Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T13:36:57.015Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2023

Paul Weithman
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abramowitz, Alan. 2018. The Great Alignment. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Acemoglu, Daron, and Robinson, James A. 2006. Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Achen, Chris, and Bartels, Larry. 2016. Democracy for Realists. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvey, James E. 2011. “James M. Buchanan on the Ethics of Public Debt and Default.” The Journal of Markets & Morality 14: 85101.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. “What Is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109: 287337.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2008. “How Should Egalitarians Cope with Market Risks?Theoretical Inquiries in Law 9: 6192.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2012. “The Fundamental Disagreement between Luck Egalitarians and Relational Egalitarians.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy S36: 123.Google Scholar
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2010. The Ethics of Identity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas. 1947 [c. 1260–73]. Summa Theologiae, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province. New York: Benziger Brothers.Google Scholar
Aristotle, . 2019 [350 bce]. Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Irwin, T., 3rd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Augustine, . 2004 [426]. City of God, trans. Bettenson, Henry. London: Penguin Classics.Google Scholar
Baier, Annette. 1985. Postures of the Mind: Essays on Mind and Morals. Minneapolis. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Bastiat, Frédéric. 1995. “Protectionism and Communism.” In Huszar, George (ed.), Cain, Seymour (trans.), Selected Essays on Political Economy. Irvington-on-Hudson. Foundation for Economic Education, 194228.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 1990. Political Equality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, Stephanie. 2000. “Do Taxes and Bonds Finance Government Spending?Journal of Economic Issues 34: 603–20.Google Scholar
Berman, Sheri. 2006. The Primacy of Politics: Social Democracy and the Making of Europe’s Twentieth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bok, P. MacKenzie. 2017. “To the Mountaintop Again: The Early Rawls and Post-Protestant Ethics in Postwar America.” Modern Intellectual History 14: 153–85.Google Scholar
Boxill, Bernard R. 1992. Blacks and Social Justice, rev. ed. Lanham, MD. Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Boxill, Bernard R. 2003. “A Lockean Argument for Black Reparations.” The Journal of Ethics 7, no. 1: 6391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, Jason. 2016. Against Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2017.Google Scholar
Broadwalter, Luke. 2012. “Wells Fargo Agrees to Pay $175M Settlement in Pricing Discrimination Suit,” Baltimore Sun, July 12. www.baltimoresun.com/news/bs-xpm-2012-07-12-bs-md-ci-wells-fargo-20120712-story.html.Google Scholar
Brown, Alexander. 2015. “Principles of Stakes Fairness in Sport.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 14: 135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brudney, Daniel. 1997. “Community and Completion.” In Reath, Andrews, Herman, Barbara, and Korsgaard, Christine (eds.), Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 388418.Google Scholar
Brudney, Daniel. 1998. Marx’s Attempt to Leave Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brudney, Daniel. 2001. “Justifying a Conception of the Good Life: The Problem of the 1844 Marx.” Political Theory 29: 364–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brudney, Daniel. 2010. “Producing for Others.” In Zurn, Christopher and Schmidt am Busch, Hans-Christoph (eds.), The Philosophy of Recognition: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 151–88.Google Scholar
Brudney, Daniel. 2014. “The Young Marx and the Middle-Aged Rawls.” In Mandel, Jon and Reidy, David (eds.), A Companion to Rawls. Chichester; West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell, 450–71.Google Scholar
Bruni, Luigino, and Sugden, Robert. 2008. “Fraternity: Why the Market Need Not Be a Morally Free Zone.” Economics and Philosophy 24: 3564.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1990. “Justice as Reciprocity versus Subject-Centered Justice.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 19: 227–52.Google Scholar
Buchanan, James, and Tullock, Gordon. 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Burke, Edmund. 1999 [1800]. “Thoughts and Details on Scarcity.” In Canavan, Francis (ed.), Select Works of Edmund Burke, vol. 4. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc. 2014. 573 U.S. 682.Google Scholar
Carcieri, Martin D. 2010. “Rawls and Reparations.” Michigan Journal of Race and Law 15: 267316.Google Scholar
Catholic Church. 2012. Catechism of the Catholic Church. Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana. https://penandthepad.com/cite-catholic-catechism-7852709.html.Google Scholar
Clark, John Bates. 1899. The Distribution of Wealth: A Theory of Wages, Interest and Profits. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Clark, Kenneth B. 1989. Dark Ghetto: Dilemmas of Social Power, 2nd ed. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2001. “Facts and Principles.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 31: 211–45.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Curley, Edwin. 1994. Introduction to Hobbes’s Leviathan with Selected Variants from the Latin Edition of 1668. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
D’Agostino, Fred. 1996. Free Public Reason: Making It up as We Go. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
