Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T00:45:25.425Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 5 - Phrenitic People

Patients and Therapies in Imperial and Late-Antique Cultures (First–Sixth Centuries ce)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 November 2023

Chiara Thumiger
Affiliation:
Cluster of Excellence Roots, Christian-Albrechts Universität zu Kiel, Germany

Summary

Chapter 5 covers the clinical part of the account left to us by the medical authors of the imperial period: the case histories, pathological descriptions and clinical narratives as they appear in Anonymus Parisinus, Aretaeus and Galen, as well as the medical developments in the following centuries, which will proceed very much along the lines traced by Galen. This is illustrated by the late-antique sources included in the last section of the chapter: Oribasius, Aetius, Alexander of Tralles and Paul of Aegina. The topics analysed include patient profiling and behaviours; the topic of ‘neighbouring diseases’ and ‘similar diseases’ to phrenitis (pleuritis and pneumonia, but especially lethargos as cold brain fever, symmetrical to the hot brain fever which is phrenitis); and the recurring symptoms. These form a clear picture by now, featuring fever, sensorial disturbance, cognitive damage, various ‘neurological’ signs like (notably) 'flocillation' (the compulsive picking of hair or flocks from one's clothes and blankets), sleep disturbance, voice alteration, expectoration, a certain quality of the urine and pulse, respiratory issues, and a rich and varied psychological disturbance, where hallucination stands out.

Type
Chapter
Information
Phrenitis and the Pathology of the Mind in Western Medical Thought
(Fifth Century BCE to Twentieth Century CE)
, pp. 129 - 184
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

In the first centuries of our era, the doctrinal representation of our disease, along with many other medical ideas, tends to consolidate around the authority of Galen. Certain models of phrenitis become dominant in learned medicine: it is an affection of the brain with fever simultaneously involving other parts of the body, especially the chest, along the lines discussed in Chapter 4 through the examples of Aretaeus and Galen. These two authors, despite their differences, both foreground the brain as localization (Galen) and/or target of therapy (Aretaeus).Footnote 1 But other roads were taken and remained open alongside this main narrative, as a variety of voices outside official medicine show.Footnote 2

Doctrines discussing a disease in terms of physiological theory in any case tell only part of the story: a different, broader testimony is offered by the observations and reports of the lived manifestations of a physical illness and in the existence of patients. These documents produce a richer picture and offer us direct (if in their own way still problematic) access to the human beings who were flesh and blood to the physician’s annotations and diagnoses.Footnote 3 Apart from Galen, this clinical information is mostly to be extracted from nosological treatises from the early centuries of our era. Nosology as a genre – a list of diseases a capite ad calcem, roughly organized into sections addressing causes, description and therapy – represents a post-Hellenistic approach to pathology to which Galen belongs only marginally, even though his immense corpus of writing offers a great deal of information about clinical and nosological aspects. The fact that, as was partially apparent in the last chapter, phrenitis becomes obviously important in medical discussions at this time is reflected by the place it occupies in other nosological treatises: in addition to Aretaeus, Anonymus Parisinus and Caelius Aurelianus put it first in their lists (as did Celsus in his discussion of insaniaFootnote 4); medical authors seldom fail to mention it in representative catalogues of diseases;Footnote 5 and Galen, as already noted, repeatedly gives it exemplary status. Parallel to this, phrenitis becomes more visible among lay audiences, escaping the technical environment of medical treatises, as will be discussed in Chapter 6. In agreement with these trends, we might infer, phrenitis was in turn more frequently diagnosed and more closely observed in clinical terms, and generally more present in contemporary language and the public imagination.

I turn now to the medical information preserved by material from the first centuries of our era (first–seventh centuries ce), dividing the discussion into authors preceding and contemporary to Galen, and thus fundamentally independent of him, and those after Galen, who reflect the massive influence exerted by his doctrine, the ‘Galenism’ which shapes the discussion in medieval receptions of Graeco-Roman medicine.Footnote 6

Nosology in Practice: Anonymus Parisinus

Exemplary of the main trends in nosology as far as phrenitis is concerned is the Anonymus Parisinus (AP), a nosological text dated to around the first century ce, regarding the doxographic style and reliability of which caution is needed.Footnote 7 Much use was made of this author’s reports of classical and Hellenistic sources in Chapter 2, since he summarizes the views of his predecessors in his sections devoted to the ‘causes’ of each disease, including in our case (phrenitidos aitia). I turn now to this author’s assessment of signs (sēmeia) and therapy (therapeia) for phrenitis.

The disease phrenitis, first of all, is the first in the treatise and receives one of the longest discussions, confirming its localization in the head within the traditional organization a capite ad calcem, but also its primary relevance as mental disease and nosological concept tout court. As the anonymous author discusses the signs of the disease, he emphasizes continual fever (synechēs pyretos); a quick, small, thick pulse (sphygmos dediō[g]menos, smikros, pyknos); and continually shallow breathing (anapnoē synechizousa kai mē diistasa teleiōs thōraka) as somatic indicators – all these in line with the importance of the pulse as a diagnostic tool in this period (AP 1.1, 2.23–4.2 Garofalo).Footnote 8

The signs included by the Anonymous concerning mental health and vitality are ‘constant sleeplessness and trouble of the mind (agrypnia diēnekēs kai paraphora tēs dianoias)’, which are typical features. In addition, there are aspects with an ethical or personal quality: a patient may ‘sometimes get angry and savage and run outside (pote men orgizomenou kai agriainontos kai exō trechontos)’, while ‘at other times he is happy and sings, or lies down (pote de hilarou kai aidontos ē katakeimenou)’. These variations in mood as a result of illness were already described by Celsus and show the acquired power of the nosological label phrenitis as a container of subgroups and psychological variations.Footnote 9 In addition, patients might need to be reminded to drink, or might refuse to do so (1.2, 4.2–4 Garofalo), signs which indicate dryness, but also potentially a damaged awareness of bodily functions.

This treatise also mentions the well-known signs of crocydism and compulsive hand movements combined with hallucinatory delusions and groping, which are described in detail (‘raising his hands into the air, or pulling lint off robes, or picking at straws and pulling chaff from the wall and seeming to pluck hair, although catching nothing, as if groping about’). The worsening of the disease is revealed by exacerbating signs: chilled extremities, complete insomnia, delirium or silence (parakopē ē aposiōpesis), laughing or depression (gelōs ē katēpheia), red eyes that move rapidly and are full of tears. Patients collect lint (krokodyzousi). Their tongue lacks moisture, and their appetite may vary (orexis allois allē). When the danger becomes more acute, ‘the hypochondrion contracts and is pulled up (prosenteinetai kai anaspatai), the neck and face sweat, the belly exudes catarrh (koilia katarrei), the body trembles’. When the moment of death approaches, finally, patients ‘utter high-pitched screams, speak indistinctly (asaphē lalousi), stutter, their pulse weakens, and they have difficulty breathing and wheeze’ (1.3, 4.5–15 Garofalo).

None of the signs the Anonymous lists is new, as comparison of his text to some of those from the classical period makes clear. Alongside the familiar cognitive and behavioural features and the signs that can be explained as consequences of high fever, however, there is some development: an ethical and emotional component; the possibility of individual variation; the elements of pulse and respiration; an affection of the belly with catarrh; and a detailed sense of progressive exacerbation. Unlike in Celsus, in this account psychology remains subordinate, and one senses the underlying tension between caput (in the visible signs of the face and head: sweating, red eyes and so forth) and torso (the catarrh in the belly, the difficult breathing, the tense, elevated hypochondrium) as locations. But no clear choice is made between the two: ‘Consider these as a whole (tauta panta) signs of phrenitis’, the author writes (1.3, 4.16 Garofalo).

Therapeutic Measures

As for therapeutics, the range of remedies is composite and bears the signs of the anatomical tension between head and chest Galen will stigmatize as contradictory in the formulations of other doctors.Footnote 10 They can be summarized as psychotherapeutics; dietetic measures and other bodily interventions; and pharmacology.

Psychotherapeutics or soothing measures are the first to be mentioned by the Anonymus Parisinus, at the very beginning, and mostly match the directions found in Celsus, perhaps reflecting the same trend in approaching distress of a mental kind: to place patients in the light, dimming it if necessary (1.1, 4.18–21 Garofalo),Footnote 11 and most importantly, to calm them when they experience delirious fantasies (en de tais tōn parakopōn phantasiais) ‘with the help of words (tēi apo logou boētheiai)’ and persuasion (parēgorēsomen); to convince them that those around them are ‘friends, not enemies’; but also to rebuke them when necessary (hote de kai epiplēxomen). These details recall Celsus’ advice and must derive from a common source: one ought to gratify patients in various ways (synaresthentes), announcing unknown facts to them,Footnote 12 and bringing their wives and children or someone to whom they have an erotic attachment (ei de kai pros tinas erōtikōs echousin) into their presence (1.6, 6.16–24 Garofalo).

Also common to the measures recommended by Celsus and the Anonymous are restraining or coercing these patients, procedures classical medicine ignored (1.3, 8.22–10.2 Garofalo). When the disease worsens, frightening them (ekphobein) might be a necessary last resource, if patients become aggressive and violent, or misbehave more generally; when they pose a threat to others, whether physicians or family, ‘slaps and blows’ (rhapismois kai epiplēxesi) may be used. Only through physical restraint are these patients led to understanding and reason and calmed down (apodeiliōsi); otherwise ‘they will not understand (ou syneisousin ei mē sōmatikōs biasthōsi)’ – explicit early advocacy for a cognitive impact of physical intervention on patients’ bodies. That passive exercises such as the use of hammocks, in accord with individual strength and the state of sleep or delirium (1.3, 6.12–13 Garofalo), are also present, is part of the same ‘holistic’ approach, which aims at mental health qua psychological datum. There is also a class element at work here: bonds are more necessary for individuals of lower social provenience (slaves) than for those who lead an ‘honest, free life (epi tōn biou eleutherou kai katharou)’. The latter constitute a class of patients whom restraint would exacerbate rather than tame (1.3, 10.3–7 Garofalo). Holding them tightly by the hands and embracing them gently is recommended instead, a use of physical contact that recurs in late-antique physiological therapy as seen in nosological discussions of mental disorders.Footnote 13

These points all go in the same direction as the ethical approach testified to by Celsus, with cognitive, emotional and relational aspects inserted within the nosological picture. In addition, they expand the social frame to include children, wives, friends and lovers, as well as the controversial (and popular) feature of the erotic remedy, a topos in the early centuries of our era.Footnote 14 Class and ethical discriminations are also part of the patient’s profile and determine different therapies for different social statuses.

Somatic measures to be adopted include bleeding and purging (1.2, 4.22–5 Garofalo) and phlebotomy (1.3, 9–13 Garofalo). Fasting and dietetic specifics are also recommended (1.3, 6.1–3 Garofalo), including drinking honey-water to relax the stomach (1.3, 10.8–10 Garofalo), bathing and a restorative regimen after improvement has begun to be apparent (1.3, 8.9–13 Garofalo). All these are directed to the respiratory tract in the chest and to the digestive parts. Other therapeutic measures centre on the head, such as embrocation with green rose oil and other ingredients (1.3, 6.4–15 Garofalo). At a later stage of the disease, inflammation ‘of the middle part’ may appear (en tois mesois phlegmonē), against which cupping with scarification is prescribed: the involvement of the lower location in the body for phrenitics returns here. Haircutting is mentioned in parallel with this, although it is to be avoided at the beginning of the illness (1.3, 8.10–12 Garofalo), and application of somniferous ointments to the face is also recommended. Sleep-inducing agents should also be given as draughts or suppositories (with various recipes offered at 1.3, 7, 8, 9, 10).

Neighbouring Diseases: lēthargos, pleuritis, and pneumonia

Nosological treatises are a precious source for exploring the relationships and overlaps among neighbouring diseases and their position in the taxonomy to which they belong. AP also explores and highlights points of contact with phrenitis in its discussion of other diseases. lēthargos comes just after phrenitis in the treatise, reflecting the important association between the two which recurs for centuries to come in all medical sources.Footnote 15 Surveying the causes mentioned by thinkers in the medical tradition (1.1–3, 10.16–27 Garofalo), the Anonymous mentions ‘affection of the psychic faculty in the meninx (pathos tōn peri tēn meninga psychikōn dynameōn), where (eph’ hōn) it is precisely that lēthargos occurs’ (attributed to Erasistratus, 1.1); affection around the heart (‘the chilling of the psychic pneuma around the heart’, attributed to Diocles, 1.2); and the brain again burdened by excessive cold phlegm and causing the patient to fall into a comatose state (kataphora) (attributed to Hippocrates, 1.3).

The signs of lēthargos are continuous fever and a distinctive pulse (2.1, 12.1–5 Garofalo); difficulty in conversing and interacting, with delirium and oppression (2.2, 12.5–8 Garofalo); a swollen, flushed face; and various signs traditionally regarded as mental. As in the case of phrenitis (2.5, 4.11–13 Garofalo), when the illness becomes worse, ‘the hypochondrion is pulled up (hypochondrion anaspatai), the hands tremble a bit, and patients have difficulty swallowing (katapinein ou dynontai) (2.6, 12.13–16 Garofalo). In the therapy, interestingly, other points also connected with phrenitis return: a concern about light (2.1, 12.1–2 Garofalo); embrocations (2.1–2, 12.22–14.3 Garofalo); phlebotomy (2.3, 14.12–14 Garofalo); the phenomenon of kōma (2.4, 14.15–18 Garofalo); and a lack of awareness of natural functions such as excretion (2.5, 14.19–16.7 Garofalo) and swallowing (2.6, 16.8–13 Garofalo). Scarification and cupping are suggested, although these are common measures (2.6, 16.8–10 Garofalo). Also recommended are hot water to the head (2.8, 16.20–18.2 Garofalo), shaving and passive exercise (2.9, 18.3–4 Garofalo).

Pleuritis is located by ancient authors in or around the pleura or lungs, according to the report by AP (e.g. by Hippocrates: 8.1–4, 56.26–58.16 Garofalo). The localization of pleurisy in AP is the same as that of phrenitis, in line with what appears to have been the case in the Hippocratic texts (8.4, 58.11–16 Garofalo). Its symptoms are a sharp, piercing sense of pain in the pleura or upper chest, and fever and expectorations, accompanied by various mental or mind-related symptoms: ‘They suffer roughness of tongue, sleeplessness, agitation, distress.’ Most relevant, ‘sometimes … they become delirious, the hypochondrion is pulled up, difficulty in breathing increases’ (8.1–3, 58.18–60.9 Garofalo). Pneumonia/peripleumonia, finally, is only briefly described in this text as an inflammation of the lungs (pneumonos phlegmonē), and in a report of Praxagoras’ views it is seen as contiguous to pleurisy: one is located ‘in the part near the ribs’, the other ‘in the part near the lobes’ (9.1–2, 64.16–21 Garofalo). Signs are fever, a heavy chest, difficulty in breathing, a thick pulse and coughing. The appearance of the face is affected (glossy eyes, blushing, bulging blood vessels). As for therapy, the vast majority of the suggestions are dietetic and pharmacological, and aim at curing the bodily physiology of the disease. At 9.11 (68.23–24 Garofalo), however, it is again said that ‘we shall allay the delirium with embrocations on the head and sponging of the face’.

