The Max Planck Trialogues on the Law of Peace and War have so far dealt with Self-Defence against Non-State ActorsFootnote 1 and with Law Applicable to Armed Conflict.Footnote 2 After taking up pressing topics of the ius contra bellum and ius in bello in its first two volumes, the series focuses on reparation for victims of armed conflict in this third, and thus it is dedicated to the ius post bellum.Footnote 3
I. Reparation in International Law
Demands for reparation have many facets and emerge on multiple levels: between States for present violations of the law; for victims of genocide, war crimes, and crimes against humanity;Footnote 4 for groups of victims with particular vulnerabilities;Footnote 5 and also for historical wrongs,Footnote 6 such as colonialism,Footnote 7 violence committed against indigenous peoples,Footnote 8 and slavery.Footnote 9 This Trialogue deals with one specific aspect of the reparation debate – namely, reparation for victims of armed conflict. It provides a new perspective on the issue by focusing on practical experiences in the implementation of individual reparation.
The concept of reparation is firmly established in international law. It originally emerged as a concept of war reparations – that is, the payments or transferral of goods that (most commonly) the defeated party in a war had to pay to the victors.Footnote 10 The term ‘war’ in ‘war reparations’ was, before World War II, a redundant modifier because no general concept of reparation existed.Footnote 11 Today, the situation is different. An established rule of customary international law stipulates that States are obliged to provide reparation for violations of international law, including violations committed outside of the context of armed conflicts. This is clearly expressed in the International Law Commission’s 2001 Draft Articles on the Responsibility of States for International Wrongful Acts (ARSIWA).Footnote 12
Reparation today has to be understood broadly, referring to restitution, compensation, satisfaction, rehabilitation, and guarantees of non-repetition.Footnote 13 A highly controversial issue under the current legal framework remains the question of whether – and if so, under what conditions – individuals may be seen to have a right to reparation under international law.
A remark is warranted regarding the terminology concerning reparation, because the use of such terminology is often inconsistent. The plural form – namely, reparations – is used to refer to ‘war reparations’.Footnote 14 When referring to a right to reparation of individuals, the singular form may be used.Footnote 15 Sometimes, however, the term reparations is used to describe one specific form of reparation – namely, compensation.Footnote 16 Plenty of scholarly publications also use the plural form as the general term covering all forms of reparation.Footnote 17 Likewise, in international criminal law, the plural form is frequently used.Footnote 18 For the sake of conceptual clarity, it seems best to speak of a (potential) right of victims to reparation and to reserve the plural form for referring to war reparations.Footnote 19
The establishment of reparation mechanisms for victims of war was already a matter of debate in the early days of the codification of international humanitarian law (IHL). In 1872, Gustave Moynier, co-founder of the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC), presented a proposal for an international criminal tribunal that was supposed to have jurisdiction over breaches of the 1864 Geneva Convention.Footnote 20 Moynier suggested that this tribunal should have the power to sentence perpetrators based on an international penal code, which he also proposed to establish.Footnote 21 Furthermore, Moynier’s proposal included a reparation mechanism under which States would have to file claims for the compensation of individuals.Footnote 22 However, the reparation award was not to be borne by the sentenced individual but by the State on whose side the individual was acting. It would be unfair, Moynier argued, if the victim were to bear the risk of the perpetrator’s inability to pay. Moynier also pointed out the benefits of governments having an immediate financial interest in their citizens respecting IHL.Footnote 23
There have been significant legal developments since then, but whether an individual right to reparation exists is still contested. The ARSIWA address only those obligations owed to States or to the international community as a whole. And they explicitly state that those Articles comprising Part 2 (relating to the content of responsibility) are ‘without prejudice to any right, arising from the international responsibility of a State, which may accrue directly to any person or entity other than a State’.Footnote 24 This clause suggests – or at least allows for – an obligation of States to make reparation towards individuals outside the scope of the ARSIWA.
