Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T06:32:34.444Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Kuhn's World Changes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 December 2009

Richard E. Grandy
Affiliation:
Carolyn and Fred McManis Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Rice University
Thomas Nickles
Affiliation:
University of Nevada, Reno
Get access

Summary

Of all the controversial elements of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962/1970), the most controversial and problematic for the majority of readers are Kuhn's claims about the changes in the world that accompany scientific revolutions. Kuhn's own ambivalence about his doctrine is exemplified by the contrast between the title of Chapter X, “Revolutions as Changes of World View,” which places the changes in the minds and theories of the scientists, and the first sentence of that section, which shows the temptation to locate the change in the worlds themselves:

Examining the record of past research from the vantage of contemporary historiography, the historian of science may be tempted to exclaim that when paradigms change, the world itself changes with it.

(1970 ed., p. 111)

Kuhn describes himself as “acutely aware” of the difficulties posed by his locutions:

The same difficulties are presented in an even more fundamental form by the opening sentences of this section: though the world does not change with a change of paradigm, the scientist afterward works in a different world.

(p. 121)

One example he discusses at some length (pun intended) is the pendulum. Heavy objects suspended by ropes or chains had existed for a long time, and certainly their occasional motions had been observed. However, for an Aristotelian this is an example of unnatural motion: The heavy body is moved by its nature toward the center of the Earth and the universe, but it is constrained by the suspension.

Type
Chapter
Information
Thomas Kuhn , pp. 246 - 260
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beth, Evert. 1961. “Semantics of Physical Theories.” In: Hans Freudenthal, ed., The Concept and the Role of the Model in Mathematics and Social Sciences. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 48–51
Brewer, William F., and Bruce B. Lambert. 1993. “The Theory-Ladenness of Observation: Evidence from Cognitive Psychology.” Proceedings of the Fifteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Brewer, William F., & C. A. Chinn. 1994. “Scientists' Responses to Anomalous Data: Evidence from Psychology, History, and Philosophy of Science.” In: PSA, Vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 304–13
Campbell, N. R. 1920. Physics: The Elements. Reprinted as Foundations of Science. New York: Dover, 1957
Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Carnap, Rudolf. 1956. “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts.” In: Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven, eds. The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 1). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 38–76
Cartwright, Dorwin. 1973. “Determinants of Scientific Progress: The Case of Research on the Risky Shift.” American Psychologist 28: 222–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul. 1965. “Problems of Empiricism.” In: R. Colodny, ed. Beyond the Edge of Certainty. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 145-260
Giere, Ronald N. 1988. Explaining Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Giere, Ronald N. 1999. Science without Laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Grandy, Richard, ed. 1973. Theories and Observation. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Press
Grandy, Richard, 1983. “Incommensurability: Kinds and Causes.” Philosophica 32: 7–24Google Scholar
Grandy, Richard, 1992. “Theories of Theories: A Perspective from Cognitive Science.” In: John Earman, ed. Inference, Explanation and Other Frustrations: Essays in the Philosophy of Science. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 216–33
Hanson, Norwood Russell. 1958. Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Hempel, C. G. 1945. “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation.” Mind 54: 1–16, 97–121CrossRef
Hempel, C. G. 1958. “The Theoretician's Dilemma.” In: Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell, eds. Concepts, Theories and the Mind–Body Problem (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 37–98
Hesse, Mary. 1966. Models and Analogies in Science. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
Horwich, Paul, ed. 1993. World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul. 1993. Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn's Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul, and Howard Sankey, eds. 2001. Incommensurability and Related Matters. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers
Kuhn, T. S. 1957. The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Kuhn, T. S. 1962/1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Kuhn, T. S. 1977. The Essential Tension: Selected Essays in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Kuhn, T. S. 1978. Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Kuhn, T. S. 2000. The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993 with an Autobiographical Interview. Edited by James Conant and John Haugeland. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Mpemba, E. G., and Osborne, D. G.. 1969. “Cool?Physics Education 4: 172–5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Osborne, D. G. 1979. “Mind on Ice.” Physics Education 14: 414–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, Dudley. 1984. Reason and the Search for Knowledge. Dordrecht: Reidel
Sneed, Joseph. 1971. The Logical Structure of Mathematical Physics. Dordrecht: Reidel
Sneed, Joseph. 1977. “Describing Revolutionary Scientific Change: A Formal Approach.” In: R. E. Butts and J. Hintikka, eds. Historical and Philosophical Dimensions of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 245–68
Stegmüller, Wolfgang. 1976. The Structure and Dynamics of Theories. New York: Springer-Verlag
Stegmüller, Wolfgang. 1979. The Structuralist View of Theories. New York Springer-Verlag
Stein, Paul S. G., L. I. Mortin, and G. A. Robertson. 1986. “The Forms of a Task and Their Blends.” In: S. Griller, P. S. G. Stein, H. Forssberg, and R. M. Herman, eds. Neurobiology of Vertebrate Locomotion. Hampshire, U.K.: Macmillan, pp. 201–16
Stoner, J. A. F. 1961. “A Comparison of Individual and Group Decisions Involving Risk.” Unpublished master's thesis, Sloan School of Management, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Suppe, Fredrick, ed. 1977. The Structure of Scientific Theories, 2nd ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press
Suppes, Patrick. 1967. “What Is a Scientific Theory? In: Sidney Morgenbesser, ed. Philosophy of Science Today. New York: Basic Books, pp. 55–67
Suppes, Patrick. 1969. “Models of Data.” In: P. Suppes, ed. Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 24–35
van Fraassen, Bas. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press
van Fraassen, Bas. 1987. “The Semantic Approach to Scientific Theories.” In: Nancy Nersessian, ed. The Process of Science. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, pp. ;105–24

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Kuhn's World Changes
    • By Richard E. Grandy, Carolyn and Fred McManis Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Rice University
  • Edited by Thomas Nickles, University of Nevada, Reno
  • Book: Thomas Kuhn
  • Online publication: 07 December 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511613975.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Kuhn's World Changes
    • By Richard E. Grandy, Carolyn and Fred McManis Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Rice University
  • Edited by Thomas Nickles, University of Nevada, Reno
  • Book: Thomas Kuhn
  • Online publication: 07 December 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511613975.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Kuhn's World Changes
    • By Richard E. Grandy, Carolyn and Fred McManis Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Rice University
  • Edited by Thomas Nickles, University of Nevada, Reno
  • Book: Thomas Kuhn
  • Online publication: 07 December 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511613975.011
Available formats
×