Still in this imperial author, then, perhaps precisely because of his comprehensive interest in doxography and lack of systematic ambitions, the ambiguity between the chest (with lung symptoms and breathing issues) and the head (partially in aetiology, but always in the signs and therapy) remains irreducible and even dominates. Compromises vis-à-vis localization and a potentially ‘holistic’ nature are reaffirmed as a marked peculiarity of our disease. At the same time, Anonymus Parisinus offers a sample of the themes addressed by nosology at this stage in Greek medicine, marking a profound difference from the Hippocratic works: the discussion of the ‘name’; the question of localization; the definition of causes and systematic description of manifestations; the therapy; and the relationship of the disease to other, similar ones.

The Signs of phrenitis in Imperial Nosology

In the early centuries of our era, a tendency to economy becomes apparent in Graeco-Roman nosology, with a coalescence of signs and details around a number of prominent syndromes, among which phrenitis stands out.Footnote 16 This is apparently brought about by a need to impose order, through lists and taxonomic schematization, on the wealth of clinical information inherited from the earlier tradition. At the same time, the grid of a ‘modern’ theoretical understanding (anatomical and physiological) is imposed on the older material, as we have seen notably in Galen.

The Galenic commentaries on Hippocratic treatises can profitably be understood as versions of such a move, both going back to the details observed by the Hippocratics and reinterpreting them within new scientific models, and adding the fruits of newly established methodologies and models, notably neurological theories and pulse diagnosis. Authors who engage less, or less explicitly, with their predecessors, such as Aretaeus, display similar tendencies towards systematization. The result, in respect of the descriptions of phrenitis, is a richer, more complex syndrome in which we begin to glimpse the characteristics of a modern representation of disease. What follows is a survey of the main signs, which emerge as common to different medical authors, and which remain central in the tradition of the disease after the end of the ancient world.

Fever

Since early times, fever had been a central marker of phrenitis.Footnote 17 In the Hippocratics, it was a key part of the disease’s affiliation with winter chest ailments. In later authors such as Diocles and Erasistratus, it apparently converged into the concept of inflammation, phlegmonē of a topical kind (the brain, meninges or diaphragm being affected) that accompanies it up to modern times. In others, such as Celsus, fever seems to sustain the delocalized, systemic, atopical account of the disease. In nosology, fever becomes a differential element to distinguish phrenitis from other mental afflictions, notably mania. Fever also remains important for another fundamental reason: it constitutes a gravitational point for many of the observable manifestations of phrenitis, which are often of a typhoid kind and associated with overheating and drying.

‘Fever’, of course, must be defined. In modern medicine, the term might be taken to indicate, rather straightforwardly, ‘a body temperature that is higher than normal’ (with ‘normal’ usually indicated as a range). But for a world that lacked the concept ‘temperature’ as continuum (as opposed to ‘hot’ vs ‘cold’), and that had no way to measure such entities with precision and no interest in them as a physical datum, the use of the modern term needs qualification. If we can, as I would argue, legitimately read pyr (πῦρ) as an experience to a substantial extent superimposable upon our ‘fever’, we must nonetheless be cautious, especially since this pathological sphere is too predominant in ancient medical literature to be taken as a strong indicator of a disease state we can recognize. Hamlin has carefully explored and exposed the network of demographic, environmental, scientific and socio-medical variables and biases that must be discounted when we apply the term to premodern contexts.Footnote 18

Aretaeus, in his therapeutic discussion, speaks of a fever ‘of a continuous type’ as characteristic of phrenitis: ‘Nor do they have long intermissions, but they experience short and ill-marked remissions’ (Th.Ac. 5.1, 92.33–93.2 Hude). For Galen, an accompanying continuous fever is also a particular element differentiating phrenitis from other kinds of insanity, as explained at Caus. Symp. 2.7 (7.202 K.): ‘All forms of delirium (paraphrosynai) are dissonant movements (plēmmeleis … kinēseis) of the hegemonic faculty (tēshēgemonikēs dynameōs), caused by malignant humours or by a bad mixture of the cerebral humours. Those with fever are called phrenitis, those without it mania.’Footnote 19 In Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 1.29 (52.7–20 Wenkebach = 17a.882–83 K.) Galen discusses various typologies of fever based on their heat, and in particular the nature of the plague described by Thucydides. He criticizes the medical categorizations offered by other authors and writes: ‘Some of the ancients called this kind of fever (i.e. that causes ulcers on the skin) phrenitic fever, like lethargic, pleuritic, peripneumonic.’ Galen disagrees, however, because ‘the fever of the phrenitic is found to display a biting heat (tēn thermasian echōn daknōdē) in every part of the body equally and continuously to the touch (dia pantos homotonōs en panti chronōi tēs epiballomenēs haphēs)’.Footnote 20 Likewise at Diff. Resp. 3.9 (7.937 K.) we read that ‘these diseases that happen with continuous fevers are of the kind [Hippocrates] demonstrates in his book On Regimen in Acute Diseases. These are acute, those the ancients call pleuritis and peripleumonia and phrenitis and kausos and all the others of this kind, whose fevers are mostly continuous.’Footnote 21

Among the symptoms of fevers described by Galen at De Cris. 11 (200.2–5 Alexanderson = 9.752 K.) are ‘strong pains to the head and neck, heaviness with or without fever. In phrenitics, spasms sometimes with yellow vomit; some of them die very quickly.’ Several details described here recur for phrenitis elsewhere as well, along with heaviness of the temples, darkened vision, tension and pain in the hypochondria, and epistaxis; the latter is also mentioned as a sign of phrenitis at Loc. Aff. 5.4 (8.330 K.).Footnote 22 Galen is well aware of the generality and frequency of the signs that characterize fevers (kausoi and other diseases with ardent fever) and, as we have seen, is very concerned with the cogency of signs as a methodological question. In this spirit, at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.15 (31.1–5 Diels = 16.545–46 K.) he comments on the following Hippocratic point: ‘Those who are severely out of themselves with fever and sweating become phrenitic.’ He writes: ‘We define this formulation as strident/contradictory (asymphōnon); its sense is so obscure, that the nouns in it can be interchangeably separated or conjoined.’ Galen proceeds with a critique of the unclear, ambiguous syntax of this author, which in his eyes fails to establish any clear interdependence between basic signs such as fever, derangement, sweating and so forth. What is notable for us is the role of fever as container already perceived by Galen himself to be dangerously loose, as by Celsus before him. Celsus in fact drew the distinction between insanity due to fevers and insanity due to phrenitis, but did not develop this as fundamental to the definition of the disease (122.17–24 Marx).

Already in the Hippocratics, fever came with a plethora of heat-related signs, such as a rough tongue, thirst and dryness; these symptoms are picked up by imperial authors as well. As expected, one of them is sweat: at De Cris. 3.3 (170.7–9 Alexanderson = 9.707 K.) it is said that ‘the good kind of sweat resolves phrenitis, and especially if abundant from the head and if warm, with the whole body sweating’. The idea, it seems, is that pressure and heat are relieved via the head, a process blood flow can also favour: ‘Through haemorrhages through the nostrils, phrenitis is even more safely resolved.’ In fact, fevers are directly related to the rise of bile to the head, as explained at Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.12 (117.5–7 Wenkebach = 17a.661 K.): ‘High fevers (kausoi phrenitikoi) derive from the excess of bile falling on the liver and stomach, and become phrenitic when they rise to the head.’Footnote 23

At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 2.2 (53.14–26 Diels = 16.592 K.) Galen writes that headaches, insomnia and asapheia – a lack of clarity in speech – should be reckoned among phrenitic signs (tōn phrenitikōn esti sēmeiōn), and ‘since we have seen phrenitis to be a particularly dry (xēron malista) illness, any symptom of dryness occurring in the organs close to the head or sharing something with it also signals oncoming derangement, by virtue of which signs the disease is called the ‘the one with thirst/the thirsty one’ – to dipsōdei/τὸ διψώδει is the transmitted form – ‘in the discussion above’. These are all classic manifestations of high fever, and their constant presence in phrenitis testifies to the strong embodied nature of the syndrome.

Sensorial Receptiveness

We have already observed that a notable element in Aretaeus’ analysis is the importance he assigns to the ambience created around the patient to protect his sensory health; the physician opens the chapter on precisely this topic. ‘A house of moderate size … a mild temperature’ are prescribed; the patient and those who live with him should ‘be ordered to preserve quiet’ (hēsychiēn agein, 91.12–15 Hude).Footnote 24 The reason for these recommendations is the extreme sensory sensitivity, tactile and visual, of phrenitic patients: they ‘have acute hearing and are affected by noise’ (oxyēkooi gar ēde psophou kathaptomenoi, 91.16 Hude), and are extremely prone to visions. For this reason, ‘walls should be smooth, level, without projections, unadorned with a frieze or paintings; for painting on a wall creates excitement’ (91.17–18 Hude). And again, since ‘certain false appearances float before their eyes (pro tōn ophthalmōn amphaireousi tina pseudea indalmata, 91.18–19 Hude)’ and easily cause them to grope and become busy with their hands (91.20–21 Hude), bedclothes should be plain, to avoid giving patients the opportunity to surrender to the urge to pluck. Light and darkness should also be modulated to suit each individual and the nature of the attack under way (92.2–8 Hude):Footnote 25 light is recommended, for instance, to keep the patient from being scared by confusing perceptions or ‘strange images (xena indalmata)’ (92.5 Hude). This hypersensitivity of the sensorial faculties is present in nuce in some Hippocratic remarks, such as those about the vividness of dreams in phrenitics,Footnote 26 and in the mention of floccillation as a recurrent behaviour. In this later period, medicine combines these traditional details and traces an image of impaired cognition: the senses impart deceptive information, and patients fall prey to images larger than life, both in dreams and awake.

The Hippocratic discussion of the vividness of phrenitic dreams just referred to is corrected by Galen at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.5 (20.10–21.18 Diels = 16.524–27 K.), in a long passage that nicely illustrates once again the complex interpretation imposed by imperial medicine on traditional signs. The observations made by physicians from the past are fitted into a comprehensive system: reading that ‘dreams in phrenitics are conspicuous/clear’ (Prorrh. I, 5, 75.10–11 Polack = 5.512 L.), Galen comments as follows:

Satyrus the student of Quintus, whom I had as my teacher before Pelops, explained this saying thus: ‘Of those things which appear clearly in phrenitics and are done by them, those that seem to us to be seen or done, are not real images matching reality but all conspicuous dreams.’ The fact that other people arising from sleep walk around while still asleep, but with their eyes open, like people who are awake, has been narrated and described in many places. But whether such things are done by phrenitics as well, is among the points that remain obscure to us. Whatever the truth might be, this inquiry does not help establish a prognosis. If I suggest that the preceding dreams of phrenitics are seen so clearly, that they are disturbed out of sleep and jump forth or speak because of the clarity of what they see, this adds something to the pre-notion of this disease; the very dryness is the cause of agrypnia and of the perspicuity of dreams. In this way, then, in melancholics as well all their visions seem perspicuous in dreams. Among those who are healthy, the dreams of those who have eaten modestly are perspicuous, while for those who are full or drunk, these appear to be without images, because the images flow in front of them due to the obscurity in such a way that they leave no sign or residue in memory; in this way too, whatever affections accompany the humidity of the brain are comatose, somnolent and without images.

It is thus the dryness of this disease and of these patients’ physiological states that causes the neatness of the images they perceive, just as humidity dulls the imagination, and torpor makes perceptions heavy and opaque. Through the language of dryness, wetness, fluid engorgement and flow, Galen is thus able to sketch out a mechanism of interaction between physiology and cognition based on the received Hippocratic sign, and forges a vocabulary for it.

Damage to Cognitive Faculties

Senses and images constitute only one level of the psychological and psychopathological portrait of the phrenitic, although perhaps the one most readily mentioned in medical literature on the history of mental disturbance.Footnote 27 While Galen is not as interested as Aretaeus or Celsus are in the emotional and personal sphere touched by phrenitic pathology, his elaboration on cognitive and imaginative damage has a depth and richness unmatched in other authors. In Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.4,Footnote 28 as we have seen, Galen distinguishes precisely among types of mental damage in phrenitis, with – according to him – unprecedented precision. As he points out, in the presence of such damage the physician must check whether the ‘muscles’Footnote 29 (myes) of these functions are affected, or if the problem is with the source of their impulses, the brain:

Since everyone calls phrenitis such a condition, in which they see damage to the phrenes (φρένες), which is how they call intellect and reasoning (noun kai dianoian), one should first inquire in which part of the body the seat of psychic intellect is located (en ōi tou sōmatos moriōi to phronoun tēs psychēs estin) … Therefore, it is necessary to identify the symptoms that express this damage … I was the first to define (heurethē de hēmin) what the damaged faculties are, namely the critical capacities: intelligence, perception and memory (hē … kata proairesin energeia kai dianoēsis, aisthēsis te kai mnēmē). The damage to these functions will indicate the type of affection …; and if one finds none of the muscles [which are the voluntary organs of those actions] to be damaged, one should suspect an encephalic lesion.

We learn more about the ‘types’ of mental affection at Loc. Aff. 4.2 (8.225–26 K.), in a passage which explores problems in the sensory organs. Here three kinds of phrenitis are distinguished, depending on which type of damage prevails:

There are two simple types of phrenitis (haplai men dyo), and a third which is a combination of the two (synthetos de ex amphoin). Some people suffering from phrenitis make no mistakes at all in distinguishing visual impressions (peri tas aisthētikas diagnōseis tōn horatōn), but base their judgement on an abnormal thought process (ou kata physin echousi tais dianoētikais krisesin). Others, to the contrary, commit no errors of judgement, but have a distorted sense perception (enioi d’ empalin en men tais dianoēsesin ouden sphallontai, paratypōtikōs de kinountai kata tas aisthēseis). Yet it happens that others are affected in both ways (allois de tisin kat’ amphō beblaphthai symbebēken).Footnote 30

In a remarkable passage at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.27 (39.22–41.26 Diels = 16.564–68 K.), Galen combines humoral explanation with hard-wired encephalocentrism to account for the variety of symptoms, sensory-motor and dianoetic, which phrenitis produces, each of the two kinds ramifying in turn into more manifestations, depending on the section of the brain affected.Footnote 31 Discussing the Hippocratic aphorism that ‘frequent changes in phrenitis are spasmodic’ (ta en phrenitisi pykna metapiptonta spasmōdea), he takes the occasion to scrutinize the nature of sudden changes in cases of paraphrosynē and in phrenitis in particular. At issue is not the change from bad to better, but from one type of bad symptoms to another, the quality of the symptoms (40.7–8 Diels = 16.564–65 K.). These manifestations are caused by variations in humoral flows, and each case is appropriate to the body part where the imbalance fixes itself, and reflects the power of the individual humour. His explanation is long but worth quoting. With phrenitis

one can conjecture from the permanence of the disease in those parts, that the humour inflicting the affection is found in the head (ek tou diamenein ep’ autōn tēn phrenitin estērichthai tis an en tēi kephalēi ton to pathos ergazomenon hyponoēseie chymon). In fact, the reflux is in the brain itself, affecting now one part of it, now another, maintaining a fixed disease conceptualization, but with symptoms that change by part

(ontōs oun kat’ auton ton enkephalon hē metarrysis estin, allote kat’ allo meros autou ti gignomenē, tēn men idean tou pathou phylattousa, kata meros d’ hypallattousa ta symptōmata).