D’Agostino, Fred. 2010. Naturalizing Epistemology: Thomas Kuhn and the Essential Tension. London: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Daniels, Norman (ed.). 1975. Reading Rawls: Critical Studies on Rawls’ “A Theory of Justice.” Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Darby, Derrick. 2010. “Reparations and Racial Inequality.” Philosophy Compass 5: 5566.Google Scholar
Darity, William A. Jr., and Mullen, A. Kirsten. 2020. From Here to Equality: Reparations for Black Americans in the Twenty-First Century. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 1977. “Two Kinds of Respect.” Ethics 88: 3649.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2002a. Contractarianism/Contractualism. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2002b. Welfare and Rational Care. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2013a. Morality, Authority, and Law: Essays in Second-Personal Ethics I. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2013b. Honor, History, and Relationship: Essays in Second-Personal Ethics II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2016. “Making the ‘Hard’ Problem of Moral Normativity Easier.” In Lord, Erroll and Maguire, Barry (eds.), Weighing Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2018. “Contempt as an Other-Characterizing, ‘Hierarchizing’ Attitude.” In Mason, Michelle (ed.), The Moral Psychology of Contempt. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2019. “What Are Moral Reasons?,” The 2017 Amherst Lecture in Philosophy. www.amherstlecture.org/darwall2017/index.html.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. Forthcoming. “Commanding Reasons and ‘Commands of Reason’: Kant on Moral Obligation.” In Bacin, Stefano and Sensen, Oliver (eds.), Kant’s Moral Philosophy in Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Diamond, Cora. 1991. “The Importance of Being Human.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 29: 3562.Google Scholar
Dietsch, Peter. 2021. “Money Creation, Debt, and Justice.” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 20: 151–79.Google Scholar
Dreben, Burton. 2003. “On Rawls and Political Liberalism.” In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 316–46.Google Scholar
Du Bois, W. E. B. 1920. Darkwater: Voices from Within the Veil. New York: Washington Square Press.Google Scholar
DuBois, W. E. B. 2009 [1903].The Souls of Black Folk (ed.), Edwards, Brent Hayes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, 1981. “What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 10: 283345.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 2000. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Eberle, Christopher. 2002. Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Edmundson, William. 2017. John Rawls: Reticent Socialist. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Employment Division, Department of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith. 1990. 494 U.S. 872.Google Scholar
Engels, Friedrich 1975 [1845]. The Condition of the Working Class in England. In Marx-Engels Collected Works, vol. 4, 295–583.Google Scholar
Enoch, David. 2013. “The Disorder of Public Reason.” Ethics 124: 141–76.Google Scholar
Enoch, David. 2015. “Against Public Reason.” In Sobel, David, Vallentyne, Peter, and Wall, Steven (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 112–44.Google Scholar
Espindola, Juan, and Vaca, Moises. 2014. “The Problem of Historical Rectification for Rawlsian Theory.” Res Publica 20: 227–43.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2003. “The Democracy/Contractualism Analogy.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 31: 387412.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2008. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2011. “Replies to Commentators.” Ethics 121: 354–89.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2015. “G. A. Cohen’s Critique of the Original Position.” In Hinton, Timothy (ed.), The Original Position. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 139–58.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 2020. Utopophobia. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Estlund, David. Unpublished. “What’s Unjust About Structural Injustice?”Google Scholar
Fiorina, Morris. 2017. Unstable Majorities: Polarization, Party Sorting, and Political Stalemate. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.Google Scholar
Fleischacker, Samuel. 2004. A Short History of Distributive Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Forrester, Katrina. 2019. In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2002. Contexts of Justice: Political Philosophy Beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism, trans. Farrell, J.. Berkeley; Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2011. The Right to Justification: Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice, trans. Flynn, J.. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2013. Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present, trans. Cronin, C.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Forst, Rainer. 2017. “Political Liberalism: A Kantian View.” Ethics 128: 123–44.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1978. The History of Sexuality, Vol. 1: An Introduction, trans. Hurley, Robert. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1983. “The Subject and Power.” In Dreyfus, Herbert L. and Rabinow, Paul (eds.), Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Frankena, William. 1963. Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel (ed.). 2002. The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel. 2003. “John Rawls: An Overview.” In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 159.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel. 2007. Rawls. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel. 2013. “Property-Owning Democracy and the Difference Principle.” Analyse & Kritik 35: 936.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fried, Barbara H. 1998. The Progressive Assault on Laissez Faire: Robert Hale and the First Law and Economics Movement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1947. “Lerner on the Economics of Control.” Journal of Political Economy 55: 405–16.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1948. “A Monetary and Fiscal Framework for Economic Stability.” American Economic Review 38: 245–64.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1968. “The Role of Monetary Policy.” The American Economic Review 58: 117Google Scholar
