evaluate different situations? Egalitarians who use this framework believe that most individuals have a degree of risk-aversion. They would not therefore evaluate a distribution of possible levels of wellbeing entirely according to its average value. They would also look at the spread of the possible outcomes. And they would prefer prospects where the probability of experiencing low wellbeing was low. In other words, for any given average wellbeing in the population, they would prefer a more equal to a less equal distribution of wellbeing.Footnote 21 The simplest way to represent this set of values is by a concept of social welfare of the type we have already described, ΣifWi where the social value of additional W declines as W increases.Footnote 22

If one accepts this argument, the issue is then ‘How fast is the decline?’Footnote 23 The most extreme view is one inspired by the work of the Harvard philosopher John Rawls.Footnote 24 In this view, the decline is so sharp that the only thing that really matters is the wellbeing of the least happy person. So the social welfare equals the wellbeing of the least happy person.

Forfollowers of Rawls:S=MinW1Wn(5)

A less extreme view is that the only thing that really matters is the number of people below some acceptable level of wellbeing.Footnote 25

Choosing a social welfare function is not a scientific matter – it involves normative considerations, even if we try to solve the issue by ‘positive’ thought experiments or by surveying the population. This is why, however much the science of wellbeing improves, there will always be a spread of views on the exact definition of social welfare.

Therefore, the most practical approach in any choice situation is to begin by first examining the difference in ΣiWi and then seeing how far the result would be altered by varying assumptions about the form of fWi.Footnote 26 A further practical step is to begin the search for new policies in those areas of life that account for the greatest amount of misery (on which Chapter 8 provides relevant evidence).

Criticisms

It is time now to face the music. For, despite its powerful approach, a philosophy based on subjective wellbeing has been subject to major criticisms. Here are some of the main criticisms, together with a typical reply from the advocates of wellbeing. It should be pointed out that many of these problems are extremely difficult to handle using any philosophical system, and the real issue is whether there is any other ethical system that is more defensible than that based on wellbeing.

Consequentialism and rights: The fat man

The first criticism is that we only take into account the consequences of actions (even though we do include in that the experiences that occur during the action itself). Critics often use the following example.Footnote 27 You are on a railway bridge. You see a train approaching from one side of the bridge, while down the line are five people on the track who will be killed by the train. However there is a fat man sitting on the bridge. Should you push the fat man to his death in order to save five others?

The calculus says there would be a net gain of four lives from this action (5 minus 1). So is it the right thing to do? Critics argue that the wellbeing approach says Yes, and this shows that the wellbeing approach is inadequate. However, how would millions of people in our society feel about their own lives if such actions became acceptable? Clearly, society has to have rules that make its members flourish. The philosophy of utilitarianism thus has two functions.Footnote 28 First, it helps us to choose the rules we should generally follow, and second, it helps us to decide when we should break the rule (for example, when we should lie to protect a Jew in hiding from the Nazis).

Some of the rules will be moral principles we teach our children, while others will be rights enshrined in law. We will teach our children to be kind because that makes other people feel better. But we also need legislated rights, especially for minorities. If we wish to prevent misery, we have to establish many legal rights. But these are deliberate legislative acts designed to promote social welfare; they are not the recognition of some pre-existing ‘natural rights’.Footnote 29 The only natural right is that each individual’s feelings count equally.

The experience machine

But are good feelings the only things that matter? In 1974, the Harvard philosopher Robert Nozick questioned the primacy of feelings by posing the following hypothetical question: ‘Suppose there was an “experience machine” you could link up to, which would make you feel anything you desire and which was equally available to other people. Would you link up to it?’Footnote 30

Many people say No. They say it matters that the experience is real. But what if the real experience was awful and that we reverse the sequence of the question. So imagine you are having a lovely time in the experience machine and are offered instead the real experience of solitary confinement in a rat-infested cell. Which would you choose?Footnote 31

A more likely possibility is that scientists come up with a drug that makes everybody feel better and has no bad side effects. This issue was raised in a striking form by Aldous Huxley in his book Brave New World. In it he has people taking soma to make themselves feel better. This was meant to appal the readers. But most people throughout history have used alcohol or other substances to improve their mood. The problem has been that all known substances of this kind also bring bad side effects. But it may be hard to object to a substance that improves mood without any bad side effects.