Different clinical manifestations, Galen adds, clearly follow the affection in different regions of the brain, involving now sight or hearing, now smell, now touch, and so forth:

And now the author of the present book mentions these changes, saying that they suffer from floccillation or carphology and, after a state of deep calm, in a little while they jump up and do something manic, and next they become calm again, blaming some non-existent external object – for example, like those who order that the trumpeters or flute-players be driven away when there is not even one of them there.Footnote 32 For just as carphology or floccillation are damage to the optical perception (blabē tēs optikēs … aisthēseōs), so these others are damage to the acoustic perception (tēs akoustikēs), and there is a similar symptom for the olfactory perception (kata tēn osphrantikēn), like those who complain of foul-smelling odours that are not there. There are also those who order that something which is there be taken away, saying that it is too heavy, or too hot, or too pungent or cold to the touch, while in such symptoms the damaged tactile perception is at work (tēs haptikēs aisthēseōs en tois toioutois symptōmasi beblammenēs) … Often we observed such forms of derangement persisting continuously while the patient was in a maddened state (hai toioutai parakopai dia pantos men en tōi paranoein), but changing its fashion in accord with each type of affected faculty (hypallattomenou … tois tropois kata panta ta genē tōn psychikōn energeiōn).Footnote 33

So much concerning sensory stimuli and their interpretation by the patient. Other types of damage are more ‘purely’ cognitive, independent of sensory appraisal, such as memory or emotional excitement:

And so, just as I have listed them with regard to the senses, so in the same way as far as reason is concerned, we see that reasoning, judgement, memoryFootnote 34 and intelligence (kata logon kai gnōmēn mnēmēn te kai noēsin) are sometimes subject to change in phrenitics, so that at times they anger themselves, but sometimes they enjoy themselves or engage in serious discourse, although they are deranged

(paraphronountas).

Remarkably, other capacities may remain intact throughout these episodes of derangement:Footnote 35

And so, I have heard of orators who would rehearse during an attack of derangement (en parakopēi), and of a grammar teacher who would read a book thinking it was Bacchylides or Sappho, or a mathematician or geometer who went through the theorems of his own art. And if, while solemnly reading these things, after a while they remembered something filthy or unholy, what in the Epidemics is called ‘being foul-mouthed’ (aischromythein) the change was not from mean to appropriate, but from bad to bad, as deranged patients sometimes appear at their boldest when caught sight of at one point, and then meek and cowardly just afterward. For such symptoms appear to be fundamentally identical: they fear things that are not to be feared, indeed at times are afraid of the smallest things. An example of such an occurrence, it seems to me, [the author of Prorrhetikon] wrote in the following statement, that says ‘passing urine without realizing, bad’. So consider someone who suffers the changes mentioned above, in the urine and in other matters, in which the memory is damaged; and imagine that in turn all his sensory representations are damaged, just as the dianoetic is.

The broad variety of forms of disturbance, finally, depends on the regional complexity of the brain as it is struck by different humours with different intensities:

Of these the cause is in the brain, but the reflux affects now one part of it, now the other (allot’ allon/alias alium ipsius locum … quod transfluitFootnote 36). We have illustrated that these refluxes arise from each of the receiving parts (tōn dechomenōn moriōn) pushing the residue towards another (eis heteron). It thus makes sense that the humour which brings the pathology, flowing down from one part of the brain into the other, should in turn be pushed away from it, and that falling on the nerves which originate there, it should cause spasms. Hippocrates himself said that this affection comes from repletion and evacuation.Footnote 37

A comprehensive physiological picture of humoral overflow in this way explains emotional, imaginative-sensory and reasoning-cognitive disturbances, as well as motor impairment: the source of everything is in the brain and the nerves originating there, with the humoral element allowing for a flexibility and complexity of internal reactions that encephalocentrism alone could not provide – a picture very similar to that of De morbo sacro, despite Galen’s surprising lack of engagement with that Hippocratic treatise.Footnote 38

We thus discover two accounts of the distinct cognitive damage that occurs in the disease phrenitis. The first is subdivided into hallucination, on the one hand, and impaired judgement, on the other (with a mixed version to complete the picture). The second is tripartite, depending on the type of cognitive damage (to the intellectual faculty, the sensory faculty, or the memory), partly superimposable on the first.

In various texts, Galen offers precise clinical examples of phrenitic patients which better illustrate the distinction. The first case is a famous one, namely his own personal experience. As a young man, Galen too once fell sick with phrenitis:

Stricken by a burning fever during summer, it seemed to me that I saw sticks of dark straw protruding from my bed, as well as similar pieces of wool from my garment. I attempted to pull these out. When I was unable to catch onto anything with my fingers, I renewed this effort more steadily and forcefully. When I heard two friends who were present telling each other, ‘He is pulling wool and straw’, I understood that I had the affection of which they spoke, but I realized that I was not deranged in my reasoning faculties and said, ‘What you say is right, but help me, to keep me from suffering from phrenitis.’Footnote 39 Then they busied themselves applying wet dressings to my head. Throughout that entire day and night, I remained agitated by frightening dreams, shrieking loudly and even trying to get out of bed; but on the next day all symptoms subsided. (Loc. Aff. 4.2, 8.226–27 K.)Footnote 40

The patient, Galen, is here beginning to hallucinate, but his judgement remains sound and he is capable of intervening promptly by asking for help. Even more precise theoretical distinctions regarding the nature of derangement and hallucinations following damage to the hēgemonikon are made at Symp. Diff. 1.4 (224.9–226.8 Gundert = 7.60–61 K.). In this case, different kinds of impairment are listed and assigned a precise vocabulary, articulating mental damage along various branches of activity and faculty, which can be weakened individually or together: ‘Often delirium exists in both at the same time, in the ill-functioning [faculty of] representation (phantasiousthai) and in the improperly functioning reasoning (logizesthai), but sometimes in only one of those two.’ At Symp. Diff. 1.4 (226.13–17 Gundert = 7.61 K.) Galen offers another famous phrenitic case for the sake of illustration:

In some [people] no phantasma appears, but they do not reason correctly (logizontai d’ ouk orthōs), because the rational part of the soul is affected in them. Such was the case of the phrenitic [person] who, having closed the doors within, was holding each of the household utensils through the windows and asking passers-by if they would order him to throw them out. He spoke the name of each of the utensils quite precisely, from which it was clear that he was neither impaired in his phantasia regarding these objects nor in his memory of names (out’ en tēi phantasiai tēi peri auta beblammenos out’ en tēi tōn onomatōn mnēmēi). Why then did he wish to throw all these objects from a high place and shatter them? This he was no longer able to understand, but by the act itself he was manifestly delirious (tout’ ouketh’ hoios t’ ēn symbalein, all’ en autōi dē tōide katadēlos egineto parapaiōn). In this case the perception of reality and memory is clearly untouched; it is the judgement, reasoning and morality, we might say, that has suffered damage.Footnote 41

At Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 7. 30, 31a and 31b (1315–23 Vagelpohl),Footnote 42 commenting on the Hippocratic passage at Epid. 6, 8.10 (175.5–9 Manetti–Roselli = 5.348.1–3 L.), Galen tackles a difficult Hippocratic lemma: ‘VIII 30. Hippocrates said: The mind, distinct from the organs and the things it resides in, thinks inwardly: it feels pain or pleasure, experiences fear or courage, hope or negative thoughts.’Footnote 43 This passage gives Galen the opportunity to offer some additional comments on mental faculties, with phrenitic parallels regarding damage to reason but not to sensation (nor memory):

A doctor in my home town in the province of Asia visited a person who was suffering from brain fever. The patient then engaged the doctor, drew a sword, grasped it, handed another (sword) to the doctor and wanted him to have a sword fight. Another man was struck by this illness in the city of Cumae.Footnote 44 In his house there was a large sack filled with flour. He emptied this flour on the floor and when the doctor arrived, he wanted him to wrestle with him on this flour as wrestlers do on fine sand in the arena. Another man who had this illness hid behind the door until a person entered. He closed and locked the door and told the person who had entered that he would not open it for him until he had wrestled with him. All these individuals did what they did while (still) recognizing the faces of the people who visited them and remembering their names. That they remembered their names, indicates that they recognized them by their appearance.

We have observed many other behaviours from people with brain fever that indicate that only their mind has been harmed but not the ability to recognize perceptible objects. I therefore think that Hippocrates wanted to mention such people. Melancholia also belongs to this category, because people suffering from it clearly perceive everything and remain aware, just not in the mind’s eye.

‘Neurological’ Signs

Some markers of phrenitis are also of psychiatric interest from a modern perspective, if more on the neurological side, on our understanding of the term.Footnote 45 These are often associated with fever and dryness in the ancient accounts. For example, there are tremors due to the ‘dry character of the disease’ and its ‘tensionsFootnote 46 of the nerves (ai … eutoniai tōn neuron)’, and once the patient’s energy has dissipated due to prolonged wakefulness and exertion, ‘the nerves dry out and tremors appear’.Footnote 47 The gesturing of the phrenitic is disorderly and uncontrolled: ‘Some puff loudly … others move their head and hands in a disorderly fashion (alogōs)’. Later on, ‘their strongest sign is agrypnia, and most of all that of the troubled kind (hē tarachōdēs): this is characteristic of the phrenitic. It is troubled, as I said, if in the course of the hallucinations they scream and jump and can barely recognize their family.’

It is interesting that Galen can superimpose both a phrenitic interpretation and his own neural understanding on a patient for whom neither is explicit,Footnote 48 as at Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.91,Footnote 49 a young man who develops a fatal fever after drinking and sexual excess (ek potōn kai aphrodisiōn pollōn). Galen comments that ‘drinking too much harms the nerves and their origin in the brain. Sex also damages them, as it affects the strength and debilitates the patient. And so this young man, once a toxic amount of humours had accumulated, was taken by a slight fever, as expected. Had it got worse over the course of the days, it would have evolved into phrenitis proper (eis phrenitin akribē)’. In this case, quite unusually, Galen seems to reconstruct a history of unhealthy lifestyle as antecedent to the humoral imbalance, sketching a chain of causation and a landscape of predisposing circumstances that can lead to phrenitis. At the same time, this shows the many venues through which he remoulds his Hippocratic sources to his own purposes.

Within the neurological manifestations, motor disturbances, such as spasms, are especially important. At Comm. Hipp. Progn. 3.39 (365.16–23 Heeg = 18b.294 K.), the discussion of violence and tremors is an occasion for a neurological assessment of the disorderly movements of the phrenitic:

Those signs that appear mainly in serious cases of phrenitis indicate spasms in illnesses of this kind in those who are grown up, and especially those of them that come about as the parts of the face are distorted, or the teeth grind, or the eyes are unstable or twisted. In the case of children, merely being sleepless is sufficient, and sometimes being extremely frightened – which he called ‘being panic-struck’ (<ekplagēnai>) – and crying intensely, and an inability to evacuate their bowels.

Children present an extreme version of the severe motor symptoms phrenitis may cause in adults.

Spasms, it is explained elsewhere, originate in the overheating and drying up (hyperxēranthentōn) of the brain and meninges through the accumulation of yellow bile.Footnote 50 In extreme cases, spasms can be violent at the end, as Galen states when he comments on the Hippocratic lemma ‘The phrenitic affections end with violent tremors’ (ta phrenitika neanikōs tromōdea teleutai) at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.9.Footnote 51 If these are extreme cases, it is a general fact that ‘the vigour of the nerves, because of the dryness of the disease, affects phrenitics for a long time. And when their strength is diminished (katalytheisēs … tēs dynameōs) by their troubled insomnia (agrypnia) and their many movements, once the nerves are entirely desiccated, at that time the tremors occur’.

This dryness and parching of the nerves may also explain yawning as a symptom – although phrenitis is only one possible factor. At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.11,Footnote 52 Galen reflects on the Hippocratic ‘Experiences of pain in the pharynx: dry, small, suffocating, when yawning, with difficulty clenching and closing the mouth, and links them to derangement; among such cases, the phrenitics are in danger.’ He adds: ‘When, in the presence of these symptoms, a phrenitis should arise, of whatever kind, it is dangerous, as is rightly said. But you should not presume that it is unavoidable that phrenitis emerge from these symptoms.’ For Galen, as he goes on to explain, these signs are related to a variety of possible forms of damage at the origins of the nerves, in the brain; phrenitis could be one such circumstance, but not the only one. As in several of these discussions, Galen takes the occasion of a description of a phrenitic sign to challenge its semiotic cogency, and in the vast majority of cases to deny that it is idion (‘specific’) to the exemplary disease phrenitis. But for our purpose of offering a sketch of how phrenitis was medically perceived and described, all these signs are equal in weight, despite Galen’s ranking and discussion, and following his own pragmatism and realism.Footnote 53 In a similar spirit, at Meth. Med. 12.8 (10.872 K.) Galen points out that a state in which patients ‘lie stretched out and in pain due to severe dryness’ indicates ‘the need for moisture’. This is especially hard to treat in case of fevers. He adds: ‘In particular, it follows the deadly phrenitides (tais olethriais phrenitisi), and I myself have seen no one who has been saved after having suffered convulsions in this way’; when the cause is dryness rather than biting humour, there is no hope of curing the patient.

Sleep is an important area of psychopathology in ancient medicine, observed in fine detail by doctors from the time of Hippocrates. In Aretaeus, sleep disturbance is an important element in the portrayal of phrenitis. A range of ad hoc soothing measures for this condition is contemplated in his text on therapy, including head fomentations, applications under the pillow, rubbing the nostrils, ears, face or feet of the patient, and bespoke relaxing measures (94.14–95.3 Hude). He recommends various activities and diversions conducive to sleep, and in particular those familiar to the lifestyle of the individual patient (94.30–95.3 Hude):

to the sailor, repose in a boat and being carried about on the sea, the sound of the beach and murmur of the waves, the boom of the wind, and the scents of the sea and the ship. But to the musician, the customary note of his pipe in stillness … to a teacher, intercourse with the prattling of children. Different persons are soothed by different charms to bring about sleep (alloisi d’ alla hypnou thelktēria).

Restoration of the conditions for a peaceful rest are fundamental: insomnia and excessive sensory response seem to go together.

In Galen, sleep disturbance is also characteristic, and phrenitis is defined to an important extent as both identical and contrary to lēthargos:Footnote 54 excessive wakefulness and tension, for which, however, the physician from Pergamon notably avoids any psychotherapeutic involvement. In particular, agrypnia of a troubled kind (tarachōdes) is typical (idion) of phrenitis, as seen above in the methodological discussion.Footnote 55 In Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, in fact, Galen devotes considerable attention to articulating sleep disturbances in cases of phrenitis and lēthargos in a differential spirit: kōma, agrypnia, kataphora and the presence of sleep proper or sleepiness are variously combined in complex ways to describe the pathology, with levels of fine distinction that are at times impossible to grasp.Footnote 56

The topic of sleep was obviously important for Galen, since he devoted an entire treatise, his De comate secundum Hippocratem, to commenting on the Hippocratic concept of kōma, a condition of pathological sleepiness. At Com. 2.14–15 an important discussion involves phrenitis:Footnote 57 reading Hippocrates, Galen first distinguishes between an ‘oppression, heaviness’ (catafora) that is sleepy in kind (somnolentia) and one that is not so (catafora non somnolentia).Footnote 58 Further on, on his reading, Hippocrates distinguishes two types of sleepless (insomnis) catafora, one that is ‘dull/somnolent’ (pigra) and one that is not so. While the first is characteristic of the lethargic, the second befalls phrenitics (188.29–33 Mewaldt = 7.656 K.); under its influence, patients ‘speak and have delirium with no grip on their mind, are particularly ready to be startled’ – all the opposite of lethargics (189.20–27 Mewaldt = 7.655 K.). Further, phrenitics are delirious about matters that make no sense, and are strong enough to get up, which is impossible during lethargic kōmata, in which patients do not respond readily to any stimulus. The phrenitic kōma is thus an alert comatose state, with no weakening of sensation or movement:

And so these patients lift themselves up immediately when they hear a voice; if touched on any part of their body, they look towards the part involved. In this type of kōma the movement is disorderly (alogōs): suddenly they are taken by uncontrolled spasms … This state is called ‘heavy oppression (nōthra kataphora)’ by Hippocrates … Already Hippocrates asked himself – and we do the same with him – if these patients should be called phrenitics or something else. In any case, a distinction between the two types of kōma is necessary.Footnote 59

Likewise, agitation and a lack of peaceful sleep (hē agrypnia kai hē tarachē) characterize phrenitis – they are phrenitika sēmeiaFootnote 60 – and show the involvement of the brain. As a consequence, phrenitic patients ‘scream through their sleep, and get up due to the vividness of their dreams/visions (dia tēn enargeian tōn phantasmatōnFootnote 61). Galen also differentiates them from persons suffering from torpor and oppression in Comm. Hipp. Epid. I:Footnote 62 ‘If these things [certain affections involving the diaphragm and the hypochondrion] arise with troubled sleep and without oppression (baros), then he will die phrenitic.’