Fukuyama, Francis. 2014. Political Order and Political Decay. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Fulton v. City of Philadelphia. 2021. 593 U.S. ___ (2021)Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 1986. “Subjective Value and Justificatory Political Theory.” Nomos 28: 241–69.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 1990. Value and Justification: The Foundations of Liberal Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 1996. Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 2011a. The Order of Public Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 2011b. “A Tale of Two Sets: Public Reason in Equilibrium.” Public Affairs Quarterly 25: 305–25.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 2016. The Tyranny of the Ideal: Justice in a Diverse Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 2018. “The Complexity of a Diverse Moral Order.” Georgetown Journal of Law and Public Policy 16: 645–80.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. 2021. The Open Society and Its Complexities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald, and Van Schoelandt, Chad. 2017. “Consensus on What? Convergence for What? Four Models of Political Liberalism.” Ethics 128: 145–72.Google Scholar
Gauthier, David 1969. The Logic of Leviathan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, David 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
George, Henry. 1912. Progress and Poverty: An Inquiry into the Cause of Industrial Depressions and of Increase of Want with Increase of Wealth: The Remedy. Garden City, NJ: Doubleday, Page & Co.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1999. “Morality as Consistency in Living: Korsgaard’s Kantian Lectures.” Ethics 110: 140–64.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin, and Kim, Jaegwon (eds.). 1979. Values and Morals: Essays in Honor of William Frankena, Charles Stevenson, and Richard Brandt. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Godley, Wynne, and Lavoie, Marc. 2006. Monetary Economics: An Integrated Approach to Credit, Money, Income, Production and Wealth. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Esping-Anderson, Gøsta. 1990. The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Greenwald, Daniel, Lettau, Martin, and Ludvigson, Sydney. 2021. “How the Wealth Was Won: Factors Shares as Market Fundamentals,” NBER Working Paper 25769. www.nber.org/system/files/working_papers/w25769/w25769.pdf.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1998. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. Rehg, William. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stephen, Haggard, and Kaufman, Robert. 2021. Backsliding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hampton, Jean. 1986. Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harsanyi, John. 1955. “Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility.” Journal of Political Economy 63: 309–21.Google Scholar
Haslanger, Sally. 2012. Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. 1991 [1820]. Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, Renee A. 2002. “Compensatory Justice: Over Time and Between Groups.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 10: 392415.Google Scholar
Hinton, Timothy (ed.). 2015. The Original Position. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1839 [1656]. Six Lessons to the Savilian Professors of the Mathematics. In The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. VII. (ed.), J. Bohn.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1985 [1651]. Leviathan (ed.), Macpherson, C. B.. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1990 [1681]. Behemoth or The Long Parliament. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hobson, John. 1891. “The Law of Three Rents.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 5: 263–88.Google Scholar
Hobson, John. 1909. The Industrial System: An Inquiry into Earned and Unearned Income. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
Hocket, Robert. 2013. “Bretton Woods 1.0: A Constructive Retrieval for Sustainable Finance.” Cornell Law Faculty Publications 921. https://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/facpub/921.Google Scholar
Hockett, Robert. 2021. “The Once and Future Fed – And Treasury: From Credit Modulo-Allocative Separation to Re-Consolidation.” https://ssrn.com/abstract=3808792.Google Scholar
Hockett, Robert, and Omarova, Saule T. 2017. “The Finance Franchise.” Cornell Law Review 102: 11431218.Google Scholar
Hockett, Robert, and James, Aaron. 2020. Money from Nothing: Or Why We Should Learn to Stop Worrying about Debt and Love the Federal Reserve. New York: Melville House Press.Google Scholar
Hodgskin, Thomas. 1825. Labour Defended against the Claims of Capital: Or, the Unproductiveness of Capital Proved with Reference to the Present Combinations Amongst Journeymen. London: Knight and Lacey.Google Scholar