Analytical clarity over whether an individual right to reparation exists may be achieved by means of a three-step approach.Footnote 25 First, there must be a primary rule of international law (in IHL or elsewhere) that grants individual rights. This is a necessary precondition because individual reparation can accrue only out of the violation of a legal position that is attributed to the individual. Second, it is relevant to determine whether international law also grants individuals the right to claim reparation for a violation of a primary rule of international law. This is by no means obvious: as a legal order traditionally addressing inter-State relations, international law can be interpreted as enabling only States to claim violations of the rights of their citizens against other States.Footnote 26 Asserting a victim’s secondary right to claim reparation is not, however, sufficient to give reparation claims effect in practice. As the International Law Association observed in its 2010 report on ‘Reparation for Victims of Armed Conflict’, ‘[u]nder traditional international law, the existence of an individual right is not dependent on the international procedural capacity to assert it’.Footnote 27 Thus a third step becomes crucial. Tertiary rights are necessary to establish sufficient procedural rights for individuals to claim reparation.Footnote 28
This three-pronged approach illustrates the complexity of the legal issues at play. There are hardly clear-cut or across-the-board answers to questions regarding the right to reparation for victims of war because the existing rules on all three levels are manifold and vary in different subfields of international law.
II. Developments towards an Individual Right to Reparation
Legal developments towards an individual right to reparation can be traced within various levels of international law and they are extensively analysed by the authors of this volume. Numerous regimes of international human rights law provide a clear legal foundation for an individual right to reparation. First of all, at the primary level, human rights law establishes individual rights. While the issue of the applicability of human rights law during armed conflict has long been (and remains) a subject of controversy, it is now widely accepted that, as a matter of principle, human rights law applies alongside IHL during armed conflict.Footnote 29 Hence, notwithstanding the controversial details of applicability, it is at least in principle possible for victims of armed conflict to rely on human rights law.Footnote 30
Moreover, numerous human rights law regimes also contain provisions on reparation. In most cases, these obligations are not expressed as an individual right to claim reparation but rather as an obligation of the State to guarantee effective reparation within the domestic legal system.Footnote 31 For example, the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights sets out States’ obligations to ensure that any person whose rights or freedoms under the Covenant have been violated shall have an effective remedy.Footnote 32 The Human Rights Committee has interpreted this to entail an obligation of States to ‘make reparation to individuals whose Covenant rights have been violated’.Footnote 33 We find the same approach in the International Law Commission’s Draft Articles on Crimes against Humanity.Footnote 34
In contrast with such State-centred approaches, some regimes have established a procedure for individual claims.Footnote 35 In some instances, the regional systems even foresee compensation as one form of reparation.Footnote 36 The European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR), for example, may award ‘just satisfaction’ where the Court deems that ‘necessary’.Footnote 37 Even where the Court does not award compensation, it considers its judgment to be a form of satisfaction.
Significant legal developments have also taken place in international criminal law. Before the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY), only claims regarding the restitution of property were foreseen in the ICTY Statute.Footnote 38 The Rules of the ICTY explicitly deferred claims for compensation to domestic courts.Footnote 39 A significant innovation, then, was the establishment of a reparation mechanism before the International Criminal Court (ICC).Footnote 40 Moreover, the Internal Rules of the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (ECCC)Footnote 41 and the Kosovo Specialist Chambers both foresee the possibility of victims seeking reparation.Footnote 42
In accordance with the individual responsibility of perpetrators that criminal proceedings seek to establish, the reparation award is, in principle, to be borne by the convicted person. Thus, in contrast to the rules on reparation within the ARSIWA framework, reparation in criminal proceedings does not lead to a claim against a State. This, of course, imposes a significant burden on victims because perpetrators often do not have the resources to bear the reparation award. This fact has led to the creation of models of collective funding for reparation awards within criminal proceedings – most notably, the Trust Fund for Victims for awards in proceedings before the ICC.Footnote 43
The trend towards awarding reparation to victims has further manifested in the proceedings before ad hoc international commissions established to issue compensation awards after international armed conflicts. Especially noteworthy are the United Nations Compensation Commission (UNCC), established by the Security Council to deal with compensation claims after Iraq’s invasion of Kuwait in 1990, and the Eritrea–Ethiopia Claims Commission (EECC), established in 2001 and based on an agreement between the two countries. These mechanisms will be thoroughly analysed and assessed throughout this volume: Shuichi Furuya focuses especially on international ad hoc reparation mechanisms; Cristián Correa provides an in-depth discussion of the UNCC and the EECC, as well as of various domestic reparation programmes; and Clara Sandoval focuses on the practice of awarding reparation before the Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR) and ECtHR.
