Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T22:44:17.462Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Appendix II - The Philosophical Background

David Gillis
Affiliation:
Tel Aviv
Get access

Summary

Outline of Neoplatonism

The school of thought known as Neoplatonism arose in Rome in the third century ce. It is so called because it represents a return, with modifications, to the doctrines of Plato after his pupil Aristotle's rejection of them. Plotinus, who studied philosophy in Alexandria and arrived in Rome in about 244, is generally considered to be the first and foremost figure of the school. His pupil Porphyry collected and edited his writings, and between 300 and 305 published them as the Enneads. Aristotle, it is worth recalling, died in 322 bce, so that the interval between him and Plotinus is five and a half centuries.

In the Islamic world Plotinus was hardly known by name. Parts of the Enneads circulated in Arabic paraphrases, such as The Theology of Aristotle.The medieval Islamic philosophers attributed this and other versions of Plotinus’ works to Aristotle, and tend to amalgamate the thought of both of them in their metaphysics. Whether or not Maimonides read The Theology of Aristotle or any similar work is not known for sure. Herbert Davidson detects no reference or allusion to such works in the Guide. Alfred Ivry, on the other hand, states forthrightly, on the basis of a comparison of some of the teachings of the Guide with those of the Enneads, that ‘The striking parallels that emerge offer persuasive evidence that this text, originally in Greek, had considerable influence in its Arabic versions upon Maimonides’ thinking, directly as well as indirectly, and that it is a major source of Maimonides’ philosophy.’ At any rate, familiarity with Neoplatonic ideas was guaranteed by Maimonides’ reading of Alfarabi and Avicenna, whose writings contain a noted Neoplatonic strain, and also through his knowledge of Ismaili writings.

Aristotle differed from Plato on the status of universals, that is, properties such as ‘chair-ness’, ‘humanity’, ‘right-angled triangle’. Plato was a realist, holding that universals really exist as ideal Forms, and that the chairs, human beings, and right-angled triangles we see are but imperfect copies of the Forms. Aristotle held form to be immanent in matter, inseparable from it but distinguishable in the mind. Both these philosophers considered knowledge to be the perception of form, but whereas for Plato this ultimately meant seeing beyond material existence to the realm of the Forms, for Aristotle it meant extracting form from matter;

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Liverpool University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×