Hohfeld, Wesley. 1919. Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Legal Reasoning. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1978 [1739]. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed., Selby-Bigge, L. A. (ed.), with text revised and notes by Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1987 [1741]. “Of the First Principles of Government.” In Essays Moral and Political. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 3236.Google Scholar
Hussain, Waheed. 2020. “Pitting People against Each Other.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 48: 79113.Google Scholar
Irwin, Terence. 1990. “The Good of Political Activity.” In Patzig, Günther (ed.), Aristoteles’ Politik. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 7398.Google Scholar
James, Aaron. 2005. “Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status Quo.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 33: 281316.Google Scholar
James, Aaron. (2022) “What Trade’s Pioneers Missed: Money.” Moral Philosophy and Politics 9 no. 1: 89106.Google Scholar
Kandiyali, Jan. 2020. “The Importance of Others: Marx on Unalienated Production.” Ethics 130: 555–87.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1965 [1797]. The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, trans. Ladd, John. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1991 [1797]. The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Gregor, Mary. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1996 [1788]. Critique of Practical Reason, in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Gregor, Mary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, Erin. 2017. “The Historical Justice Problem for Political Liberalism.” Ethics 128: 7594.Google Scholar
Keynes, J. M. 1930. A Treatise on Money. London: Macmillan & Co.Google Scholar
Keynes, J.M. 1933. “A Monetary Theory of Production.” www.hetwebsite.net/het/texts/keynes/keynes1933mtp.htm.Google Scholar
King, Martin Luther Jr. 1961. “The Time for Freedom Has Come.” The New York Times. September 10.Google Scholar
King, Martin Luther Jr. 1963. “Letter from a Birmingham Jail.” Philadelphia: American Friends Service Committee.Google Scholar
King, Martin Luther Jr. 1964. “Letter from a Birmingham Jail.” Why We Can’t Wait. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
King, Martin Luther Jr. 1967. “Where Are We?” In Where Do We Go From Here: Chaos or Community? Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 122.Google Scholar
Kloppenberg, James T. 1986. Uncertain Victory: Social Democracy and Progressivism in European and American Thought, 1870–1920. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Krishnamurthy, Meena. 2013. “Completing Rawls’s arguments for equal political liberty and its fair value: the argument from self-respect.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43: 179205.Google Scholar
Kutz, Christopher. 2004. “Justice in Reparations: The Cost of Memory and the Value of Talk.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 32: 277312.Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles. 1987. Patterns of Moral Complexity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, Charles. 2008. The Autonomy of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Laurence, Ben. 2021. Agents of Change: Political Philosophy in Practice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lawford-Smith, Holly. 2010. “Debate: Ideal Theory – A Reply to Valentini.” Journal of Political Philosophy 18: 357–68.Google Scholar
Lee, Trymaine. 2019. “A Vast Wealth Gap, Driven by Segregation, Redlining, Evictions and Exclusion Separates Black and White America.” New York Times Magazine. August 14. www.nytimes.com/interactive/2019/08/14/magazine/racial-wealth-gap.html.Google Scholar
Lerner, Abba. 1941. “The Economic Steering Wheel.” The University Review 7: 257–63.Google Scholar
Lerner, Abba. 1943. “Functional Finance and the Federal Debt.” Social Research 10: 3851.Google Scholar
Lerner, Abba. 1944. The Economics of Control. New York: Kelley.Google Scholar
List, Christian, and Pettit, Phillip. 2013. Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
List, Christian, and Valentini, Laura. 2016. “The Methodology of Political Theory.” In Cappelen, Herman, Gendler, Tamar, and Hawthorne, John (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 525–53.Google Scholar
Little, Daniel. 2014. “Rawls and Economics.” In Mandle, Jon and Reidy, David (eds.), A Companion to Rawls. Sussex: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
Little Sisters of the Poor Saints Peter and Paul Home v. Pennsylvania. 2020. 591 U.S. ___.Google Scholar
Lloyd, S.A. 1992. Ideals as Interests in Hobbes’s Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, S. A. 2009. Morality in the Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes: Cases in the Law of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, S. A. 2020. “All the Mind’s Pleasure: Glory, Self-Admiration, and Moral Motivation in On the Citizen and Leviathan.” In Douglass, Robin and Olsthoorn, John, (eds.), Hobbes’s On the Citizen: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 5170.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 1959 [1689]. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Fraser, A. C. (ed.). New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 1983 [1689]. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Tully, James H. (ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Lukács, Georg. 1972. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, trans. Livingstone, Rodney. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lukes, Steven. 2018. “‘Getting and Spending, We Lay Waste Our Powers’: On the Expanding Reach of the Market.” In Melzer, Arthur M. and Kautz, Steven J. (eds.), Are Markets Moral?. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 6884.Google Scholar
