Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T17:38:04.392Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CHAPTER 8 - LINEAR TWO-SORTED ARITHMETIC

from Part 3 - Constructive logic and complexity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2012

Helmut Schwichtenberg
Affiliation:
Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität Munchen
Stanley S. Wainer
Affiliation:
University of Leeds
Get access

Summary

In this final chapter we focus much of the technical/logical work of previous chapters onto theories with limited (more feasible) computational strength. The initial motivation is the surprising result of Bellantoni and Cook [1992] characterizing the polynomial-time functions by the primitive recursion schemes, but with a judicially placed semicolon first used by Simmons [1988], separating the variables into two kinds (or sorts). The first “normal” kind controls the length of recursions, and the second “safe” kind marks the places where substitutions are allowed. Various alternative names have arisen for the two sorts of variables, which will play a fundamental role throughout this chapter, thus “normal”/“input” and “safe”/“output”; we shall use the input–output terminology. The important distinction here is that input and output variables will not just be of base type, but may be of arbitrary higher type.

We begin by developing a basic version of arithmetic which incorporates this variable separation. This theory EA(;) will have elementary recursive strength (hence the prefix E) and sub-elementary (polynomially bounded) strength when restricted to its Σ1-inductive fragment. EA(;) is a first-order theory which we use as a means to illustrate the underlying principles available in such two-sorted situations. Our aim however is to extend the Bellantoni and Cook variable separation to also incorporate higher types. This produces a theory A(;) extending EA(;) with higher type variables and quantifiers, having as its term system a two-sorted version T(;) of Gödel's T. T(;) will thus give a functional interpretation for A(;), which has the same elementary computational strength, but is more expressive and applicable.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×