A highly contested question is whether these developments have also led to the emergence of an individual right to reparation for violations of IHL. Underpinning the debate is an acknowledgement that, at least from a normative standpoint, the legal situation under IHL should be no different from that under other subfields of international law, especially human rights law. In fact, as Rainer Hofmann points out, it is ‘difficult to accept that the situation should be different under international humanitarian law’.Footnote 44
However, plenty of legal challenges remain, on all of the three levels that are necessary for a robust right to reparation. On the primary level, it remains contested whether IHL contains individual rights or whether it sets out only the obligations of States. The background to this controversy is that IHL rules – based on their wording – mostly establish State duties, so that individuals could be viewed as ‘indirect beneficiaries’ only.Footnote 45 Ziv Bohrer argues in this direction, pointing out that IHL is focused on obligation-bearers, not on rights-holders, which – so he argues – is more effective in protecting individuals.Footnote 46 Kate Parlett concludes that IHL ‘remains consistent with the nineteenth century framework of the international legal system, as a system which creates only interstate rights’.Footnote 47 This conclusion, however, is by no means compelling. The ‘obligations language’ has not prevented anybody from assuming that IHL creates obligations not only for States but also for acting soldiers,Footnote 48 so that it would seem coherent if the bestowal of obligations and rights were to go hand in hand. Rather, the very aim of IHL is to guarantee minimum standards of humanity in times of armed conflict and this implicit focus on the individual supports the case for IHL-based individual rights.Footnote 49
Even more controversial is whether, on the secondary level, individuals have a right to reparation for violations of IHL (or whether only States have the right to claim violations on behalf of their citizens). Existing treaty law provides an important starting point. Article 3 of the 1907 Hague Convention (IV) respecting the Laws and Customs of War on LandFootnote 50 and Article 91 of the 1977 Additional Protocol I (AP I) to the Geneva ConventionsFootnote 51 contain an obligation for States to pay compensation. Based on their wording, it seems possible to interpret the provisions as also entitling individuals to claim reparation.Footnote 52 This interpretation is not ruled out by the fact that such a perspective was certainly not the original intention of the Conventions’ drafters.Footnote 53 Although sound, however, such an interpretation has yet to be adopted by courts and other law-appliers – in other words, it is not lex lata.
In view of changing circumstances – above all, the general recognition of the individual in various subfields of international law and its recognition as a partial subject of international lawFootnote 54 – these rules could potentially be (re)interpreted in light of subsequent practiceFootnote 55 – practice and opinio iuris that might then also provide evidence of a respective right under customary international law.
Assessing the practice of States clearly illustrates a reluctance to acknowledge and implement an individual right to reparation. Courts have generally been very dismissive and have often employed ‘avoidance doctrines’Footnote 56 – as illustrated, for example, by GermanFootnote 57 and JapaneseFootnote 58 court decisions and their general lack of recognition of an individual right to reparation.Footnote 59
More openness appears to be reflected in the 2004 Israeli Wall Advisory Opinion of the International Court of Justice (ICJ), in which the Court stated that ‘Israel also has an obligation to compensate, in accordance with the applicable rules of international law, all natural or legal persons having suffered any form of material damage as a result of the wall’s construction’.Footnote 60 The Court did not provide further substance concerning this claim’s legal foundation. However, Israel being the occupying power and thus IHL being a relevant legal framework, and because there is no generally recognised State that could file a claim on behalf of its citizens, this advisory opinion can be read as evidence of an individual right to reparation.Footnote 61
Some international bodies and individuals – such as the judges of the ICTYFootnote 62 or the International Commission of Inquiry on DarfurFootnote 63 – have been more straightforward in recognising an individual right to reparation.
III. The Trialogue on Reparation
Against this complex backdrop of diverse legal regimes, the Trialogue aims to find answers to three leading questions.