At Com. 1.3 (181.15–16 Mewaldt = 7.644 K.) Galen notes that Hippocrates’ use of the term kōma (κῶμα) differs from the traditional one. ‘Hippocrates … says (phēsi) that kōma often arises with troubled sleep/sleeplessness (agrypnia) and accompanies the phrenitic condition (phrenitikois synedreuein)’, and Galen comments:

Had he not anticipated that no phrenitics have a manic outburst, but simply said that those phrenitics who were present died with narcotic kataphora, it would have been persuasive to hear that after a conversion into lēthargos, they died this way. But since he anticipates that none had a manic outburst, it makes more sense to say that they died with kataphora while remaining phrenitic, namely while still deranged. In fact, this is the only discriminating fact, together with fever, that we accept for phrenitis, which is otherwise in no way different from mania except for fever. For both are damage to the mind, but the one without fever is characteristic of the manic, while to have fever is characteristic of phrenitics. It therefore causes no surprise that when raw humours gather in the body, as shown by the excrement and urine, they become at the same time comatose and deranged: comatose because of the coldness and abundance of the raw humours, and deranged because the humours, as they putrefy, generate acridity and heat.

At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.33 (46.18–27 Diels = 16.578–79 K.) Galen returns to the same passage:

About such phrenitic patients, Hippocrates writes as follows in the books of the Epidemics, that none of the phrenitics was raving … but they were dying oppressed by another kind of narcotic state, kataphora. In the discussion above, he calls these phrenitics ‘unclear’ (asapheis), as if saying that they are difficult cases not only for non-specialists but also for the doctors. For they think that only those who cry out and jump up are phrenitic, while Hippocrates refers this way to those who are hit in the phrenes, even if they appear to be in some form of kataphora all the time.

It is clear that this particular kind of kōma characterizes a version of our disease, since it appears, despite variations, in a number of different sources.Footnote 63 It is also clear that Galen considers types of sleep to be indicators of states of mental health generally, with these exemplified by phrenitis and lēthargos. The underlying physiology is described at De causis pulsuum 3.10 (9.140 K.), where a distinction is drawn between two different causes of sleep, a dry and a moist one, with opposite pathological outcomes:

Sleep comes from natural heating or through toil of some sort or through excessive dryness, or is caused by food or by excessive moisture that is unable to find a way out. The first is healthy and in accord with nature, whereas the second described is the type in cases of kōma or lēthargos. The state of wakefulness of phrenitis and in all cases of insomnia contrary to nature is in antithesis to this, [coming about] at the point where the natural heat dries up excessively and, as if it were burnt up, is for this reason pushed violently towards the exterior.

Voice and Tongue

The feverish dryness of phrenitis has consequences for the voice and tongue of these patients, as repeatedly noted in the Hippocratic texts, where a ‘rough tongue’ or ‘lisping tongue’ often accompanies high fevers. At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.3,Footnote 64 the Hippocratic aphorism under discussion attributes to phrenitics precisely ‘muffled and dry tongues’ (hai daseiai glōssai kai kataxēroi), which Galen connects with those that are tracheiai (‘rough’), emphasizing the dryness and roughness caused by the heating generated by yellow bile. At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.20,Footnote 65 ‘a trembling tongue is a sign of a mind not well composed’: what is at stake here is this sign and a weakened psychic faculty, as also in the case of phrenitis: ‘For when the brain suffers and there is a hot affection, it cannot stay still.’ In both cases, the issue involves heating, dryness and the state of the organs of speech.

Galen also considers this sign in terms of semiotics and cogency vis-à-vis phrenitis. At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.19Footnote 66 he comments: ‘Derangements with a shrill voice and trembling spasms of the tongue, when these grow tremulous, [the patients] are out of themselves, and in these cases hardening (of the tongue) is fatal.’ This sign, Galen observes, is characteristic but not exclusive:

Whenever derangement appears in phrenitis, which is a hot, dry illness, and the dryness is passed on to the trachea, a shrill voice develops, just as a raucous voice derives from being drenched in moisture. But these are not affections proper to phrenitis; for they also arise in other diseases and do not last for the whole duration of the phrenitic affection. The tremor of the tongue thus affects the psychic faculty because of the dry condition of the above-mentioned illness. The spasms are instead a consequence of the dryness of the muscles in it (i.e. the tongue), as they suffer together with the head, just as the voice becomes tremulous because of a lack of tone due to the bad mixture in them. All the symptoms mentioned above arise because of the onset of dryness in the head, and obviously signal affection of the mind. In all these cases of hardening, [this set of signs] is fatal because of the excessive dryness accumulated in the brain.

In this way, the sign is revealed as characteristic of fevers generally, but not of phrenitis specifically. In the same spirit, at Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.33 Galen comments on the Hippocratic statement regarding a phrenitic quality of certain kinds of voices, writing:Footnote 67

Since the affection to the head belongs to this katastasis, which is hot, moist and continuously without wind, it follows that also in phrenitics and those with ardent fever there will be the same symptom due to the same cause, and not because of the constitution proper to the disease in itself. For the phonetic parts dry themselves more than they moisten themselves, as in the katastasis being discussed here. And then also the voice becomes metallic and acute because of the dryness of the phonetic organs, and hoarse because of the moisture.

As was the case already in the Hippocratics, a lack of clarity in articulated speech – which in the older sources is often identical to a lack of mental clarity – is associated with overheating and dryness.Footnote 68 Overheated, feverish patients may suffer from a characteristic insecurity of speech, the ‘trembling tongue’ (hai tromōdeis glōssai), a general consequence of a weakened ‘mental power’ found in phrenitis or due to other causes. This too is not a defining sign for Galen (ouk … tōn oikeiōn tēs phrenitidos sēmeiōn, Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.20).Footnote 69 The trembling tongue, he says, is seen by some as a sign of psychic weakness, while the lack of clarity is instead ‘a sign of cerebral suffering caused by heat that does not allow the brain a state of calm’.

In conclusion, just as this manifestation is not exclusive (idia) to phrenitis, neither are the muffled tongue or the quality of the voice – the ‘metallic voice’.Footnote 70 These are all interconnected for Galen as features of the dry and hot disease, which also involves urinary incontinence while asleepFootnote 71 and a dry tongue. As such, they are ‘common’ but not exclusive (ouch henikōs phrenitikon alla plēthyntikōs).Footnote 72

Urine, Sweat and Other Secretions and Excretions

As we have seen, the urine of phrenitics was described by the Hippocratics as whitish with sediment. Urine and the excreta generally are an object of scrutiny in ancient medicine from its early origins. This tradition of observation continues through the imperial age with the work of late-antique doctors and is substantially developed there, expanding into a separate branch of medical diagnosis.Footnote 73

For Galen, as we have seen, the quality of urine lacks cogency as a nosological marker. Urine, he explains at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.13,Footnote 74 can be white for various reasons, especially diet-related ones. At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.4Footnote 75 he notes again that neither urine nor sweat is a sufficient sign. For the vast majority of patients, in fact, bodily products – stools, urine, vomit, sweat, exanthema, sputum and a sense of oppression/unwellness in one particular body part – are not cogent. At Comm. Hipp. Aph. 4.72,Footnote 76 Galen also points out that the quality of the urine reflects the general state of the individual, although this is particularly true for acute cases like phrenitis: ‘Those pertaining to urine are signs of extreme indigestion/crudity, on which account the disease becomes chronic. Some of these are very damaging when they attack already fading strength, as in the case of phrenitis.’ Likewise, he writes later on (Comm. Hipp. Aph. 4.72, 17b.760 K.) that ‘a watery kind of urine is most negative; such things appear especially in phrenitic patients who are doing very badly’.Footnote 77

Other secretions are also discussed. Sweat is similar, associated with fever generally rather than with phrenitis in particular: ‘Those who are insane with fever and sweating are phrenitic’ (Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.15Footnote 78); ‘Phrenitic difficulties accompanied by chilling and sweating in the upper parts with fevers, as for Aristagora, are fatal’ (Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.26Footnote 79). Linked to heat and dryness is also a symptom that often recurs after Galen, the dense acridic lacrimation of phrenitics: ‘When they are about to suffer from phrenitis, they have very dry eyes, or a single acridic tear flows from one or the other’ (Loc. Aff. 5.4, 8.330 K.).

Expectoration – coughing and sputum – was important in the early history of phrenitis as well, since the association with derangement was consonant with a localization of phrenitis in the chest. Galen tests this sign too in terms of validity – as seen in Chapter 4 – and regards it as relevant but not restricted to phrenitis. This chest sign is thus retained by Galen, albeit minimized in its importance as non-exclusive, and is explained as a consequence of the impairment in the brain-centred proairetic capacities, and thus as entirely disconnected from any inflammation, clogging or pathology of the respiratory tract as primary.

Pulse

A fundamental diagnostic element in the medicine of the imperial period is the pulse, inspection of which is increasingly regarded as a major prognostic technique, as we have seen as early as the Anonymus Parisinus.Footnote 80 In the case of phrenitics, the pulse is described by Galen as characteristically ‘low/small (mikros); but very rarely it may appear large (megas), and it has a moderate tone and is hard and sinewy (sklēros kai neurōdēs) and overly thick and fast (pyknos agan kai tachys). But it also comes in waves; sometimes it will be felt by you as trembling, but at other times as spasmodically intermittent’ (Caus. Puls. 4.14, 9.184 K.). At De causis pulsuum 4.14 (9.186 K.) we read that ‘spasmodic intermission in the movement, and its stopping for a rather long interval of time throughout, belongs to phrenitics, as if the heat were taking over and the organs becoming hard’.

The cause of these qualities of the pulse is the bilious humour that causes heating and hardness (sklerotēs) in the arteries (De Caus. Puls. 4.14, 9.184–86 K.).Footnote 81 Rufus, writing in the first/second century ce, likewise says in his Synopsis de pulsibus 6.2 (227.1–2 Daremberg) that ‘the pulse of the phrenitic is short and vigorous, because of the continuous motion of the breath due to the lack of sleep’. The second-century ce medical writer Marcellinus in his De pulsibus (289–90 Schöne) also describes the pulse of phrenitics as generally frantic and stressed: ‘fast, thick, and irregular, in many cases small/frequent … In some cases, it also appears to tremble. There are in addition cases in which the artery falls down and rises up again suddenly. In some cases, there is only shrinking of the artery, in others indeed its collapse. Such a state develops quickly into a “tickling” feeling (formicatio).’Footnote 82 Again at De pulsibus 431 Schöne, discussing Herophilus, he claims to have often observed the ‘gazelle-like pulse’ the Alexandrian mentioned as a common feature of phrenitic and cardiac dispositions (en … phrenitikais kai kardiakais diathesesi), with a noteworthy conceptualization of the phrenitic ‘disposition’.

Respiration

A kind of pathological respiration is also associated with phrenitis. Respiration is an important point of connection between the physiology of pulsation, with its distribution in the body perceived as holistic, which is delocalized, and the chest function of respiration, localized in the lungs and heart, and which phrenitis affects or involves, at least in its Hippocratic formulation, where this is explicit.Footnote 83 At Diff. Resp. 3.10 (7.940–41 K.), Galen cautiously discusses a connection between respiration, thirst and phrenitis:

For this reason, deep breathing (hē makropnoia) is a sign or pathological cause of continuous yawning … Because shallow breathing is characteristic of those who do not drink or drink very little; but this is not said clearly – actually, it is expressed as if it were quite symbolic (touto d’ ouketi saphōs, all’ ēdē symbolikōteros eirētai).Footnote 84 For should we think that phrenitics are meant by him here, since others too say that phrenitics drink little, are startled by noises and have tremors? Or [should we think] instead that he means to indicate those in whom the parts around the heart and lungs cool, so that their inhalation is prolonged and they exhale due to being chilled at the same time? For shortness of breath in both is a sign of healing (eisagomenē gar ex amphoin hē brachypnoia sēmeion ietērion).Footnote 85

In the chapter of Loc. Aff. (5.4 = 8.332 K.) that concerns the phrenitis that involves the diaphragm, Galen carefully differentiates between the different affections of respiration in these cases, as opposed to cases where the phrenitis affects primarily the brain: in the second case, respiration is ‘deep and slow’ (mega kai araion), in the first ‘rapid and spasmodic’ (mikron kai pyknon).

Drinking, Thirst and Lack of Awareness Thereof

Thirst is also an area where mental distress manifests itself at the crossroads between physiological alteration and mental-behavioural disturbance. This is already noted in the Hippocratic texts in several cases where mental disturbance is preponderant, as well as in concomitance with fever.Footnote 86 As such, phrenitis is an obvious case, although the classical sources do not discuss thirst as a specific sign in connection with it. Thus at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.16 Galen reflects on the lemma ‘Phrenitics drink little, are bothered by noise, tremble (hoi phrenitikoi brachypotai, psophou kathaptomenoi, tromōdees)’Footnote 87 and comments:

What is said here is true; for they are troubled by noise as timid people are when they hear a sudden strong thundering or realize a wild animal is nearby. But in addition phrenitics all drink little, although they have a dry and hot affection, so that they have a rough tongue due to the extreme dryness. In addition, Hippocrates teaches us that their mind is sick in that aphorism which says: ‘Whoever aches in any part of the body and does not feel the pain, his mind is sick (hē gnōmē nosei)’. Moreover, in the third book of the Epidemics, in which he speaks of the pathological state of phrenitics, he says the same: ‘They were notably lacking in thirst.’Footnote 88

Galen here decisively interprets a lack of thirst as having to do with a lack of self-awareness as a psychopathological sign somehow analogous to unmotivated fears, bringing in parallels from other physiological functions also discussed by the Hippocratics.Footnote 89 At Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.45,Footnote 90 in the same spirit, he comments on a mention of lack of thirst in the Hippocratic text, writing: ‘The talk is about phrenitics, for [Hippocrates] says that they have become thirstless not so much because of having excessive moisture at the mouth of the stomach, but because of being unaware of what happens to them, and because the oretic power at the mouth of the stomach has perished in them.’

Psychology and Behaviour

As far as character and psychology are concerned, aggressiveness is a recurring behavioural trait in the disease. This is an interesting ethical elaboration if we compare the imperial material with earlier classical medicine, where a dangerous character is not emphasized as much: the insane may be agitated, easily startled or prone to shouting, but there is no parallel for the complexity of these examples of aggressiveness or for the consequent moralization of the motor phenomenon they allow.