Adaptation

Then there is the issue that our feelings adapt (see Chapter 3). Most people adapt to hardship to a considerable extent, so that it causes less misery than might be expected.Footnote 32 If we take this fact into account, critics say, we shall do less to reduce hardship than we should.Footnote 33 But this does not follow, because people who are more fortunate also adapt to their good fortune. So if we take from the privileged and give to the deprived, the privileged will also suffer less than might be expected. Thus the case for redistribution is hardly affected by the fact of adaptation: the poor may gain less extra wellbeing from it than might be expected, but the rich also suffer less than might be expected.Footnote 34 The balance of the argument is thus unaffected.

However, adaptation does have important implications if some experiences are less subject to adaptation than others. It is therefore important to distinguish between hardships that cannot be adapted to and those that can be. Hardships that are hard or impossible to adapt to include mental pain, chronic physical pain, incarceration, torture, indignity and intolerable noise.Footnote 35 These types of hardship need high priority in public policy.

Selfishness is encouraged

Critics often complain that, if we accept wellbeing as the supreme goal, this means that individuals should simply maximise their own wellbeing. Far from it. For each person’s wellbeing depends hugely on the benevolent behaviour of others. This is illustrated in Figure 2.1.

Figure 2.1 How wellbeing is determined by behaviour

In this profoundly important diagram, the outcome we care about is the overall wellbeing of society, represented by the whole right-hand side of the diagram. How can it be maximised? The answer is: only if everyone chooses to behave so as to maximise the overall wellbeing of society. That is the fundamental ethical principle proclaimed by Bentham and by all other supporters of the greatest happiness principle. This aspiration should inform a person’s whole life – both in private matters and also in the job they choose to do. In this view, morality is not just about what you should not do but also what you should do. For example, it is wrong to hurt someone but it is also wrong not to help them.

Some people say this is too ‘demanding’Footnote 36 – it takes over too much of your life. As with all other moral theories, it is hard to specify exactly how far we should sacrifice our individual happiness for the sake of others. But, if we want to reduce suffering, we clearly have to avoid not only hurting people (sins of commission) but also failing to help them (sins of omission).

To encourage good lives, we have two key psychological traits we can build on. The first is the pleasure that people derive from helping others: doing the right thing is not always pleasurable but it often is (see Chapter 3). The second is the impact of norms on habit. If people are expected to behave well from an early age, it just becomes a habit. This was the route that Aristotle stressed.

Both of these routes are at variance with the doctrines of Immanuel Kant, the great philosopher of the German Enlightenment, which provide the main alternative system of ethics to that based on the maximisation of wellbeing.Footnote 37 In the Kantian system, the ethical rightness of a person’s actions are judged by the person’s motives and not by their consequences. A moral action has to be a conscious act of will, and pleasure and habit are considered antithetical to truly moral action. There is, however, one key feature on which both Kantian and Benthamite approaches are agreed: every individual is of equal ultimate importance. This is fundamental to any ethical theory based on reason.

The nanny state

Turning to political theory, critics of the wellbeing approach sometimes claim that, if the government concerns itself with how people feel, this will lead to excessive interference in people’s lives. But wellbeing science itself shows the huge importance of freedom for personal wellbeing (see Chapters 8 and 16). So any government aiming at wellbeing will be constantly restrained by that consideration. Whenever possible, the government will provide opportunities that people can use or not, as they prefer.

It is, however, crucial to realise that many of the things that matter most to people are intensely personal (their mental health, their family relationships and their work situation) and failures in these dimensions are major sources of human misery. So a benevolent state is bound to offer help, if there are cost-effective forms of help that can be made available.

Social justice

A final problem is one that affects all ethical theories – how much weight to give to the interests of the least fortunate. Classic utilitarianism can be criticised because it gives equal value to more happiness whether it accrues to someone who is already happy or to someone who is miserable. But the ‘prioritarian approach’ we advocated earlier avoids this problem, and it provides a stronger basis for the legal creation of rights. It also asserts that income inequality is bad because an extra dollar is worth more to a poor person than a rich one. So a good society establishes rights (as a form of safety net) and it redistributes income.Footnote 38

No ethical theory is without problems. If you find the wellbeing approach problematic, can you think of a better criterion for how to live or how to make policy?