Lyons, David. 2013. Confronting Injustice: Moral History and Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1994A Partial Response to My Critics.” In Horton, John and Mendus, Susan (eds.), After MacIntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair MacIntyre. South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, Catharine. 1989. Toward a Feminist Theory of the State. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Marglin, Stephen A. 2021. Raising Keynes: A Twenty-First Century General Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mason, Liliana. 2018. Uncivil Agreement: How Politics Became Our Identity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission. 2018. 584 U.S. __.Google Scholar
Martin, Rex. 2014. “Overlapping Consensus.” In Mandel, Jon and Reidy, David (eds.) A Companion to Rawls. Sussex: Wiley Blackwell, 281–96.Google Scholar
Martinich, A. P. 2021. Hobbes’s Political Philosophy: Interpretation and Interpretations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1967 [1867]. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. New York: International.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1973 [1857]. Grundrisse, trans. Nicolaus, Martin. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1975a [1844]. “Comments on James Mill.” In Marx-Engels Collected Works, vol. 3, 211–28.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1975b [1844]. “Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844.” In Marx-Engels Collected Works, vol. 3, 229348.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1989 [1875]. “The Critique of the Gotha Programme.” In Marx-Engels Collected Works, vol. 24, 7576.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl, and Engels, Friedrich. 1975–. Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW), New York: International.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl, and Engels, Friedrich. 1976 [1845]. “The German Ideology.” In Marx-Engels Collected Works, vol. 5, 4243.Google Scholar
McAward, Jennifer Mason. 2012. “Defining the Badges and Incidents of Slavery.” Journal of Constitutional Law 14: 561630.Google Scholar
McCarthy, Thomas. 2004. “Political Philosophy and Racial Injustice: From Normative to Critical Theory.” In Benhabib, Seyla and Fraser, Nancy (eds.), Pragmatism, Critique, Judgment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 147–68.Google Scholar
McCarty, Nolan. 2019. Polarization: What Everyone Needs to Know. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McConnell, Michael. 1990. “The Origins and Historical Understanding of Free Exercise of Religion.” Harvard Law Review 103: 14091519.Google Scholar
McDaniel, W. Caleb. 2019. Sweet Taste of Liberty: A True Story of Slavery and Restitution in America. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McDermott, Daniel. 2008. “Analytic Political Philosophy.” In Leopold, David and Stears, Marc (eds.), Political Theory: Methods and Approaches. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1128.Google Scholar
McGary, Howard. 1999. Race and Social Justice. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McGary, Howard. 2010. “Reconciliation and Reparations.” Metaphilosophy 41: 546–62.Google Scholar
Meade, James. 1965. Efficiency, Equality and the Ownership of Property. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mehrling, Perry. 2014. “MIT and Money.” History of Political Economy 46: 177–97.Google Scholar
Mehrling, Perry. 2019. “The Monetary Education of John Hicks.” In Roselli, Annalisa, Naldi, Nerio, and Sanfilippo, Eleonora (eds.), Money, Finance and Crises in Economic History. London: Routledge, 107–16.Google Scholar
Meyer, Lukas H. 2006. “Reparations and Symbolic Restitution.” Journal of Social Philosophy 37: 406–22.Google Scholar
Milanovic, Branko. 2016. Global Inequality: A New Approach for the Age of Globalization. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1979 [1861]. Utilitarianism. Sheer, George (ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1861. Considerations on Representative Government. London: Parker, Son & Bourn.Google Scholar
Miller, J. Joseph. 2003. “J. S. Mill on Plural Voting, Competence and Participation.” History of Political Thought 24: 647–67.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 1997. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2003. “White Supremacy as a Sociopolitical System.” In Mills, Charles W. (ed.), From Class to Race: Essays in White Marxism and Black Radicalism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 177–94.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2005. “Ideal Theory as Ideology.” Hypatia, 20: 165–83.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2007. “Contract of Breach: Repairing the Racial Contract.” In Pateman, Carole and Mills, Charles W. (eds.), Contract and Domination. Cambridge, MA: Polity Press, 106–33.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2017a. “Racial Liberalism.” In Black Rights/White Wrongs: The Critique of Racial Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2848.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2017b. Black Rights/White Wrongs: The Critique of Racial Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W.Epilogue (As Prologue): Towards a Black Radical Liberalism.” In Black Rights/White Wrongs: The Critique of Racial Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 201–16.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W., and Flikschuh, Katrin. 2018. “Racial Justice.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume XCII: 6989.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2018. “Through a Glass, Whitely: Ideal Theory as Epistemic Injustice.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 92: 4377.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. “Theorizing Racial Justice.” https://tannerlectures.utah.edu/MILLSTANNERLECTURE.pdfGoogle Scholar