1. Does an individual right to reparation exist in international law, or does it arise out of an interplay between international and domestic law? This question has often been asked, but it remains unresolved. As usual, when confronted with emerging rules of customary international law, we debate for quite some time whether sufficient State practice and articulations of opinio iuris have materialised for the new rule to be thought to have crystallised into binding international law. Even though the question about the existence of an individual right to reparation appears to be rather theoretical, it nevertheless has practical relevance, especially with regard to the prospect of enforcing a possible right to reparation before domestic courts. For example, within the German legal system, rules of customary international law form an integral part of federal law.Footnote 64 If an individual right to reparation were to exist under customary international law (which German courts have so far deniedFootnote 65), reparation could in principle also be claimed before German courts. Thus the legal question about the existence of a right to reparation remains relevant and requires analysis in light of recent developments.
2. How can reparation programmes practically be implemented? The authors of this volume are convinced that, because victims themselves do not greatly benefit from an abstract analysis of the existence of a general right to reparation, the debate therefore has to move forward by focusing instead on the procedural, institutional, and concrete designs of reparation programmes. Which type of legal mechanisms have proven successful in practice? What were the factors relevant for success and what caused a programme to fall short of the expectations expressed towards it? These questions relate to, but are independent of, the actual existence of a right to reparation. Even if one were to find that practice has not crystallised into a general individual right, policy-makers would still depend on an understanding of the concrete legal designs of reparation mechanisms that have been implemented in practice and have proven to be beneficial in post-conflict societies. The experiences of past programmes are important for identifying best practices, and they might also form the building blocks for the procedural or substantive elements of an emerging right to reparation.
3. What is the content of the right to reparation? This content is largely determined by the context of implementation. What is the substance of the right to reparation in mechanisms that have already been established? What conclusions can we draw for a general individual right to reparation? Which legal challenges exist in view of the particular situation we face following armed conflicts – that is, in cases in which a particularly high number of victims has to be deplored? Do principles of awarding reparation established before international human rights courts need to be adapted to mass proceedings after armed conflict? And if so, how?
These questions are addressed throughout this Trialogue, and three authors with broad expertise in both the legal and practical dimensions of awarding reparation to victims of war develop a number of answers. The first author, Shuichi Furuya, is a professor of International Law at Waseda University Law School in Japan and a member of the United Nations Human Rights Committee. Shuichi Furuya has extensively researched the right to reparation and its implementation. He has been a co-rapporteur of the International Law Association’s Committee on Reparation for Victims of Armed Conflict.
In answering the first question about the existence of an individual right to reparation for victims of war, Shuichi Furuya provides a detailed study of the development of state practice in regard to reparation. He shows how the concept of reparation has been transformed from a mere inter-State affair that results in lump-sum agreements to become a victim-centred and individual-oriented process. Drawing on developments in the various fields of international law, his assessment is that an individual right to reparation did indeed emerge in the 1990s. According to Furuya, however, the abstract question about the existence of such a right is not particularly helpful: ‘[F]rom a practical point of view, the substantive right to reparation would be mere “pie in the sky” without the procedural right to access an effective reparation mechanism.’Footnote 66
Accordingly, Furuya’s particular focus rests on how a right to reparation can and should be practically implemented. Based on his analyses of reparation mechanisms established in international human rights bodies and before international criminal tribunals, and various ad hoc international reparation mechanisms established since the early 1990s, Furuya sets out the elements of the right to reparation. According to Furuya, this right entails substantive, as well as procedural, elements. The concrete content of the right to reparation has to be defined under specific historical circumstances, taking into account the specific challenges of concrete post-conflict constellations. This requires interlinking substantive and procedural aspects. In other words, the substance of a right to reparation will be defined only as the result of an adequate procedure. For that reason, the core contribution of Furuya’s chapter is the identification and elaboration of the substantive, as well as procedural, elements of the right to reparation that international reparation mechanisms have to implement.
The Trialogue’s second author, Cristián Correa, is a Chilean and US-trained lawyer who serves as a senior expert for the International Center for Transitional Justice, a non-governmental organisation based in New York City. In this capacity, Correa has provided advice and technical assistance on the creation and implementation of reparation programmes to governments, as well as civil society and victims’ organisations, in numerous countries, particularly in South America, Africa, and Asia. Previously, Correa was legal adviser for a commission of the Presidency of Chile responsible for identifying the ‘disappeared’ and defining a human rights policy. He further served as legal secretary for the Commission of Political Imprisonment and Torture of Chile (known as the Valech Commission).