We can end with a different question. Is wellbeing an experience that humans were designed for? The answer from ‘evolutionary psychology’ is ‘Partly yes and partly no’. The basic features of human nature were created by natural selection about 200,000 years ago in Africa. The genes that survived in the struggle for survival were those that maximised our ‘inclusive fitness’ – in other words, the genes that were most likely to produce successive generations carrying the same genes. So how conducive to wellbeing were the genes that got selected? We were certainly constructed to enjoy many of the things necessary for survival and reproduction – sex, food, drink and a capacity to cooperate (see Chapter 3). Moreover, as we have seen, wellbeing is extremely good for many other things that are good for our survival – good for our physical health, for our productivity and for our creativity.Footnote 39

There were, however, some traits that were essential for survival in the Savannah that are not particularly conducive to an enjoyable life. The most obvious of these is anxiety. If lions are about, it is a good thing to be anxious. But life today is a lot more safe, and most people would have a more enjoyable life if they were less anxious (see Chapter 4).

As this book shows, we have the knowledge to improve our own wellbeing and that of others – a noble cause.

Conclusions

  1. (1) We are considering a very powerful idea – that social welfare depends only on the subjective wellbeing of the population. This is relevant to all aspects of life from public policy-making to personal behaviour. It is a concept with at least three uses.

    • It provides a measure for comparing situations, for example, comparing countries or comparing the same country at different periods in time.

    • It provides the fundamental principle of moral philosophy: that we personally should at all times do what we can to maximise social welfare.

    • It provides the fundamental principle of political philosophy: that governments should provide the conditions for the greatest possible social welfare.

  2. (2) Wellbeing has been a central issue in philosophy from the earliest times.

  3. (3) In the eighteenth century, Anglo-Scottish philosophers proposed the ‘greatest happiness’ of the people as the goal of moral and political action. Thus individuals should aim to be ‘creators of happiness’ and policy-makers should target the wellbeing of the people.

  4. (4) In the early twentieth century, behaviourism postulated that we could not know how others feel. In consequence, economists abandoned the policy goal of maximising happiness and moved to maximising aggregate income (GDP).

  5. (5) There is now a strong movement against using GDP as an indicator of wellbeing and in favour of some measure of the quality of life.

  6. (6) One version of the ‘social welfare function’ is ΣWi, where Wi is the wellbeing of the ith person. But most policies have impacts over a number of years. Thus forward looking social welfare is measured by ΣiΣt1δtWit, the discounted sum of future Wellbeing Years (WELLBYS).

  7. (7) The discount rate should be low. In this case the wellbeing of future generations is given the weight it deserves – making climate change and sustainability into hugely important issues.

  8. (8) Egalitarians prefer to measure the social value of today’s wellbeing not by ΣWi but by ΣfWi where fWirises at a diminishing rate as Wiincreases. In policy evaluation, a practical approach is to start with ΣWi and then test for sensitivity to different forms offWi. In addition we can mainly search for new policies in those areas of life which account for the greatest amount of misery.

  9. (9) The wellbeing approach has been criticised on many grounds including rights, ‘experience machine’, adaptation, selfishness and the ‘nanny state’. This book discusses these criticisms.

Questions for discussion

  1. (1) Do you agree that coherent policy-making requires some single overarching criterion? Should this be wellbeing?

  2. (2) Should the same idea govern our personal ethical choices?

  3. (3) Should the social welfare function be the simple sum of wellbeing across people? Or should it give extra weight to the scale of misery?

  4. (4) What is your view on the main criticisms made of the wellbeing approach to ethics and policy choice:

    • Consequentialism, rights and social justice

    • The experience machine.

    • Adaptation

    • Selfishness

    • Nanny state

Footnotes

1 We discuss the contribution of the Buddha in Chapter 4.

2 Of course, Christianity also forecast a new world on earth but only after the Second Coming.

4 There were also supporters on the continent of Europe but not so numerous. Notable contributors included the Italian jurist Cesare Beccaria (1738–1794) and the French philosopher Claude Adrien Helvétius (1715–1771).