Phrenitics do not display a particular ethical makeup in the Hippocratics, where the focus is on their physiological state. In the late-antique period, a character, an ethical typology, and a peculiar emotional state begin to take shape. This is most evident in the non-technical literature, but also appears with increasing frequency in medical authors. Galen is not a rich source here, however. Outside the impermeable container of his ethical treatises, Galenic psychology remains fundamentally reductionist. This position is most evident in his account of phrenitis, which is extensive on all physiological levels, broadly intended (neurological, encephalic, humoral, sensory-motor and cognitive), but close to non-existent when it comes to psychology in the sense of the subjective, conscious life of patients (emotions and character).Footnote 91 It is no coincidence that phrenitis, Galen’s favourite case in many discussions of the physiology of the body, is mentioned only once in his ethical treatises,Footnote 92 while mania and melancholia are evoked a few times as examples of impaired states of health impacting the state of the mind. For the physician, phrenitis was perhaps simply too hard-wired a disease to be subject to ethical or psychological scrutiny – which in turn, I suggest, made it ideal material for allegory in non-medical authors.

Galen’s comments about the eyes of the phrenitic open up a perspective on this. This body part is seen in Greek medicine in a quite literal sense as an expression of the state of the individual’s mental and ethical health,Footnote 93 an element that reflects a wider cultural belief, and ‘encrusted eyes’ are explicitly mentioned as manic signs (ommata epichnoun echonta, manika) in this sense in Prorrh. I, 17 (77.1–3 Polack = 5.514 L.). Galen has an interesting comment on this passage (Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.17):Footnote 94 this sign, he says, while common to various diseases – and especially the putrescent sort – appears in phrenitics as well, and in the most aggressive cases (tōn sphodrotata phrenitizontōn). Moreover, the eyes of these patients ‘have a bold glance (to blemma thrasy)’, while in putrescent patients the glance is meek (deilon). When phrenitics display this sign, they ‘are frantic in a furious way (maniōdōs parapaiousin)’ due to their overwhelming dryness. Here we see Galen wrestling with the variety of Hippocratic data, returning again and again to phrenitis as an inclusive category, even when mania – a disease he pointedly differentiates from phrenitis by virtue of the presence or lack of fever – is being explicitly discussed instead. Galen’s engagement with the psychological event tends to return to the bodily manifestation and physiological account, in this case specifically dryness.

Extraordinary strength is also a fundamental characteristic of the portrayal of violence, linked, visually in particular, to the spasms, restlessness and compulsive movements from which phrenitics suffer. At 3.5 in the Problemata attributed to Alexander of Aphrodisias, it is observed that these patients are identified as strong during the disease but weak during remission, again due to the drying effect of the illness, emphasizing the polarity between the alternating states:

Why are phrenitics especially strong in their disease, but weak when it remits? Because the dry dyskrasia takes over the brain and the nerves, and this imparts tonicity (tonon) to the nerves, energizing them (pros energeian). Then when they realize they are in remission, from this fatigue a lucid state comes about in the judgement faculties in the ill, and once wetted, their nerves become soft and weak.

Cassius Iatrosophista, the author of the Quaestiones Medicae et Problemata Naturalia (possibly from the late second/early third century ce) likewise discusses this remarkable strength in a medical problem (62.1–2 Garzya–Masullo):

Why are phrenitics and manics stronger in their paroxysms (en tois paroxysmois ischyroteroi), and why do they have increased strength (tēn dynamin epitetamenēn echousi)? One should say, because they are rendered bolder by derangement; for their body is made inflexible/rigid by the excessive contraction (hoti thrasynontai men hypo tēs parakopēs; dyskampton de autois esti to sōma apo tēs agan sphixeōs). For this reason, once they have reached remission, they relax/lose strength, not because they are passing from a better to a worse state, but because once the tension is loosened, everyone returns to being able to see without obfuscation.Footnote 95

We now come to variation and inconsistency of character. In this determinist account of phrenitic derangement, mental alterations with their duration and chronology are fundamental. All forms of behaviour that are out of character are seen as characteristic. At Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 2.8,Footnote 96 as he comments on the fact that ‘an aggressive reply from a kind person is a bad sign’, Galen explains that the discontinuity in itself signals phrenitis, just as the contrary change, from bold to mild, signals lēthargos: ‘A person who habitually has a gentle nature, not only reveals his state when he is deranged in a fatal way, but also reaches the point of phrenitis (hekei phrenitidos) when he answers in an aggressive way. In turn, a polite reply in a bold character foresees kataphora and lēthargos in the patient.’

Aretaeus’ extant testimony, with its focus on therapy, is by contrast especially dense in clinical information aimed at the psychology of the patient in a more comprehensive sense. He opens his discussion of the care of phrenitics with psychotherapeutic aspects: the whole initial section at Th.Ac. 1 (91.12–92.8 Hude) stresses elements of psychology rather than strictly physiological ones. Patients ‘ought to lie in a house of moderate size and mild temperature’; peace and quiet should be maintained by family and guests; the walls should be smooth, devoid of any image, since images might trigger the patients’ disturbed imagination; likewise covers should be smooth, so as not to excite the ill to compulsive picking with their hands (floccillation). The company of friends should be encouraged, but without producing excessive excitement, and an appropriate modulation of light should be obtained to suit the mood of the patient. This approach presents phrenitics as primarily patients of a mental kind, although the usual dietetics and physiological measures follow.

In Aretaeus as well, explicit mental and neurological signs are included: impaired cognition; sensory alteration, especially hallucinations; pathological insomnia; or restlessness and uncontrolled movements of the limbs. Even the voice may change in these patients, this being a traditional marker of psychic alteration in ancient medicine:Footnote 97 ‘Insomnia (agrypniē) and false visions (phantasiē) are present … They become disordered in understanding (tēn gnōmēn parakineontai) and their voice changes (tēn phthenxin exallassontai) … The delirium becomes more violent’ (93.31–94.3 Hude). Degrees of delirium signal stages in the progression of the disease and demand different pharmacological options to keep derangement (paraphorē) in check (92.17 Hude).

In addition to these general categories, numerous features of general behaviour are important indicators for mental cases, communicating impairment on a holistic level or simply characterizing the patient, the ‘human being’, as phrenitic in the reality of his or her existence. Despite his attention to physiology and the poverty of his comments on phrenitic personal psychology, Galen offers a great deal on the level of assessment through direct observation, again following the path of Hippocratic clinical activity. The behavioural portrait of phrenitics includes disparate elements such as gesturing, a lack of desire or ability to drink, a fixed gaze, sudden weeping and incoherent responses to questions. Patients are deranged and speak senselessly, are afraid for no reason, and pick flocks with their hands. ‘Sometimes they speak aggressively, others remain despondent and hardly answer. Even if they feel pain in some parts, sometimes they do not feel physical contact, even if one touches them forcefully (ē merous tinos odynēran echontos diathesin oud’ holōs aisthanesthai, kan sphodroteron tis autou thigēi)’, as described at Loc. Aff. 5.4 (8.331 K.).

The most representative individual visible sign of phrenitis is surely floccillation or crocydism, which we have already encountered many times.Footnote 98 Galen explicitly interprets it as a form of hallucination, a misrepresentation of reality belonging to the same category as visions. (He pays no attention, however, to the compulsive specifics of the focus on small items, whether dust, pieces of wool, threads or insects.)Footnote 99 We have seen how Galen at Loc. Aff. 4.2 (8.226–27 K.) relates his own experience as a phrenitic patient beginning precisely with this sign: ‘Stricken by a burning fever during summer, it seemed to me that I saw sticks of dark straw protruding from my bed, as well as similar pieces of wool from my garment.’Footnote 100 He explains the nature of this disturbance, which was in his case accompanied by nightmares:

Throughout the entire day and night I remained agitated by frightening dreams, shrieking very loudly and even trying to get out of bed; but on the next day, all symptoms subsided … When a bilious humour accumulates in the brain at the time of a burning fever, the brain is affected in the same manner as objects which are burned on a very hot fire. A kind of smoky flame arises, as from an oil lamp. When fumes enter the blood vessels leading to the eyes, they produce optical illusions (phantasmata) in these patients.

The process is also considered at Problema 2.54 by ps.-Alexander of Aphrodisias, where the optical pneuma is discussed. The text explains that in phrenitic patients the vapours (hoi atmoi) go directly from the damaged brain to the optical pneuma, making it difficult for them to see things the way they are.Footnote 101

Different causes can produce the malignant vapours which obscure vision, although phrenitis is one of the most common, and Galen takes it as his chief example:

It can happen in this way also in acute fevers and inflammation of the lungs, when the humours in the body rise as vapours to the head, that the clear fluid around the pupil shares in their exhalation. And wherever and in whatever way it is made turbid, the aforesaid images are generated.Footnote 102 But in violent headaches, just as in cases of phrenitis, because the head becomes full and some part of the humours reaches the eyes, this causes the same symptoms. And ‘picking at loose flocks’ and ‘picking at things’, verbs habitually used by all doctors, especially for patients suffering from phrenitis, have acquired their meaning from the following. Some people have described the image of flocks (krokydon) and of chaff, both while this was actually happening and afterward, recalling it later.

(Comm. Hipp. Progn. 1, 23Footnote 103)

And a bit later:

For it seemed to them that in many places the flocks of the bedclothes were protruding, and that there was chaff attached to the walls, and often also that there were many pieces of straw lying on the bedding, and that small creatures were flying past close to their eyes. They attempt to chase these, moving their hands about as if to catch something. As for the other things that appear to be protruding, they attempt to remove the former from the bedclothes and to tear away the latter from the wall. Accordingly, the dispositions producing such symptoms are fairly grave, with acute fever, inflammation of the lungs, and headache affecting them due to their intensity, while phrenitis does so because of the pre-eminence of the affected part.Footnote 104

Neighbouring Diseases

A useful measure of the ontological status of a disease is its position within a taxonomy or community of diseases synchronically present in a given context. Classical medicine notably placed phrenitis among the winter diseases affecting the chest and among high fevers. Celsus clearly positioned it among the kinds of insania, as its most representative type; other nosological authors of the early centuries placed phrenitis first within an order a capite ad calcem, implying its importance and position in the head (meninges and brain). Another important relative positioning which emerges in this period has to do with mania, from which phrenitis as a mental disorder is differentiated by fever.Footnote 105 The most important relation, however, is between phrenitis and lēthargos, as already posited with Celsus.Footnote 106 The relation between these two appears to have a primarily practical importance: this is clear in the fact that the pharmaceutical author Dioscorides often presents and discusses the two together in his notes, and that their course and therapy are presented as symmetrical by several late-antique and medieval authors.

In Aretaeus as well, proximity or convertibility into other diseases is a recurring feature of phrenitis. First, kausos (καῦσος) can be its co-affection (97.14–19 Hude), with ‘thirst, restlessness, mania’ (dipsos, aporiē, maniē). Second, Aretaeus is the first (and perhaps only) author to mention the disease synkopē, literally ‘collapse of strength’, as a possible outcome of phrenitis (phrenitis gar eutrepton es synkopēn kakon, 92.22 Hude); in this case, therapy must disregard the delirium and focus on preventing the patient from dissolving his or her strength into vapours and humidity (97.19–23 Hude). Support is given by wine, with its ability to ‘impart pleasure through its sweet smell’ and to ‘soothe the mind in delirium’, two important effects of drinking.Footnote 107 synkopē is localized in the heart (kardiē; cf. 2.3, 21.27–23.12 Hude).Footnote 108 Third and most important, since Aretaeus maintains that phrenitis has connections in the body with both the chest and the head, affiliation to neighbouring diseases in these two parts is mentioned: lēthargos, on the one hand, and the more traditional pleuritis and peripleumoniē, on the other. Just as for phrenitis, the chapter on lēthargos survives only in Aretaeus’ book on therapy (Th.Ac. 2); here he mentions the importance of moderating light and creating a suitable environment, offering patients interesting conversation, massages and tickling, as well as stimulating images on the wall to inspire their sense of vision – an entire invigorating package identical but contrary to the one for phrenitis, where relaxation and calm are key. If excessive sleep prevails, strong measures such as shouting, angry reproach and exciting announcements are in order, ‘the opposite as for phrenitics’, as he specifies (98.8–14 Hude).

The polarity, symmetry and complementarity of the two conditions are clear in physiological terms, but also as an ethical contrast between the excessive, hyperactive, ‘phrenitic’ ways of the one group of patients and the passivity, sleepiness and lack of engagement of the other. For Aretaeus, in lēthargos as well both belly and head are in focus, calling for the same prescriptions as for phrenitics (99.10–11 Hude), namely therapy directed at body parts located in the lower chest (bladder, hypochondrion). In general, lack of aisthēsis, sensitivity (101.23 Hude), is the issue for lēthargos, corresponding to the hypersensitivity found in phrenitis. This sensory aspect has ethical repercussions, and therapeutic measures for the two are either similar to or mirror images of each other (e.g. here too hair must be clipped, 102.3–4 Hude).

In Aretaeus, pleuritis shows no pathological point of contact with phrenitis, apart from the close localization, and therapy is addressed to the body exclusively; peripleumoniē (2.1, 15.1–16.26 Hude), on the other hand, presents similarities. The latter disease is obviously focused on the respiratory system and its organs and seat in the chest and neck. The description of it, however, includes interesting mental aspects, as was already the case in some of the Hippocratic material.Footnote 109 Among these are aberration of mind, gnōmēs aporiē (16.6 Hude) and vain fancies, phantasiai axynetoi; patients are deranged in their understanding (paralēroi tēn gnōmēn) although not violently delirious (ekstatikoi ou mala), and have no knowledge of their present suffering (agnōsiē tōn pareontōn kakōn, 16.9–11 Hude). There are also visible signs (heat, pulsating veins on the temples, gasping and a dry tongue) which suggest involvement of the brain.

Galen follows similar lines, giving particular emphasis to lēthargos as a contrasting and symmetrical condition. At Symp. Caus. 3.10 (7.259–60 K.), for example, phrenitis is a dry, hot disease, and because of this it promotes and intensifies the active functions. lēthargos, on the other hand, is said to be weak, soaking the parts with abundant moisture, and cold.

In his invective against the Thessalians and the followers of Athenaeus at Meth. Med. 13.21 (10.928–31 K.), as we have seen, Galen criticizes the fact that, despite their cardiocentric affiliation, they focus their therapeutic attention on the head in cases of phrenitis – just as Galen himself would do. He extends the example to lēthargos and adds:

Even in those with lēthargos, there is no one who does not apply the remedies to the head, for this affection is in a way symmetrical in kind to phrenitis (touto gar to pathos enantion men pōs esti kata tēn idean tēi phrenitidi). It occurs when the brain, in which the hēgemonikon of the soul is located, is affected. Therefore, whenever the humour predominating in the brain is cold, anaisthēsia and akinēsia befall the person … This, then, is common to both diseases (koinon amphoterois tois nosēmasin), both those which occur with lēthargos and those which occur with troubled sleep/insomnia.

