Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T10:51:12.101Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Towards an evolutionary theory of language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Nikolaus Ritt
Affiliation:
Universität Wien, Austria
Get access

Summary

Can there be linguistic replicators at all?

Criteria for identifying replicators

The chances of finding an integrated evolutionary model of language and language change depend on the question of whether linguistic replicators can really be assumed to exist. Unless they do, we need not bother with the rest. Are there really any competence properties that qualify as linguistic replicators then? In order to decide, we first need clear criteria. Dawkins proposes a definition that is analogical to his definition of a ‘gene’, ‘which comes from G. C. Williams. A gene is defined as any portion of chromosomal material [i.e. DNA] that potentially lasts for enough generations to serve as a unit of natural selection. [… It] is a replicator with high copying-fidelity. Copying fidelity is another way of saying longevity-in-the-form-of-copies’ (Dawkins 1989: 28f). Accordingly, Dawkins sees a meme as ‘an entity that is capable of being transmitted from one brain to another’ (1989: 196), and Dennett basically follows him by defining memes as ‘the smallest units that replicate themselves with reliability and fecundity’.

These definitions yield the following criteria for ‘replicatorship’.

  • First, a replicator needs to be an ‘entity’. This means it must be identifiable, and persist for a minimal period of time with its characteristic properties intact, that is, it must have a minimal stability, or longevity.

  • Secondly, a replicator must be capable of being transmitted faithfully. That is to say there must be a minimal fidelity to its copies. Otherwise it would not be justified to call an entity replicating at all. So, the second criterion must be copying fidelity. Of course, while copying fidelity must be high for an entity to qualify as a replicator, it must be less than perfect for evolution to become possible.

Type
Chapter
Information
Selfish Sounds and Linguistic Evolution
A Darwinian Approach to Language Change
, pp. 122 - 229
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×