Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-pdxrj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-09T22:38:27.622Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - The Confusion of the Two Powers and the Baroque Drift of Cartesianism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 March 2025

Get access

Summary

Let us first of all ask what concept of royal power is at work in the scholium:

By God's power ordinary people understand God's free will and his right over all things which are, things which on that account are commonly considered to be contingent. For they say that God has the power of destroying all things and reducing them to nothing. Further, they often compare God's power with the power of Kings. But we have refuted this in I, 32 cor. 1 and cor. 2, and we have shown in I, 16 that God acts with the same necessity by which he understands himself, i.e., just as it follows from the necessity of the divine nature (as everyone maintains unanimously) that God understands himself, with the same necessity it also follows that God does infinitely many things in infinitely many modes. And then we have shown in I, 34 that God's power is nothing except God's active essence. And so it is as impossible for us to conceive that God does not act as it is to conceive that he does not exist.

The distinction between the two powers intersects with two others: that of divine and human natures, and the distinction between conceptions of freedom. The common person (vulgus) is inclined to attribute a body and a mind to God, and consequently to subject it to the passions; when it comes to philosophers, judging God's sovereign perfection by human perfections, they ascribe to God an understanding and a will. Spinoza has in mind the prophetic visions of the Old Testament studied in the Theologico-Political Treatise. The passage also repeats the expression instar hominis, which is utilised in the scholium to I, 15. However, the anthropomorphism here is of another nature: it consists in attributing to God a potentia humana; and then there is the polemic on freedom (the philosophers, whether we are talking about Thomas Aquinas or Descartes, have tended to confuse constraint and necessity, and to define God's freedom as ‘free will’, ‘absolute will’, ‘arbitrariness’ [bon plaisir], ‘indifference’).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Edinburgh University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×