Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T02:38:46.974Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part IV - Cognition in the psychology of science

Cognitive psychology of science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Barry Gholson
Affiliation:
Memphis State University
Eric G. Freedman
Affiliation:
Memphis State University
Arthur C. Houts
Affiliation:
Memphis State University
Get access

Summary

A major goal for the cognitive psychology of science is to provide a cognitive theory that can account for how the working practices of scientists lead to developments in scientific knowledge. In our view, such a theory should begin with an abstract model that provides an understanding of developments in science and specifies the events to be addressed. This first task involves some discussion and synthesis of recent work in the philosophy and history of science. The second task is to specify the working practices of scientists that lead to the events incorporated in the abstract model. Finally, the various practices must be understood in terms of a rigorous cognitive theory of psychology that can be empirically evaluated by conventional scientific methods.

During the past 25 years, a number of philosophers have presented postpositivist accounts of science and scientific change that have been quite influential in interdisciplinary science studies. These philosophers generally agree that the important overall units for understanding science, that is, for interpreting and analyzing scientific developments, are large-scale conceptual structures, variously referred to as paradigms (Kuhn, 1962), disciplinary matrixes (Kuhn, 1970), global theories (Feyerabend, 1975, 1981a, 1981b), research traditions (Laudan, 1977), guiding assumptions (Laudan et al., 1986), and research programs (Lakatos, 1970, 1978). In what follows we adopt the term “research program,” but this should not be taken as an endorsement of any particular philosophical position. Examples of research programs include Newtonian physics and behavioral psychology.

The abstract model outlined below is not completely representative of any previously articulated view.

Type
Chapter
Information
Psychology of Science
Contributions to Metascience
, pp. 267 - 274
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×