Phrenitis is thus pragmatically categorized as a ‘wakefulness’-related disease, especially when therapy is under discussion, being defined a little later as one of the ‘diseases with troubled sleep/insomnia and raving (tois … agrypnitikois kai perikoptikois nosēmasi)’ that must be cured by ‘making the hēgemonikon sleepy and numb, cooling, obviously, the over-heated brain. But in the opposite affections [i.e. lēthargos] it is appropriate to rouse and to cut and heat the thickness of the distressing humours which, without putrefaction, creates deep somnolence.’ It thus makes sense that for Galen lēthargos should be the obvious resolution for phrenitis, as explained in Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 6.9:Footnote 110 ‘Just as the quartan fever resolves epilēpsia, and fever any sort of spasm or catarrh or asthma, in the same fashion diarrhea resolves ophthalmia, heartburn the passing of indigested food, pleuritis peripleumonia, (and) phrenitis lēthargos.’Footnote 111

Galen also appears to implicitly categorize phrenitis as a mental health issue when he implicates it in previous discussions of other mental disorders.Footnote 112 Consider his critique of a Hippocratic diagnosis of melancholia at Comm. Hipp. Acut. 4.37.Footnote 113 The original Hippocratic statement runs as follows: ‘In those patients, during fevers the cavity is wet and the mind troubled (gnōmē tetaragmenē), and many of them pick flocks and pick their nose and reply to questions only briefly, but by themselves do not say anything sensible. Therefore, these seem to me to be melancholic.’ Galen disagrees with the Hippocratic author and offers instead a phrenitic interpretation:

The other symptoms are typical of phrenitics, but the one involving a wet cavity is sometimes present in phrenitis but is not specific to it, so that it is appropriate to treat the wet cavity independent of the definitions/territories (of phrenitis) and to consider other therapies proper to phrenitis. The therapy this author described does not target phrenitis precisely, but appears to me to want to cure a disposition arising from a situation in the cavity, which involves the head by sympathy, so that there is delirium with affection of the cavity. He writes that such cases are ‘melancholic’, incorrectly; for such cases arise more because of yellow bile when it reaches the cavity.

It is clear that Galen focuses here on a sign of mental significance, floccillation, and takes it in the abstract to be associated, by virtue of other physiological details, to a general phrenitic make-up.

Finally, in Galen, as in Aretaeus, phrenitis can be co-present with ardent fevers (kausoi) or follow them, with different outcomes. He comments on a passage in Hippocrates as follows (Comm. Hipp. Epid. I, 2.78):Footnote 114

In those who had become phrenitic without having had kausos, none of the above-mentioned symptoms occurred, but death came around the sixth day to those who had become phrenitic after a kausos, the severity of their disease having been doubled (diplasiasthentos autois tou kakou).

Both pathological forms are caused by yellow bile, with kausos hitting the stomach, while phrenitis affects the brain and its membranes (Comm. Hipp. Epid. I, 2.75):Footnote 115

The same humour causes burning fevers and phrenitis, but occupies different places (ou ton auton de topon echōn). When it settles in the brain and in the meninges, it causes phrenitis. Before it settles, when it flows down through the vessels in the meninges, it brings not phrenitis but those forms of paraphrosynē which occur at the peak of fevers.Footnote 116

Age, Season, Profiling, Predispositions

While the profile of patients prone to our disease was not made particularly clear in earlier medicine, external factors and aspects of profiling begin to appear in the nosology being discussed here, more fully contextualizing the disease. In Galen, the typical phrenitic is said to be neither very young nor old, but just ‘past the young age’, as we read in PHP 8.6.31;Footnote 117 this age-profile is shared, however, with pleuritis, peripleumonia and lēthargos. The age-specification is in any case not rigid: at Comm. Hipp. Aph. 3.30Footnote 118 we also learn that ‘the forms of phrenitis, burning fever, cholera, dysentery hit the young no less than those past their prime (tois neaniskois ouden hētton ē tois parakmazousi ginontai), taking their origin from the yellow bile’.Footnote 119

As for triggering circumstances, in Galen summer heat is predominant in favouring the disease (alongside springtime, youth and a hot nature), as we read at Com. 2,7;Footnote 120 Galen himself, as we have seen, fell prey to the disease in summer. The development of the description of phrenitis in the direction of a dry, bilious ailment determines this emphasis on heat, sun and summertime. We are a long way from the Hippocratic chest infection linked to the cold months of the year.Footnote 121

Similar information, to the effect that phrenitis is not a cold disease, is found at Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI 7.50 (1255.14–16 Vagelpohl): ‘So phrenitis is a disease of the warm nature and one that corresponds to the warm age of life, and it stays in opposition to a cold nature and cold age’ (and, as such, to lēthargos - my translation). Again: ‘When someone is scattered in his movements, fidgety, vehement, clumsy, irritable, he has the disposition for wandering of the mind with fever, which is called “hot phrenitis” (“heiße phrenitis”)’; opposite this is a ‘cold phrenitis’ – lēthargos, we might suppose: ‘In cases of madness with fever, the person who is dumb, slow, sluggish is predisposed to fall into cold phrenitis, which is called lēthargos(Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 7.38, 1219.17–1221.2 Vagelpohl).Footnote 122

These ‘cold’ and ‘hot’ models aside, there is only sporadic information about what might make a patient more prone to falling ill with our disease. At Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.72,Footnote 123 for example, in a physiognomic spirit, we are told that ‘the red-faced and those prone to melancholia, having thick, hot blood, were likely to be taken by phrenitic diseases or forms of kausos or blood-stained forms of dysentery in the vast majority of cases’. Even emotions can have an impact, as Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 2.40 explains:Footnote 124 fear can cause the blood to become serous and lead in turn to agrypnia, and ‘if there is a bad humour, not only does the serous part of the blood circulate in the blood vessels, but it will also cause forms of paraphrosynē, phrenitis and mania’.

Diet and what we would call lifestyle can also play a part, although they are not systematically foregrounded. At Comm. Epid. III, 3.91Footnote 125 Galen comments on the young man in Moelibea discussed by Hippocrates (Epid. 3, 17, 111.10–13 Jouanna = 3.146 L.) and mentioned previously. The youth had a fever and ultimately died ‘as a result of drinking and sexual activity’ (ek potōn kai aphrodisiōn). Galen retrospectively explains this death as a phrenitic outcome: it may (eikotōs) have begun with a moderate fever, with the passing of time it became worse, and it ultimately resulted in a true and proper phrenitis (eis phrenitin akribē periestē). The reason is that excessive drinking and sexual activity can damage the nerves and their origin, the brain (ta te neura blaptousin kai tēn archēn autōn, ton enkephalon). Most important, Galen stresses the nature of each individual, his or her ēthos (ἦθος), as a determinant: ‘In men of an unstable and troubled nature (kouphois kai tarachōdesin), a small cause is enough (epi smikrais prophasesin) to unleash the disease. For those, on the other hand, who have the opposite nature (ēthos, i.e. one that is stable and calm), more substantial triggers are needed (epi megalais aitiais).’

Cure and Prognosis

Surprisingly for a modern reader, phrenitis does not attract much specific therapy of a physiological kind, despite its importance. In general, measures target the patients’ over-heated, flushed head, and try to induce sleep in order to favour calm and relaxation. In reference to this period, it would be poor anthropology to distinguish ‘scientific’ therapy from folk or magic methods. We should nonetheless, albeit with some reservation, group here the measures invented by professional doctors who insert themselves in a tradition of incremental scientific discourses, and leave other methodologies, more reliant on traditional, symbolic and ritual elements, to a separate discussion in which non-technical sources are surveyed, even if there is a grey area between the two categories.Footnote 126

As for pharmacology, at Gal. Meth. Med. 13.21 (10.930 K.) various methods of purging are proposed for diseases that involve humoral excess, phrenitis among them: fasting, phlebotomy, washing and the application of oxyrrhodinum, a mixture of vinegar and rose oil, to the head. The latter, a mixture of rose oil and low-quality wine or vinegar, is a recurrent recipe mentioned at Simpl. Med. 3.9 (11.559 K.) as a remedy often recommended for the initial stages of the disease, as well as at Comp. Med. Loc. (12.523–24 K.), where Galen reports that Apollonius ‘orders that vinegar be mixed with rose oil, as for the phrenitic and lethargic. At the beginning of diseases, most doctors usually employ that’, although he criticizes the lack of precise indications of the quantities recommended. Later he moves on to explaining the efficacy of this acrid mixture precisely in terms of its ability to reach deep beneath the skin:

In the case of phrenitics, since all the external parts of the cranium are insensitive, as are the skin and the surrounding pericranial membrane, some conveniently begin by mixing old wine/vinegar, following the principle I exposed at length in my treatise on pharmacology when I said that it is appropriate for conditions which are deep seated within the body (tais en tōi bathei tou sōmatos ginomenais diathesesin) to apply different pharmaka from those destined for illnesses which are superficial (tōn epipolēs ginomenōn diatheseōn).

Phrenitis is then a ‘deep’ illness, and suitable substances should be chosen for it, capable of reaching deep under the ‘insensitive’ (apathes) layer of the cranium.Footnote 127

The acrid recipe is also found in the De materia medica of the famed Greek doctor and botanist Pedanius Dioscorides (first century ce), who recommends, as others do as well, ‘combining old wine/vinegar and rose oil as ointments for the lethargic, phrenitic, skotomatic, epileptic, those with chronic cephalgism, paralytics, etc.’ (Mat. Med. 3.78.2, 91.10–13 Wellmann). When speaking of ‘cow-parsnip’ (sphondylion), he further claims that ‘when drunk, it can cure hepatic diseases, hicterus, … epileptics, hysterical suffocation … Together with oil in embrocations to the head, it applies to phrenitics, lethargics, headaches’ (Mat. Med. 3.76, 88.9–89.5 Wellmann). Dioscorides generally discusses lēthargos and phrenitis in succession when affections involving the head are at issue: at Mat. Med. 3.38 (50.7–51.11 Wellmann) we find a special preparation for both, while at Mat. Med. 1, 103, 96.1–3 Wellmann ‘inhaled seed of pennyroyal moves to cleansing, as a plaster resolves headache, and is used for soaking with oil and vinegar in phrenitis and lēthargos’.Footnote 128

Another category of pharmacological remedy targets the need to restore a state of peace and quiet. In the Galenic Ther. 15 (14.271 K.) we read that ‘often the theriakē [a powerful animal-based remedy] halted the derangement in phrenitic patients (parakopas gennaiōs epausen), bringing about sleep, and through sleep making the troubles of the mind and the entanglements of nightmares (tas tēs gnōmēs tarachas te kai peripolkas phantasias) cease’. Severus Iatrosophista (second–fourth centuries ce?) in his De instrumentis infusoriis seu clysteribus ad Timotheum (18.12–19 Dietz) follows the same principle by targeting the head with specific herbal ingredients:

Another use of the kolokynthis is for the kentaurion; for it brings specific, so to speak, topical relief for affections of the head (tois peri kephalēn pathesin) … This is most helpful for phrenitics; at best it works marvellously for those with karos, mania and melancholia, most of all for those whose brain abounds in excretions (epi tōn perittōmatikon enkephalon echontōn).

This formulation confirms that in this period phrenitis is finally accepted as a disease of the head with humoral manifestations (here the abundant excretions).

The use of wine is controversial in cases of mental disturbance, as is stated clearly by Caelius Aurelianus in his remarks on its inappropriateness in critical phases of phrenitisFootnote 129 and on the importance of using it in moderation. At Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 5.1,Footnote 130 Galen is more open in this respect, but he also acknowledges the crucial importance of recognizing exactly the correct time and quantity. He writes, a bit self-evidently:

If giving wine should be beneficial, giving it will help. If, however, upon giving it at the wrong moment it causes paraphrosynē or phrenitis, acting as pathogenic, then it is neither healthy nor a help. So who is responsible for determining the benefit? Clearly the one person who can establish the right moment. And how do the Greeks refer to this person? Well, is it not clear to everyone that he is called ‘the doctor’? So the doctor is more powerful than wine when it comes to the preservation of health and action.

A similar concern is shared in a Problem in ps.-Alexander of Aphrodisias, where the author wonders: ‘Why can both water and wine have a trigger effect when given at the wrong moment in cases of fever, and cause phrenitis (phrenitin kataskeuazei) despite being opposite substances (for water is cold, while wine is hot)?’ (Probl. 1.96).

The psychotherapeutics for phrenitic patients, the chapter of the history of the disease to which a modern reader can perhaps best relate, is most attended to by authors whose anatomical, localized orientation was less strong or whose physiological account was more flexible: Asclepiades (as far as we can tell from the little we know directly about his clinical practices), Celsus and Caelius Aurelianus,Footnote 131 as we have seen, but also Aretaeus, whose take on localization was more fluid than that in others. These authors offer the richest discussions. Aretaeus has much to contribute regarding psychotherapy for these patients, as well as describing the cures their bodies require. These include first the typical corporeal interventions: dietetic measures, moderate venesection, the consumption of liquid food, and pharmacological preparations appropriate to fevers. Then there are localized measures: cooling the head by means such as damp applications and fomentations is a central feature – the head should not be warm – but anything moist should be kept away from the neck and the nerves that depart from it. The head also receives massages on the temples and ears, with effects that are emotional and psychological as well, targeting the predisposition to furious anger in these patients: ‘For by stroking their ears and temples, wild beasts are overcome, to make them cease from their anger and fury’ (94.28–29 Hude). The hair should be cut (96.16 Hude), again to keep the head fresh. In parallel, however, localized attention is directed to the chest in agreement with the double positioning of phrenitis in this author: the hypochondria and belly (hē koiliē) (95.3 Hude), the liver (hēpar, 95.9 Hude), as well as the spleen (splēn, 95.13 Hude), receive embrocations and cataplasms drenched in various substances. Moreover, the bowels (hē koiliē) should be stimulated, since these patients are often constipated (96.2–3 Hude). Galen, on the other hand, assigned cognitive and psychotherapeutic therapies to a separate class of emotional complaints, those discussed in his ethical writings, and once phrenitis had been classified as a hard-wired bodily disease, he disregarded the psychology of its healing process almost entirely.

After Galen: Summary and Consolidation

All late-antique nosology after Galen is massively shaped by the work of the physician from Pergamum, at least in the ‘flag topics’ in regard to which he made full use of his argumentative powers; phrenitis is certainly one of those. The topics that have already emerged regularly in regard to the definition of our disease are the encephalic localization (brain, meninges or the area around them; within the brain, the ventricular location becomes a topic); inflammation and overheating;Footnote 132 and humoral imbalances. In terms of the manifestations of the disease, sleep, hallucination and derangement, along with fever, dominate. The therapeutics elaborate on those already seen, with a combination of dietetics and pharmacological, environmental and occupational psychotherapeutics.

In post-Galenic medical authors, the most extensive sources on phrenitis are of a compilatory sort, found in authors usually defined as ‘encyclopaedists’: Oribasius (fourth century ce),Footnote 133 who does not however discuss phrenitis extensively in the extant portion of his main work, the Medical Collections, but summarized the topic in the Synopsis to Eustathius; Alexander of Tralles (sixth century ce); Aetius of Amida (Libri Medicinales, fifth–sixth century ce); and Paul of Aegina (seventh century ce). All of these discuss phrenitis, mostly elaborating on previous sources (Galenic and other), but in some cases inserting additional details. It is to a large extent through the versions ‘digested’ by these authors that the earlier medical tradition is preserved for clinical use for several centuries to come, through the Middle Ages and beyond. Despite their derivative and largely unoriginal nature in terms of simple content, therefore, their role is fundamental for the reception of Graeco-Roman medicine in postclassical and medieval times.Footnote 134 The following are, in more detail, the key topics they highlight when it comes to phrenitis.