Mizruchi, Mark S. 2013. The Fracturing of the American Corporate Elite. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, Barrington, 1966. Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of the Modern World. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Mulligan, Thomas. 2018. “Plural Voting for the Twenty-First Century.” Philosophical Quarterly 68: 286306.Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris. 1985. The Sovereignty of Good. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Murphy, Colleen. The Conceptual Foundations of Transitional Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017.Google Scholar
Murphy, Liam, and Nagel, Thomas. 2002. The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1973. “Rawls on Justice.” The Philosophical Review 82: 220–34.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 2005. “The Problem of Global Justice.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 33: 114–47.Google Scholar
Nelson, Eric. 2019. The Theology of Liberalism: Political Philosophy and the Justice of God. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Ockham, William of. 1495. Quaestiones et decisiones in quattuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi. Lyon.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Martin, and Williamson, Thad. 2012a. “The Promise of Predistribution.” Published online by Policy Network. www.policy-network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=4262&title=The-Promise-of-Pre-distribution.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Martin, and Williamson, Thad (eds.). 2012. Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora. 1987. “Abstraction, Idealization and Ideology in Ethics.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 22: 5569.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora. 1996. Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paine, Thomas. 1792. Rights of Man. Part the Second. Combining Principle and Practice. London: H. D. Symonds.Google Scholar
Paine, Thomas. 1796. “Agrarian Justice.” www.ssa.gov/history/paine4.html.Google Scholar
Pallikkathayil, Japa. 2017. “Persons and Bodies.” In Kisilevsky, Sari and Stone, Martin J. (eds.), Freedom and Force: Essays on Kant’s Legal Philosophy. Oxford: Hart, 3554.Google Scholar
Pallikkathayil, Japa. 2019. “Disagreement and the Duties of Citizenship.” American Philosophical Quarterly 56: 7182.Google Scholar
Derek, Parfit. 1973. “Later Selves and Moral Principles.” In Montefiore, Alan (ed.), Philosophy and Personal Relations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 137–69.Google Scholar
Pettit, Phillip. 1997. Republicanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Phillips, Jack. 2018. “I’m the Masterpiece Cakeshop Baker. Will the Supreme Court Uphold My Freedom?” The Washington Post, April 26.Google Scholar
Piketty, Thomas. 2014. CAPITAL in the Twenty-First Century, trans. Goldhammer, Arthur. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Pinkard, Terry. 2017. Does History Make Sense? Hegel on the Historical Shapes of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Plato. 1992 [c. 375 bce]. Republic, trans. Grube, G. M. A., rev. Reeve, C. D. C.. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. 2002. “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?” in McAdam, Jim (ed.), Moral Writings. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 720.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quong, Jonathan. 2011. Liberalism without Perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reidy, David A. 2014. “From Philosophical Theology to Democratic Theory.” In Mandle, Jon and Reidy, David (eds.), A Companion to Rawls. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 930.Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry S. 2021. “Taking Multidimensionality Seriously: Capabilities, Rawls’s Primary Goods and Guiding Action.” In Chiappero-Martinetti, Enrica, Osmani, Siddiqur, and Qizilbash, Mozaffar (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of the Capability Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 146–64.Google Scholar
Ripstein, Arthur. 2009. Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2012. “Care, Gender, and Property-Owning Democracy.” In O’Neill, Martin and Williamson, Thad (eds.), Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 163–79.Google Scholar
Rödl, Sebastian. 2007. Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenfeld, Sam. 2017. The Polarizers. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ruml, Beardsley. 1946. “Taxes for Revenue are Obsolete.” American Affairs VIII: 3539.Google Scholar
Ronzoni, Miriam. 2010. “Constructivism and Practical Reason: On Intersubjectivity, Abstraction, and Judgment.” Journal of Moral Philosophy 7: 74104.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997 [1762]. “Of the Social Contract.” In The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, trans. Gourevitch, Victor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 38155.Google Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2019 [1755]. “Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men.” In The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings, trans. Gourevitch, Victor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 111–88.Google Scholar
Samuelson, Paul. 1972. “Money, Interest Rates, and Economic Activity: Their Interrelationship in a Market Economy.” In Merton, Robert C. (ed.), The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson, vol. 3. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 550–70.Google Scholar
Samuelson, Paul. 2014. Interview with Mark Blaug in his film, “John Maynard Keynes: Life/Ideas/Legacy,” selection at www.youtube.com/watch?v=4_pasHodJ-8.Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2016. “How Practices Matter.” Journal of Political Philosophy 24: 323.Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael. 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael. 1984. “The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self.” Political Theory 12: 8196.Google Scholar