In answering the Trialogue’s first question on the existence of an individual right to reparation, Cristián Correa takes a more cautious approach than Shuichi Furuya. While he acknowledges the legal practice of awarding reparation under international human rights law, he is more sceptical about whether a general right to reparation has emerged within IHL, particularly in view of opposing decisions of domestic courts. More promising, as Correa points out, is the avenue of international human rights law, which is generally applicable also to armed conflict and therefore can provide the legal tools to implement the right to reparation for victims of armed conflict.
The gist of Correa’s chapter, however, is a comprehensive analysis of practices of awarding reparation occurring not at the international level but within domestic reparation programmes. Thus Correa’s focus rests on answering the second question. He shows that the international legal debate has a lot to learn from domestic experiences, particularly because domestic programmes have been at the forefront in providing a comprehensive answer to mass violations of human rights and IHL during armed conflicts. While international human rights law places its focus on the individual victim, Correa shows that post-conflict societies benefit from establishment of comprehensive reparation programmes capable of dealing with large numbers of victims. This reorientation, however, necessitates an adjustment to the legal principles upon which reparation can be awarded to victims of armed conflict. Based on analysis of domestic reparation programmes, Correa draws a set of conclusions in answer to the third question about the content of the right to reparation regarding, inter alia, the types of violation and the victims that should be included in reparation programmes, the registration process, evidentiary standards, budgetary planning, and the concrete content of reparation awards, as well as in regard to implementation measures.
The Trialogue’s third author is Clara Sandoval. Clara Sandoval is originally from Colombia and is a professor at the School of Law and Human Rights Centre at the University of Essex, as well as a co-director of the Essex Transitional Justice Network in the UK. Her research focuses on human rights, particularly on the implementation of reparation mechanisms in transitional justice environments. Additionally, she has served as an expert before international tribunals such as the ICC and the IACtHR. She has also worked as a consultant for various UN bodies dealing with reparation for victims of mass atrocities. In this volume, Sandoval follows the approach towards operationalising victims’ right to reparation that her co-authors pursue. She focuses on the case law of international human rights bodies, particularly the IACtHR and the ECtHR (as the international bodies with the most extensive jurisprudence on reparation). Her chapter addresses the interplay of different legal mechanisms for awarding reparation – namely, the involvement of domestic reparation programmes (which Correa has identified and presented as an important and often effective way of awarding reparation), on the one hand, and international bodies such as the IACtHR and ECtHR, on the other. An analysis of practice shows that the reparation awards granted by domestic reparation programmes are, in many cases, less substantive – in that they provide less compensation than an international human rights court would usually provide. This raises the question of the interplay between these different levels of awarding reparation.
In a careful and pointed analysis of the jurisprudence of the IACtHR and ECtHR on reparation, Sandoval shows how this interplay is regulated by the principle of subsidiarity. Both courts give leeway – Sandoval also speaks of ‘qualified deference’Footnote 67 – to States regarding how they design and implement reparation. This is necessary to pay respect to differing concrete circumstances, but it is also problematic because States may use an under-ambitious and deficient domestic reparation programme to shield themselves from reparation awards issued by an international human rights court. Sandoval presents a solution to this problem: she suggests a two-pronged test for international bodies, on the basis of which they should decide whether a specific domestic reparation programme is in accordance with States’ obligations under international law. First, and under what Sandoval describes as the ‘international law test’, States must fulfil certain minimum core obligations. Once this minimum level is respected, the second test – the ‘public policy test’ – is meant to determine whether States have struck a reasonable balance between victims’ right to reparation and other concerns based on public policy.
It seems that the debate on the right to reparation for victims of armed conflict has been stuck for some time now. It is hoped that the three chapters of this Trialogue, as well as Anne Peters’ concluding reflections, will offer some lead on how this situation might be overcome and on how the much-needed right to reparation for victims of armed conflict could eventually become reality.