The Centrality of the Brain and its Ventricles

Oribasius takes the encephalic location of phrenitis for granted. Elaborating on the Galenic ventricular articulation and encephalic localization more generally,Footnote 135 at Coll. Med. (Libri incerti, 159.19–23 Raeder) he firmly defines phrenitis as damage to the first part within the tripartite model of the living body (brain, heart, liver).Footnote 136 Likewise, AetiusFootnote 137 (whose writing on phrenitis is much more extensive) presents the brain as the most straightforward and clear localization of the disease in his discussion of the doctrine of Poseidonius of Byzantium (Medical Books 6.2, 125.4–128.5 Olivieri).Footnote 138 The disease is here ‘an inflammation of the meninges which surround the brain, accompanied by acute fever which brings derangement and impairment of the mind (hē phrenitis phlegmonē esti tōn peri ton enkephalon mēningōn meta puretou oxeos parakopēn kai paraphoran tēs dianoias epipherousa)’ (125.4–6 Olivieri). A description of the damage caused by phrenitis to the three ventricular areas of mental functioning, engendering different variants of the disease, familiar from the Galenic discussion, follows:Footnote 139

There are now very many kinds of phrenitis, but the most important are three: for some are damaged only in the imaginative faculty, but in them the logistikon and memory are preserved; or only the logistikon is damaged, but the imaginative and memory are spared; or the damage is in the phantastikon and logistikon, while memory is spared. When memory is damaged in diseases with fever, by and large the logistikon and the phantastikon are damaged together with it. And so, when the frontal part of the brain alone is damaged, the phantastikon is harmed, while if the central cavity (tēs mesēs koilias) of the brain is damaged, there is a change in the logistikon, and when in the posterior part the back of the brain is damaged, it destroys the mnemonic faculty, and together with it also the other two in most cases. And so, in cases in which the phantastikon is damaged, they can judge correctly, but they have alien imaginations; in cases in which only the logistikon in damaged, they imagine correctly but do not judge properly; in those in which the mnemonic is damaged, they cannot recall anything of what happened previously, but they also cannot either imagine or judge correctly in most cases. It is appropriate, then, to apply the most medicament to the most damaged part, but not to neglect the others. (125.9–26 Olivieri)Footnote 140

Already at Libri Medicinales 5.72 (46.30–47.1 Olivieri) as well Aetius identifies a category of nervous diseases to which phrenitis belongs: ‘Some suddenly suffer from orthopnoea, oppression, lēthargos, phrenitis, parotid gland tumour, with spasms, tremors or apoplexia, and to summarize, the whole nervous system and the head suffer.’ Paul of Aegina’s chapter dedicated to phrenitis (3.6, 144.4–6 Heiberg) offers a similar formulation: ‘Phrenitis is an inflammation of the meninges, when the brain becomes inflamed together with them, or when there is an unnaturally overheated state in it.’

The Survival of the Chest Localization and Pathology

Aetius, in his compilation, mentions the ‘split’ location of phrenitis – encephalic as well as in the torso – but does so indirectly, on the occasion of the mirror discussion of lēthargos, according to Archigenes and Poseidonius. At 6.3 (128.6–10 Olivieri) he describes two versions of the disease, one located in the phrenes and splanchna, the other in the brain:

There are two types of lēthargos, for in some cases the primary affection (prōtopathēsanta) in the phrenes and splanchna leads to sympathy (eis sympatheian agei) with the brain, while in another the primary affection begins in the brain, and in some cases it attacks straight at the beginning of the disease, in others through a change from one of the other acute diseases.

It is significant that the discussion of lēthargos that follows presents many of the well-known points of complementarity with phrenitis. More explicitly, at 5.48.13 (29.20–21 Olivieri) Aetius speaks of the relationship between phrenitis and yet more diseases, saying that haemorrhages through the nose often resolve phrenitis but not lēthargos or peripleumonia, again pointing at the parallel with a lung disease, exposing the lasting trace of the archaic association with the chest.Footnote 141

Paul of Aegina’s chapter dedicated to phrenitis (3.6, 144.8–28 Heiberg) explicates the possibility of sympathy with the diaphragm, again following Galen in On the Affected Places 5.4:

The cause of this disease is an excess either of blood or of blood containing yellow bile, sometimes even yellow bile being overcooked and mutating into black bile, in which case the phrenitis is most severe; it occurs when the brain suffering together with the diaphragm through the nerves maintains the affection through the nerves that are spread through it. The derangement (parakopē) that comes at the height of burning fevers or arises through sympathy with the stomach is not phrenitis but simply a paraphrosynē But if the phrenitis develops through sympathy with the phrenes, then the breathing is anomalous and it pulls up the hypochondria and these have considerable heating, just as they in turn, because of the brain, display heating and flushing in the face and full blood vessels.Footnote 142

Alexander of Tralles’ discussion of phrenitis at 1.13 (509–27 Puschmann, Peri phrenitidos) uniquely emphasizes the controversy regarding the localization as a well-known point of conflict. This is an important bit of information, since it acknowledges something about phrenitis which is hidden in plain sight in most other authors in this period: its problematic location.

That phrenitis is one of the most acute and dangerous diseases (tōn oxytatōn esti kai epikindynotatōn pathōn), everyone agrees. Whence it arises (hothen de synistatai), and under which condition suffered by the brain, and which part [of it] is affected, and about the therapy for the disease – everyone treats this as controversial

(ti paschontos tou enkephalou kai poiou merous autou kai peri tēs therapeias tou pathous, touto pasin amphisbēteitai). (1.13, 509.3–6 Puschmann)

Later the question of the phrenitic location is tackled and resolved by dismissing it:

The main signs of phrenitis are of such a kind and magnitude. From the start, the cause is in the brain; for phrenitis proper does not arise from affection of any other part, unlike what some think, that phrenitics become so from an inflammation of the diaphragm. This is not true, but once the brain itself is inflamed (kai autos ho enkephalos epeidan phlegmainēi) it causes the powerful derangements, as are characteristic of cases of phrenitis (hōs eoikenai phrenitisin).

(511.17–20 Puschmann)

The Relation of phrenitis to lēthargos and other Diseases

The traditional association is perpetuated by all these authors and remains central in Byzantine and medieval medicine as well. Oribasius (Syn. ad Eust. 8.1.2 = 244.8–11 Raeder) pairs phrenitis and lēthargos as diseases which attract similar therapeutic measures, mostly phlebotomy and applications with oxyrrhodinum. The two are seen by him as mirror images and capable of curing each other (Coll. Med. 45.30.55 = 195.30–33 Raeder): ‘Phrenitis is a cure (iamata) for lēthargos, and lēthargos tames those who are continuously out of themselves and undoubtedly phrenitic (aparalogistōs phrenitikous).’

At 6.2 Aetius as well mentions lēthargos as parallel to phrenitis: ‘For mostly in those who, coming from a phrenitis, have been cooled through narcotic pharmaka, there is a change to lēthargos’ (128.10–12 Olivieri). At 6.3 (= 131.16–19 Olivieri) he reports in regard to Archigenes and Poseidonius ‘about katochos and katalepsis’, diseases seen as a combination of phrenitis and lēthargos already in Galen:Footnote 143 ‘You will find that there is a disease in the middle between phrenitis and lēthargos, which is a kind of paranoia or parakopē (eidos paranoias ē parakopēs). Doctors usually called it katochē or katalepsis because of the settling humour, especially melancholic.’ Again at 6.4, in regard to patients with katochos, who manifest symptoms similar to phrenitics, he says: ‘Sometimes they scratch the nearby walls and speak foolishly (haplōs eipein), in ways not at all similar to phrenitics or lethargics (oute phrenitikois to pan eoikasin oute lēthargois)’ (132.9–11 Olivieri). Paul of Aegina also underlines the contiguity with lēthargos: ‘And lēthargos, a form of damage affecting the logistikon, has the same location as phrenitis, I mean the head, but through an opposite substance. For it arises through moister and colder phlegm running through the brain’ (3.9.1 = 147.6–8 Heiberg). He too mentions the disease katochos as a comparable ailment: ‘We have already clarified the substance of the disease phrenitis in the chapter on this disease. But [consider now] the signs that are on the whole common somehow to phrenitis and lēthargos, as the opposite substance prevails’ (3.10.1 = 149.1–5 Heiberg). Most interesting, Alexander of Tralles (1.17 = 591.10–12 Puschmann) identifies a link between melancholia and phrenitis, where some patients with melancholia can display phrenitic behaviour: ‘Some of them (the melancholic) laugh all the time and their imagination is always full of hilarity, while others appear to suffer from anger and tension, as in the case of those who are called phrenitic (phrenitikois onomazomenois)’. Here ‘phrenitic’ already appears to embody a type, despite the fact that earlier literature had repeatedly recognized and classified different typologies for the behaviour of such patients;Footnote 144 Galen in particular described the comatose, passive type alongside the aggressive one. The profile offered by Alexander is that of the furious, violent madman, the ‘so-called phrenitic’.

The existence of different versions of the disease phrenitis is thematized in these authors as well. Alexander of Tralles in his discussion (Peri phrenitidos) follows Galen in distinguishing phrenitis from paraphrosynē:

What is the cause of phrenitis? Phrenitis proper arises from yellow bile, whenever going up it causes inflammation (phlegmonē) around the brain or its meninx (peri ton enkephalon ē tēn en autōi mēninga). For before it goes up and fixes itself, it causes not phrenitis but paraphrosynē.

He continues:

For the form of phrenitis is not only one, but [there can be] also different ones. In one, the ochre bile (hē ōchra cholē) establishes itself, and it is milder; another involves yellow bile (hē xanthē cholē), is much more severe and brings higher fevers; the third is most aggressive, called theriōdes, in which the yellow bile is uncontrollably overheated and overcooked.

(509.10–23 Puschmann)

He also mentions the ‘false phrenitis’ Galen describes, the peculiar state of ‘phrenitics who are already chronic’, and the issue of differential diagnosis. All these authors engage with such ‘false phrenitis’, which will be picked up by medieval medicine and, with the discomfort with definition it betrays, constitutes an interesting point of taxonomic maturity.

Therapeutics

Aetius reports on the therapeutics for phrenitis in general and independent of locus affectus, and regardless of the ventricular localization of the illness he had explored; as we have often noted, these are the more holistic and psychotherapeutic kinds of measures. Detailed suggestions are accordingly offered about the ideal environment for the disturbed patients (6.2 = 125.27–126.6 Olivieri):

Now it is necessary to speak of the care for the phrenitic (as a whole). It is necessary to let the patient lie down in winter in a warm house, and in the summer in a fresh one, and to order him and the others in the house or nearby to maintain a calm environment. And those who are made worse by light should lie in a dark home, while those who are instead made calm by light should be in a well-lighted home.

Aetius also mentions venesection (although for him it should be practised cautiously),Footnote 145 purging of the stomach and embrocation of the head with warm rose extract,

For when the meninges are inflamed, neither the cold nor the very hot are harmless. Because the cold, on the one hand, clogs the pores and hinders the residues in the head from flowing through, while the very hot, on the other hand, doubles the inflammation, so that in the summer one must apply rose oil, especially lukewarm with a little vinegar, but in winter rather warm.

(126.20–127.1 Olivieri)

In this summary, Aetius combines traditional physiological measures with classic remedies from the tradition of soft medicine for the mentally disturbed: the importance of a particular environment, the role played by calm, the modulation of light and darkness. Elsewhere in his Libri Medicinales Aetius summarizes the manifestations and therapy of phrenitis and lēthargos combined: at 1.146 (72.15–19 Olivieri) he discusses pain in the head and its therapies in chronic cases of lēthargos and phrenitis and reports on the use of oxyrrhodinum for both, since ‘it stops the upsurges of blood’. Combining a psychotherapeutic tradition with the more strongly deterministic Galenic account, when he returns to therapy at 3.6 (= 264.1–5 Olivieri), he recommends use of a hammock for patients weakened by fever or hellebore, but also for phrenitics. Unlike Galen’s practice, psychotherapeutics and soft measures are combined with physiological interventions.

Paul of Aegina as well offers a combination of bodily measures (venesection, pharmaceutical interventions, head embrocations) and environmental and other psychotropic remedies, for example the creation of a suitable ambience, modulating light and darkness, and soothing or binding patients as necessary. Here Paul offers an especially competent summary of the character of the phrenitic, based on Galen and others:

The patient should be placed in a location with moderate light and temperature, after any colourful picture has been removed (for such things bring distress), where some concerned friends should visit and provide suitable company, sometimes addressing them gently, other times startling them with harsh remarks.

(3.6.2 = 145.12–16 Heiberg)

Some comments appear attentive to social distinctions and a consciousness of class:

And in cases of akinēsia, you must remember to leave space, if some are very rich (zaploutoi), for them to be supported/helped by slaves (dia paidōn), whereas otherwise they should be bound tight with ropes (desmois perisphingomenoi); for disorderly movement (ataktos kinēsis) of the dynamis can bring about a synkopē (synkoptikē estin).

(3.6.2 = 145.31–146.1 Heiberg)

In a different version, the feet should be fastened with ropes, but not tightly, and examined/palpated for the sake of preventing spasms (3.6.2 = 146.2–3 Heiberg). To conclude, ‘it is important to aid the recovery of phrenitics by avoiding excess of wine, strong emotional alterations (orgas), excessive food and most of all exposure to the sun (hēliokaias)’ (3.6.2 = 146.17–18 Heiberg).

Alexander of Tralles gives similar indications: again venesection and embrocation of the head with rose oil and vinegar, especially if hallucinations become more severe. There are also specific indications regarding houses (519 Puschmann):

One must consider the house in which the patient spends his time, so that the air should not be too thick or humid or cold or the least bit hot, lest a thickening of the pores affect the head or an overflow, but it should be quite temperate, so that in the good mixture the psychic pneuma can be tempered and relax. Let it also be more light than dark, so that through his perception the patient might be able to gain awareness of matters familiar to him

(hōste dia tēs aisthēseōs eis synaisthēsin erchesthai tōn synēthōn ton kamnonta).

The same psychological and social advice returns:Footnote 146

For this reason, some friends, the closest, should also stay close to him, so that he will respect their mild advice when he interacts with them. Nor should any person of the household or any relative with whom he has had reason for pain or anger be allowed to enter; for this is a trigger and causes disturbance and is a clear cause of strong upsetting. Nor should friends visit in a crowd, since many people simply become a cause of much confusion, and in addition they make the air thicker with their breathing moistly. They should watch out not to move in a scattered manner but gently, lest they hit the bed and move it; for this is exacerbating, and among other things it deprives the patient of sleep.

Finally, massage and physical interaction can do some good:

Those present should hold all the limbs firmly but gently, and calmly massage them, especially in the lower part, and especially when the patient suffers spasms. The legs should be tied with bandages, since this procedure turns the (pathological) substance downwards and also makes the cramps milder. Even better is to foment the extremities after rubbing.

