Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T06:33:55.512Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Kuhn and Logical Empiricism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 December 2009

Michael Friedman
Affiliation:
Professor of Arts and Humanities, Indiana University
Thomas Nickles
Affiliation:
University of Nevada, Reno
Get access

Summary

Conventional wisdom concerning twentieth-century philosophical approaches to scientific knowledge has held that Kuhn's theory of scientific revolutions is diametrically opposed to the philosophical movement known as “logical positivism” or “logical empiricism.” Logical positivism has been portrayed as a naive version of empiricist foundationalism, according to which all knowledge is to be reduced to an epistemically certain basis in observational reports. And it follows, on this view, that there can be no genuine scientific revolutions in the Kuhnian sense: scientific progress must rather follow the “development-by-accumulation” model (in this case, development by accumulation of observable facts) that Kuhn explicitly rejects at the outset. If we accept Kuhn's theory, by contrast, it follows that the progress of science is marked by radical discontinuities quite incompatible with such naive empiricism. So it is no wonder that Kuhn's theory of scientific revolutions is standardly taken as a major factor in the demise of logical empiricism.

Over the past twenty-five years, however, a growing body of active research has been devoted to detailed study of the rise and decline of the logical empiricist movement. And this research has shown, not surprisingly, that the accepted conventional wisdom concerning the relationship between Kuhn's theory of scientific revolutions and logical empiricist philosophy of science is seriously oversimplified and fundamentally misleading. Perhaps the most striking results of this research appear in an article by George Reisch (1991) entitled “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Empiricism?