6 Kaldor (Reference Kaldor1939); and Hicks (Reference Hicks1940).

8 Robert Kennedy in a speech at the University of Kansas on 18 March 1968.

9 Easterlin (Reference Clark1974).

10 See Diener (Reference De Neve, Ward, De Keulenaer, Van Landeghem, Kavetsos and Norton1984). Important forerunners were Cantril (Reference Cantril1965); Campbell, Converse and Rodgers (Reference Campbell, Converse and Rodgers1976); and Andrews and Withey (Reference Andrews and Withey1976). These books used the new wellbeing metric.

11 There are some wellbeing scientists who would only use the social welfare function as a guide to the choice of political constitutions, not as a guide on individual policies (see Frey Reference Frey2008).

12 As we argue later, future wellbeing should be slightly discounted.

13 HM Treasury (2020, 2021).

15 HM Treasury (2020).

16 We are now measuring wellbeing on a ‘ratio scale’ implying that we can say A is twice as happy as B. This is a further assumption that goes beyond (but does not contradict) the case for an interval scale which we made in Chapter 1.

17 See Chapter 10.

18 For example, Rawls (Reference Rawls1971) – see equation (5) below.

19 The symbol f(Wi) means a magnitude that varies with Wi. The symbol f′ means the increase in that magnitude as Wi increases by 1 unit. The symbol f′′ means the increase in f′ as Wi grows by one unit. If we assume that dead people have no social value, we have to choose a f(W) function that has the property that f(0) = 0.

20 Harsanyi (1953, Reference Harsanyi1955); Rawls (Reference Rawls1971).

21 Dolan (Reference Dolan2014) p. 179.

22 This is not contrary to the principle that future prospects should be valued according to their ‘expected utility’, as Harsanyi (1953, Reference Harsanyi1955) argued, i.e., according to Σπiui where πi is the probability of outcome i and ui is the ‘utility’ of outcome i. This is because for every outcome i there is a value ui such that the person is indifferent between the outcome i (experienced with certainty) and, alternatively, the probability ui of the best outcome plus the probability 1−ui of the worst outcome. But Egalitarians would argue that if people are risk averse, uiwill be a concave function of true happiness, Wi: thus ui=fWif′>0f″<0.

23 One formulation of this question is to assumeS=Σ1λWiλλ≤1. We then debate the value of λ.

24 Rawls (Reference Rawls1971). (Rawls applied this judgement only to the distribution of ‘primary goods’).

25 This approach has been called ‘sufficientarian’. To encourage a focus on misery Kahneman and his colleagues devised a so-called u-index, which measures the proportion of the day in which a person is predominantly miserable (Krueger Reference Krueger2009).

26 Some modern philosophers, like the leading utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer, argue that we should stop at ΣWi partly because going any further takes us too far from what could in principle be objectively measured. De Lazari-Radek and Singer (Reference de Lazari-Radek and Singer2017).

27 Sen and Williams (Reference Sen and Williams1982). For a different view, see Smart in Smart and Williams (Reference Mill1973).

29 According to Bentham the doctrine of natural rights is ‘nonsense on stilts’. See Bentham (Reference Bentham2002).

31 See Hindriks and Douven (Reference Deaton and Cartwright2018).

32 For the scale of adaptation to many types of experience, see A. E. Clark et al. (Reference Clark, Flèche, Layard, Powdthavee and Ward2018).

34 Actually, there is not much evidence of adaptation to income once social comparisons are taken into account – see Chapter 13.

35 On noise, see Weinstein (Reference Weinstein1982).

36 See Railton (1984).

37 See, for example, Scruton (Reference Scruton1982).

38 Layard and Walters (Reference Layard and Walters1978) pp. 47–51 and references therein.

References

Further Reading

de Lazari-Radek, K., and Singer, P. (2017). Utilitarianism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Layard, R., and Ward, G. (2020). Can We Be Happier? Evidence and Ethics. Penguin UK.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1863). Utilitarianism. Parker, Son & Bourn, West Strand.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C., and Williams, B. (1973). Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 2.1 How wellbeing is determined by behaviour

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×