Sandel, Michal. 2020. The Tyranny of Merit: What’s Become of the Common Good? New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T.M. 2003a. “Rawls on Justification.” In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2003b. “The Difficulty of Tolerance.” In The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays in Moral and Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 187201.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2008. Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2018. Why Does Inequality Matter? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 1979. “Moral Independence and the Original Position.” Philosophical Studies 35: 397403.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 2018. “Membership and Obligation.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 26: 323.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 2019. “The Rawlsian Diagnosis of Donald Trump.” Boston Review, February 1.Google Scholar
Schultz-Bergin, Marcus. 2021. “Does Convergence Liberalism Risk Anarchy?Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 20 no. 1. www.jesp.org/index.php/jesp/article/view/1072.Google Scholar
Schmidtz, David. 2002. “How to Deserve.” Political Theory 30: 774–99.Google Scholar
Schwartz, Adina. 1973. “Moral Neutrality and Primary Goods.” Ethics 83: 294307.Google Scholar
Schweickart, David. 2012. “Property-Owning Democracy or Economic Democracy?” In O’Neill, Martin and Williamson, Thad (eds.), Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 201–21.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya, and Williams, Bernard. 1982. Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Senior, Nassau. 1836. An Outline of the Science of Political Economy. London: W. Clowes and Sons.Google Scholar
Shelby, Tommie. 2004. “Race and Social Justice: Rawlsian Considerations.” Fordham Law Review 72: 16971714.Google Scholar
Shelby, Tommie. 2013. “Racial Realities and Corrective Justice: A Reply to Charles Mills.” Critical Philosophy of Race 1: 145–62.Google Scholar
Shelby, Tommie. 2016. Dark Ghettos: Injustice, Dissent, and Reform. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sher, George. 1979. “Effort, Ability, and Personal Desert.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 8: 361–76.Google Scholar
Sherbert v. Verner. 1963. 374 U.S. 398Google Scholar
Shiffrin, Seana Valentine. 2021. Democratic Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith. 1990. The Faces of Injustice. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1981 [1874]. The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John. 2010. “Ideal and Nonideal Theory.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 38: 536.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 1984. “The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives.” In Rorty, Richard, Schneewind, Jerome B., and Skinner, Quentin (eds.), Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 139222.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. 1869 [1759]. “The Theory of Moral Sentiments.” in The Essays of Adam Smith. London: Alex Murray, 9304.Google Scholar
Smith, Sophie, Bejan, Teresa M., and Zimmermann, Annette (eds.). 2021. The Historical Rawls (Special Forum), Modern Intellectual History 18, no. 4.Google Scholar
Spencer, Herbert. 1891. Principles of Ethics. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Spencer, Herbert. 1981. “The Coming Slavery.” In Mack, Eric (ed.), The Man versus the State, with Six Essays on Government, Society, and Freedom. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.Google Scholar
Spinner-Halev, Jeff. 2007. “From Historical to Enduring Injustice.” Political Theory 35: 574–97.Google Scholar
Stein, Ben. 2006. “In Class Warfare, Guess Which Class Is Winning.” New York Times, November 26. www.nytimes.com/2006/11/26/business/yourmoney/26every.html.Google Scholar
Stephen, James Fitzjames. 1992 [1873]. “Liberty, Equality, Fraternity.” In Liberty, Equality, Fraternity and Three Brief Essays. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 23282.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1962. “Freedom and Resentment.” Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 125.Google Scholar
Sumner, William Graham. 1911. What Social Classes Owe to Each Other. New York: Harper and Brothers.Google Scholar
Táíwò, Olúfẹmi O. 2019. “States Are Not Basic Structures: Against State-Centric Political Theory.” Philosophical Papers 48: 5982.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1985. “Atomism.” In Taylor, Charles (ed.), Philosophical Papers: Volume 2: Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 187210.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tebbe, Nelson. 2021a. “The Principle and Politics of Equal Value.” Columbia Law Review 121: 2397–482.Google Scholar
Tebbe, Nelson. 2021b. “The Principle and Politics of Liberty of Conscience.” Harvard Law Review 135: 267321Google Scholar
Teitelman, Michael. 1972. “The Limits of Individualism.” Journal of Philosophy 69: 545–56.Google Scholar
Terry, Brandon M. 2021. “Conscription and the Color Line: Rawls, Race, and Vietnam.” Modern Intellectual History 18: 960–83.Google Scholar
Thomas, Alan. 2017. Republic of Equals: Predistribution and Property-Owning Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thompson, Janna. 2001. “Historical Injustice and Reparation: Justifying Claims of Descendants.” Ethics 112: 114–35.Google Scholar
Thompson, William. 1827. Labor Rewarded. The Claims of Labor and Capital Conciliated: Or, How to Secure to Labor the Whole Product of Its Exertions, by One of the Idle Classes. London: Hunt and Clarke.Google Scholar