Type
Chapter
Information
Thomas Kuhn , pp. 19 - 44
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ayer, Alfred Jules. 1936. Language, Truth, and Logic. London: Gollancz
Brunschvicg, Léon. 1912. Les étapes de la philosophie mathématique. Paris: Alcan
Brunschvicg, Léon. 1922. L'expérience humaine et la causalité physique. Paris: Alcan
Carnap, Rudolf. 1922. Der Raum. Berlin: Reuther & Reichard
Carnap, Rudolf. 1928. Der logische Auf bau der Welt. Berlin: Weltkreis, 1928. 2nd ed. Hamburg: Meiner, 1961. Translated from the 2nd ed. as The Logical Structure of the World. Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1967
Carnap, Rudolf. 1934. Logische Syntax der Sprache. Wien: Springer. Translated as The Logical Syntax of Language. London: Kegan Paul, 1937
Carnap, Rudolf. 1936. “Von der Erkenntnistheorie zur Wissenschaftslogik.” In Actes du Congrès international de philosophie scientifique, vol. 4. Paris: Hermann
Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 11: 20–40. Reprinted in Meaning and Necessity, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956
Carnap, Rudolf. 1963. “Intellectual Autobiography.” In Schilpp (1963), pp. 3–43
Cassirer, Ernst. 1906–7. Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit. 2 vols. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer
Cassirer, Ernst. 1910. Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer. Translated as Substance and Function. Chicago: Open Court, 1923
Cassirer, Ernst. 1921. Zur Einsteinschen Relativitätstheorie. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer. Translated as Einstein's Theory of Relativity. Chicago: Open Court, 1923
Coffa, J. Alberto. 1991. The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Cohen, H. Floris. 1994. The Scientific Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Cohen, Robert and Yehuda Elkana, eds. 1977. Hermann von Helmholtz: Epistemological Writings. Dordrecht: Reidel. Translation of P. Hertz and M. Schlick, eds. Hermann v. Helmholtz: Schriften zur Erkenntnistheorie. Berlin: Springer, 1921
Earman, John. 1993. “Carnap, Kuhn, and the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology.” In Horwich (1993), pp. 9–36
Friedman, Michael. 1983. “Critical Notice: Moritz Schlick, Philosophical Papers.” Philosophy of Science 50: 498–514. Reprinted (with a Postscript) in Friedman (1999), pp. 17–43
Earman, John. 1987. “Carnap's Auf bau Reconsidered.” NoÛs 21: 521–45. Reprinted in Friedman (1999), pp. 89–113
Earman, John. 1992a. “Philosophy and the Exact Sciences: Logical Positivism as a Case Study.” In J. Earman, ed. Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 84–98
Earman, John. 1992b. “Epistemology in the Auf bau.” Synthese 93: 15–57. Reprinted (with a Postscript) in Friedman (1999), pp. 114–62Google Scholar
Earman, John. 1993. “Remarks on the History of Science and the History of Philosophy.” In Horwich (1993), pp. 37–54
Earman, John. 1994. “Geometry, Convention, and the Relativized a Priori.” In W. Salmon and G. Wolters, eds. Logic, Language, and the Structure of Scientific Theories. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 21–34. Reprinted in Friedman (1999), pp. 59–70
Earman, John. 1995. “Carnap and Weyl on the Foundations of Geometry and Relativity Theory.” Erkenntnis 42: 247–60. Reprinted in Friedman (1999), pp. 44–58Google Scholar
Earman, John. 1996. “Poincaré's Conventionalism and the Logical Positivists.” In J.-L. Greffe, G. Heinzmann, and K. Lorenz, eds. Henri Poincaré: Science and Philosophy. Berlin and Paris: Akademie Verlag, 1996, pp. 299–314. Reprinted in Friedman (1999), pp. 71–86
Earman, John. 1997. “Helmholtz's Zeichentheorie and Schlick's Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre.” Philosophical Topics 25: 19–50CrossRef
Earman, John. 1998. “On the Sociology of Scientific Knowedge and Its Philosophical Agenda.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 239–71Google Scholar
Earman, John 1999. Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Earman, John 2000a. “Geometry, Construction, and Intuition in Kant and His Successors.” In: G. Sher and R. Tieszen, eds. Between Logic and Intuition: Essays in Honor of Charles Parsons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 186–211
Earman, John 2000b. A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Chicago: Open Court
Earman, John 2001. Dynamics of Reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications
Earman, John 2002. “Geometry as a Branch of Physics: Background and Context for Einstein's ‘Geometry and Experience’.” In D. Malament, ed. Reading Natural Philosophy: Essays in Honor of Howard Stein. Chicago: Open Court
Giere, Ronald. 1988. Explaining Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Golinski, Jan. 1987. “Hélène Metzger and the Interpretation of Seventeenth Century Chemistry.” History of Science 25: 85–97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson. 1951. The Structure of Appearance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Goodman, Nelson. 1963. “The Significance of Der logische Auf bau der Welt.” In Schilpp (1963), pp. 545–58
Haack, Susan. 1977. “Carnap's Auf bau: Some Kantian Reflexions.” Ratio 19: 170–6Google Scholar
Halsted, George, ed. 1913. The Foundations of Science. Lancaster: Science Press
Horwich, Paul, ed. 1993. World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Koyré, Alexandre. 1931. “Die Philosophie Emile Meyersons.” Deutsch-Französische Rundschau 4: 197–217Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre 1978. Galileo Studies. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. Translation of Etudes Galiléenes. 3 vols. Paris: Hermann, 1939
Kuhn, Thomas. 1968. “The History of Science.” In International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. New York: Crowell Collier and Macmillan. Reprinted in Kuhn (1977), pp. 105–26
Kuhn, Thomas. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Original edition published in 1962
Kuhn, Thomas. 1977. The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Kuhn, Thomas. 1984. “Revisiting Planck.” Historical Studies in the Physical Studies 14: 231–52. Reprinted as Afterward in Kuhn (1987), pp. 349–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1987. Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912. 2nd (paperback) ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Kuhn, Thomas. 1993. “Afterwords.” In Horwich (1993), pp. 311–41
Maier, Anneliese. 1930. Kants Qualitätskategorien. Berlin: Metzner
Maier, Anneliese. 1949. Die Vorläufer Galileis im 14. Jahrhundert. Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura
Metzger, Hélène. 1923. Les doctrines chimique en France du début du XVIIeà la fin du XVIIIesiècle. Paris: Les Presses Universitaires de France
Metzger, Hélène. 1930. Newton, Stahl, Boerhaave et la doctrine chimique. Paris: Alcan
Metzger, Hélène. 1937. “La méthode philosophique dans l'histoire des science.” Archeion 19: 204–16CrossRef
Meyerson, Émile. 1930. Identity and Reality. London: Allen & Unwin. Translation from 3rd ed., 1926 (identical to 2nd ed., 1912), of Identité et réalité. Paris: Alcan, 1908
Moulines, C. Ulises. 1985. “Hintergründe der Erkenntnistheorie des frühen Carnap.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 23: 1–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Natorp, Paul. 1910. Die logischen Grundlagen der exakten Wissenschaften. Leipzig: Teubner
Poincaré, Henri. 1902. La Science et l'Hypothèse. Paris: Flammarion. Translated as Science and Hypothesis. In Halsted (1913), pp. 27–197
Poincaré, Henri. 1905. La Valeur de la Science. Paris: Flammarion. Translated as The Value of Science. In Halsted (1913), pp. 205–355
Poincaré, Henri. 1908. Science et Méthode. Paris: Flammarion. Translated as Science and Method. In Halsted (1913), pp. 359–546
Quine, Willard van Orman. 1951. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” Philosophical Review 60: 20–43. Reprinted in From a Logical Point of View. New York: Harper, 1963, pp. 20–46
Quine, Willard van Orman. 1969. “Epistemology Naturalized.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 69–90
Reichenbach, Hans. 1920. Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori. Berlin: Springer. Translated as The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge. Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1965
Reisch, George. 1991. “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Empiricism?Philosophy of Science 58: 264–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, Alan. 1992. “Logical Idealism and Carnap's Construction of the World.” Synthese 93: 59–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, Alan. 1996. “From Epistemology to the Logic of Science.” In R. Giere and A. Richardson, eds. Origins of Logical Empiricism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 309–32
Richardson, Alan. 1998. Carnap's Construction of the World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press
Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. London: Allen & Unwin
Sargent, Steven, ed. 1982. On the Threshold of Exact Science. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
Sauer, Werner. 1985. “Carnaps ‘Aufbau’ in Kantianischer Sicht.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 23: 19–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, Werner. 1989. “On the Kantian Background of Neopositivism.” Topoi 8: 111–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schilpp, Paul Arthur, ed. 1963. The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, IL: Open Court
Schlick, Moritz. 1917. Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Berlin: Springer. 2nd ed., 1919. 3rd ed., 1920. 4th ed., 1922. Translated from the 3rd ed. as Space and Time in Contemporary Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1920. Expanded to include changes in the 4th ed. in H. Mulder and B. van de Velde-Schlick, Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978
Suppe, Frederick. 1977. The Structure of Scientific Theories. 2nd ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press
Whitehead, Alfred and Bertrand Russell. 1910–13. Principia Mathematica. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×