Tilly, Charles. 1999. Durable Inequality. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Tomasi, John. 2012. Free-Market Fairness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ture, Kwame (aka Stokely Carmichael), and Hamilton, Charles V. 1992. Black Power: The Politics of Liberation. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Turner, Piers Norris, and Gaus, Gerald (eds.). 2018. Public Reason in Political Philosophy: Classic Sources and Contemporary Controversies. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2009. “On the Apparent Paradox of Ideal Theory.” Journal of Political Philosophy 17: 332–55.Google Scholar
Valentini, Laura. 2016. “On the Messy Utopophobia vs Factophobia Controversy.” In Vallier, Kevin and Weber, Michael (eds.), Political Utopias. Oxford University Press, 1134.Google Scholar
Vallier, Kevin. 2018. “Public Justification.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justification-public/.Google Scholar
Vallier, Kevin. 2019. “Political Liberalism and the Radical Consequences of Justice Pluralism.” Journal of Social Philosophy 50: 212–31.Google Scholar
Vallier, Kevin. 2022. The Social Philosophy of Gerald Gaus: Moral Relations Amid Control, Contestation, and Complexity. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1–23. doi:10.1017/apa.2022.16.Google Scholar
Vallier, Kevin, and Muldoon, Ryan. 2021. “In Public Reason, Diversity Trumps Coherence.” Journal of Political Philosophy 29: 211–30.Google Scholar
Van ‘T Klooster, Jens. 2019. “Central Banking in Rawls’s Property-Owning Democracy.” Political Theory 47: 674–98.Google Scholar
Vincent, Michael. 2021. “A Sympathetic Critique of Gaus’s The Order of Public Reason.” A dissertation submitted to Brisbane: University of Queensland.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1992. “Superseding Historic Injustice.” Ethics 103: 428.Google Scholar
Walker, David. 2015 [1830]. David Walker’s Appeal in Four Articles. Mansfield Centre, CT: Martino.Google Scholar
Walker, Margaret Urban. 2006. “Restorative Justice and Reparation.” Journal of Social Philosophy 37: 377–95.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. 2019. The Moral Nexus. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, Alan, ed. 1998. The Digest of Justinian. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Wall, Steven. 2006. “Rawls and the Status of Political Liberty.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87: 245–70.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Webb, Sidney. 1888. “The Rate of Interest and the Laws of Distribution.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 2: 188208.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1978 [1921]. Roth, Guenther and Wittich, Claus (eds.), Economy and Society, vol. 2. Berkeley; Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1909. “Letter to Ferdinand Tönnies, February 19, 1909.” In Kloppenberg, James T.. 1986. Uncertain Victory: Social Democracy and Progressivism in European and American Thought, 1870–1920. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weithman, Paul. 2010. Why Political Liberalism? On John Rawls’s Political Turn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weithman, Paul. 2015. “Inclusivism, Stability, and Assurance.” In Bailey, Tom and Gentile, Valentina (eds.), Rawls and Religion. New York: Columbia University Press, 7596.Google Scholar
Weithman, Paul. 2016. “John Rawls and the Task of Political Philosophy.” In Weithman, Paul (ed.), Rawls, Political Liberalism and Reasonable Faith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2940.Google Scholar
Weithman, Paul. 2017. “Autonomy and Disagreement about Justice in Political Liberalism.” Ethics 128: 95122.Google Scholar
Wenar, Leif. 2006. “Reparations for the Future.” Journal of Social Philosophy 37: 396405.Google Scholar
White, Stuart. 2014. “Property-Owning Democracy and Republican Citizenship.” In O’Neill, Martin and Williamson, Thad (eds.), Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 129–44.Google Scholar
Wiens, David, and Ingham, Sean. 2021. “Demographic Objections to Epistocracy: A Generalization.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 49: 323–49.Google Scholar
Wilkins, Clara L., and Kaiser, Cheryl R. 2014. “Racial Progress as Threat to the Status Hierarchy: Implications for Perceptions of Anti-White Bias.” Psychological Science 25: 439–46.Google Scholar
Williams, Joan C. 2020. White Working Class: Overcoming Class Cluelessness in America. Boston: Harvard Business Review Press.Google Scholar
Wolff, Jonathan. 1998. “Fairness, Respect, and the Egalitarian Ethos.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 27: 97122.Google Scholar
Wray, L. Randall. 1988. Understanding Modern Money. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Wray, L. Randall. 2002. “A Monetary and Fiscal Framework for Economic Stability: A Friedmanian Approach to Restoring Growth.” dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1010174.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 2011a. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 2011b. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Edited by Paul Weithman, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: Rawls’s <i>A Theory of Justice</i> at 50
  • Online publication: 20 July 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009214704.025
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Edited by Paul Weithman, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: Rawls’s <i>A Theory of Justice</i> at 50
  • Online publication: 20 July 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009214704.025
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Edited by Paul Weithman, University of Notre Dame, Indiana
  • Book: Rawls’s <i>A Theory of Justice</i> at 50
  • Online publication: 20 July 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009214704.025
Available formats
×