In addition, dietetic details are offered which cannot be summarized here (519.6–521.3 Puschmann). Wine (525–27 Puschmann), generally considered a fortifying but strong substance, even dangerous, remains a point of therapeutic controversy. Alexander too recommends caution: ‘(One should) venture to give phrenitics wine not treated with gypson, in cases when the trouble with sleeping is serious and their strength is fading and the fevers are no longer vehement or very hot, but there appears to be a form of coction in the urine’ (525.28–527.1 Puschmann). It is especially appropriate to give wine to those who were already accustomed to drinking it while healthy. Here Alexander introduces a note regarding the character of the phrenitic: ‘In addition to these, it is appropriate to give wine to everyone who suffers from paraphrosynē with moderation, for it changes their thymos and their angry disposition into benevolence, and brings sleep by producing “coction of food” (= digestion) quickly, and promotes the recovery of the whole body’ (527.4–8 Puschmann). He also refers to the gastric area as relevant: ‘In cases in which the inflammation in the hypochondria is not severely fierce and the dynamis is not fading, I strongly urge giving wine.’ In this case, in fact, the benefit will exceed the damage. Fundamental with wine is balancing the benefits and the risks, a calculation which ultimately lies with the physician. This repeats the point already made by Galen:Footnote 147 for Alexander, ‘the doctor is stronger than wine’ and ‘it is the task of the doctor to measure and judge such matters (iatrou d’ esti to metrein kai krinein ta toiauta)’ (527.17 Puschmann).

Other Themes

Finally, several other elements from previous pathologies are retained by these compilers; their presence is fundamental for the future portrayal of these patients. The quality of urine (mentioned for example by Aetius at 5.37 = 22.26–23.4 Olivieri) remains important as an indicator. The same is true of the pulse (Paul at 2.11.24c = 93.4–8 Heiberg) and for the whole variety of clinical manifestations, largely traditional: neurological (on our definition), sensory, motoric (alteration of sleep patterns, spasms, hallucinations, tremors), psychological (strong emotions, anxiety, torpidity), behavioural (crocydism, aggression, recklessness), sometimes with additions which appears less technical in their provenience. Alexander of Tralles, for instance, stands out for reporting a belief about prophecy (509–11 Puschmann):

Signs of emerging phrenitis. What signals impending phrenitis are most of all a continuous and intense state of troubled sleep (synechēs kai epitetamenē agrypnia), troubled sleep and leaping up, and appearances of images as in dreams, such as to make some people conjecture that they are aware of the future and are attempting to offer predictions (hōste kai tinas hyponoein eidenai ta mellonta kai prolegein ethelein).Footnote 148

The usual manifestations (aggression, hallucinations, crocydism, altered respiration) accompany this; these appear also in Paul of Aegina (144–46 Heiberg).

Conclusion

The extent and relative position of phrenitis in nosological treatises, and Galen’s constant – indeed, overwhelming – reference to it as a paradigmatic mental and acute disease, make it apparent that this is one of the most powerfully conceptualized disorders in this period, clearly codified and readily recognized as experienced in the ancient world, especially in the first centuries of our era. This state of affairs is corroborated by Galen’s influence, but antecedent tendencies and independent strands are also visible.

To summarize the medical doctrines elaborated over the course of these six centuries of medical history, the defining topics of our disease are, from a strictly physiological point of view, fever, troubled sleep (agrypnia), a specific pulse and sensory disturbance. Vis-à-vis localization, the brain (and its ventricles) and membranes are central, with the nerves, the diaphragm and the hypochondria involved by sympathy, along with the stomach. Finally, the depth of the affection, reaching beneath the surface of the skull far into the enkephalon, is important. Behaviourally, an aggressive and disordered ‘type’ emerges. Its markers are spasm and crocydism; being startled and disordered, but also comatose and weak; sudden changes and behaviour out of character for the patient; a lack of awareness of one’s own physiology (notably, urination) and of one’s state of illness altogether; a propensity to sudden anger and aggression; supernatural strength and ‘tension’; and nonsensical laughter.

In theoretical terms, different ‘phases’ of the disease are recognized and various types thereof. Phrenitis can be primary (‘idiopathic’ or ‘protopathic’) or secondary (by sympathy); genuine, mixed or ‘false’; and three types can be distinguished, depending on the damage it causes. Its relationship to lēthargos is confirmed and elaborated, while the diaphragmatic version of the disease is included but marginalized. These points all confirm a strong conceptualization and a substantial investment in taxonomy. In humoral terms, pathological centrality is given to yellow bile, ochre bile, blood and putrefaction of bodily fluids. Physiologically, heat and inflammation are key: phrenitis remains first and foremost a fever. It is a summertime, dry disease (bringing thirst, tremors, a dry tongue), and overheating characterizes it physiologically, seasonally and environmentally. In a metaphysical sense, finally, the themes of hallucination, heightened senses and even prophecy give the suffering individual a touch of the extraordinary.

This long chapter has taken us deep into the details of medical and biological reflection. To complete the picture, a key question awaits, which involves the status of phrenitis as experience and popular concept outside the world of medical professionals. The elements listed above prove useful building blocks for the powerful allegorical construct ‘phrenitis’ in the centuries to come. But medicine is not the only influence here: the ethical reflections offered by philosophers writing in Greek and Latin at the beginning of our era are also a fundamental set of sources, which converge with the medical material to produce the description of the phrenitic in post-classical European culture, as we will see in Chapter 7.

Footnotes

1 A good overview of the vulgate view of the disease in the early centuries of our era is offered by the ps.-Galenic Introductio seu Medicus (second century ce), which should perhaps be understood as a school handbook of medicine (see Reference Petit and HorstmanshoffPetit 2010): ‘phrenitis is an ecstasis of the intellect with acute derangement (ekstasis dianoias meta parakopēs sphodras) and nonsensical motions of the hands, crocydism and carphology, and a high fever. It mostly arises from a cause such as excess of bile. It fixes itself in the brain, or meninges, or as some say in the phrenes, which is how the diaphragm is referred to (synistatai de peri enkephalon, ē mēningas, ē hōs tines legousi peri phrenas, ho diaphragma kaleitai). This is the appropriate therapy, if one can prognosticate it from its beginning: phlebotomy, cupping, blood-letting, clysters and abstinence from food as appropriate. Once the disease is established, soporific embrocations and sleep-inducing ointments and a wet diet’ (14.732–33 K.). Cf. Reference DevinantDevinant (2020) 169 on the ‘non-Galenism’ of this schematization, and on what, he warns, is the apparent stability, the ‘stabilité de surface’ in the medical authors of the first centuries ce (183 n. 344), perhaps with some overstatement, as other authors, especially those discussed in terms of delocalization in Chapter 3, share Galen’s pragmatism when it comes to nosological discussion; 158 on the sole (dubious) passage in Mot. Musc. 2.6 (35.13–20 Rosa = 4.445.8–446.1 K.) where Galen appears to suggest that phrenitis can be categorized as a ‘disease of the soul’, a pathēma tēs psychēs.

2 See Chapters 3, 6 and 8.

3 On patient reports and their problematic nature in ancient medicine, see Reference ThumigerThumiger (2015), (Reference Thumiger2018c); the discussions in Petridou and Reference ThumigerThumiger (2015).

4 See Chapter 3.

5 In medical contexts, phrenitis is not only generally considered a central example of an important disease, but is also evoked out of context as a ‘typical’ disease, as in Soranus Gyn. 3.1 (94, 13–15 Ilberg): diseases are defined as states ‘against nature’, whereby phrenitis or lēthargos are examples of pathological states which are ‘partial’, i.e. ‘localized’ (merikon) and ‘acquired’ (hypobebēkos).

6 This is Temkin’s classic formulation (1973), variously re-qualified by more recent scholarship: see e.g. Reference Bouras-VallianatosBouras-Vallianatos (2019) and other discussions in that collection.

7 On this author’s doxography, see Reference van der Eijk and Eijkvan der Eijk (1999a).

9 And notably unlike classical medicine, where the reverse is the case: univocal signs generate or are expressed in the disease label through a one-way move.

10 See above, p. 108.

11 A traditional move, according to Celsus; cf. the later treatise usually included in the Hippocratic Corpus Seven (Hebd. 51, 76.84–89 Roscher = 8.670.15–17 L.).

12 Cf. Celsus 124.11–26 Marx, on provoking them with intentional errors or announcing happy news.

13 On touch in the Hippocratic tradition, see Reference KosakKosak (2015); Reference ThumigerThumiger (2020a) generally on ‘psychotherapeutic’ measures; and the classic Reference EntralgoEntralgo (1970) 159–72. The class specification returns in Paul of Aegina as well (3.6.2, 145.31–146.1 Heiberg; see below, p. 180).

15 And several traits in common with pneumonia: see Chapter 2, pp. 22, 32 n. 27, 45.

16 For a comprehensive discussion of the signs of phrenitis, see Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1981/2006) 71–100; Reference CentanniCentanni (1987).

17 See Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1987/2010) 34–36 on fever as a differential sign in phrenitis, and more generally 67–69; Reference HamlinHamlin (2014) 17–88, 43–53 on Galen.

18 Reference HamlinHamlin (2014) 6–12, 24–30.

19 The same point returns at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.1 (5.3–5 Diels = 16.493 K.): ‘All those are said to be manic (mainesthai) who are deranged without fever, those with fever to be phrenitic (phrenitizein).’ On the two types of paraphrosynē, mania and phrenitis, see Reference Singer, Thumiger and SingerSinger (2018) 389–90.

20 More on the topic at Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 1.29 (56.19–57.15 Wenkebach = 17a.889–91 K.).

21 On the course of fevers, and phrenitis as an example, see also Dieb. Decr. 2.13 (9.897 K.), where Galen mentions Diocles in agreement.

22 At Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.34 (132.4–5 Wenkebach = 17a.686 K.), Galen writes that phrenitis and ardent fever have a common cause, but differ in their locus affectus (koinēn … echonta tēn aitian, diapheronta de tois paschousi topois): the first is in the liver and stomach, and especially its mouth, the second in the brain. On this topic, see also Reference AhonenAhonen (2014) 156–58.

23 For a full discussion of the localization of fevers in the body, with special reference to the hypochondrion, see Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 2 (63.10–64.23 Wenkebach = 17a.580–82 K.).

24 Some of these ‘psychotherapeutics’ have already been discussed with reference to Celsus and Caelius Aurelianus.

25 For criticism, see also ps.-Galen, De Optima Secta ad Thrasybulum liber 22 (1.167 K.): ‘Besides this, they also stupidly take over the idea of darkness for phrenitics. Because if darkness exacerbates stegnōsis (stoppage), exacerbated stegnōsis exacerbates derangement.’

26 See Chapter 2, p. 28.

28 17.1–18.3 Diels = 16.517–20 K.

29 Another difficult term, that does not map precisely onto our notion of ‘muscle’. See the introduction by Reference Debru, Garofalo and DebruDebru (2005); Reference Gregoric and KuharGregoric and Kuhar (2014) on the problems posed by neura and muscles in Aristotle.

30 The distinction closely resembles the famous one drawn by Jaspers and his school between ‘content’ and ‘form’ in madness, which was then taken up by the history of psychopathology (cf. Reference JaspersJaspers 1923/1963, 58–59). Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1987/2010) explores the partially superimposable distinction between ‘illusion’ and ‘delusion’ vis-à-vis appraisal of reality; see also Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1983) on the ancient philosophical and medical traditions.

31 Localization in the brain, and the separate but related topic of ventricular localization, is a difficult chapter in the history of medicine, evidence for it being episodic and unsystematic. See Reference YoungYoung (1970) on the history of localization in modern science; Reference Grunert, Althoff, Föllinger and WöhrleGrunert (2002) 152–66; Reference GreenGreen (2003); Reference RoccaRocca (2003) 245–47 for a summary of the material, and 196–98, although he dismisses the present Galenic evidence for subdivision of different areas of the brain in favour of a view of Galen’s doctrine as involving ‘the hegemonic faculties’ of the brain as a whole; the observations in Reference DebruDebru (2010); Reference GuentherGuenther (2015) for the place in history of modern neurology; Reference WrightWright (2016) 129–30, 182–94, discussing Nemesius (as the earliest occurrence), Posidonius and Galen, Reference Wright(2018); the essays in Reference MacLehoseAmbrosio and MacLehose (2018) on various chapters in the historical ‘imagi(ni)ng on the brain’ in Western cultures.

32 Galen refers to the case of the doctor Theophilus hallucinating pipe-players also at Symp. Diff. 1.4.3 (224.18–226.8 Gundert = 7.60–61 K.), in a discussion of kinds of paraphrosynē. See Reference KingKing (2013b) for this peculiar musical element as a topic in Greek stories of psychopathology.

33 See also Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.35 (134.14–16 Wenkebach = 17a.690 K.) on continuous derangement as phrenitic sign; cf. 3.47 (139.15–16 Wenkebach = 17a.700 K.).

34 On damage to memory in phrenitis, see Reference JuliāoJulião (2018) 228–35.

35 On ancient remarks about this phenomenon of ‘selective’ madness, see Reference ThumigerThumiger (2017) 60.

36 This is the Latin translation given in Kühn’s edition (Reference DurlingDurling 1961, n. 157, Vassaeus, Johannes), also interpreting the expression allot’ allon (ἄλλοτ’ ἄλλον) as locative, ‘regional’, conceptualizing the brain as an organ subdivided into functional areas.

37 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 27 (40.9–41.26 Diels = 16.565–68 K.).

38 The relevant passage is at De morbo sacro 14 (25.12–26.10 Jouanna = 6.387 L.).

39 On this famous passage, see also Reference DevinantDevinant (2020) 291–92.

40 Cf. Aretaeus, Morb. Chr. 1, 6 on mania, for a similar distinction regarding ‘another species of mania’, that of patients who have ‘a madness of judgement only; for in all other respects they are sane (kai esti tēs hypolēpsios he maniē mounon, ta d’ alla sōphroneousi)’ (43.31–44.1 Hude), but are in particular victims of ‘holy fantasies’ and religious fanaticism.

41 This patient, or a similar one, is also mentioned at Loc. Aff. 4.2 (8.226 K.) in a description of phrenitic behaviour due to impairment of the mental faculties: ‘A man who was confined to his house in Rome in the company of a young wool-worker rose up from his bed and went to the window, where he could be seen and could also watch the people passing by. He then showed them each of his glass vessels and demanded that they ask him to throw them down. The people laughed, clapped their hands, and told him to do so. Then the man grasped one vessel after the other and threw it down. The people laughed and screamed. Later he also asked whether they wanted him to throw down the wool-worker. And when they told him to do so, he complied. When the people saw the man fall from high up, they stopped laughing, ran to the fallen man, who was crushed, and lifted him up.’ On this anecdote, see also Reference DevinantDevinant (2020) 288–90.

42 On this passage, Reference VagelpohlVagelpohl (2023) ad loc.

43 On the problems raised by this Hippocratic passage, see Reference ThumigerThumiger (2017) 331–32.

44 Transliterated as Kymī.

45 I use this term with the caution expressed in Chapter 4, Footnote nn. 6, 26.

46 Or lack thereof, ‘slackness’, atoniai (ἀτονίαι)? Cf. Diels ad loc.: εὐτονίαι L, ἀτονίαι RT.

47 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.9, 24.25–28 Diels = 16.533 K. Cf. De trem. 8 (7.641–42 K.).

48 On this retrospectivity, see again Chapter 4, pp. 49–50.

49 186.8–187.4 Wenkebach = 17a.790–91 K.

50 Comm. Hipp. Epid. I, 2.56, 78.2–4 Wenkebach = 17a.153 K.

51 24.17–28 Diels = 16.533 K.

52 26.7–18 Diels = 16.536–37 K.

53 On which, see again Reference DevinantDevinant (2020) 169–90.

54 See Comm. Hipp. Prοrrh. I, 1.1 (6.27–7.1 Diels = 16.496–97 K.): ‘Those affected by lethargic kōma can in no way be considered phrenitic. Instead, the patients who are wakeful without kōma will be called phrenitics, when they are struck by the affection proper to the disease. It will be called phrenitis proper (hē akribēs) when yellow bile occupies the seat of the hēgemonikon … lēthargos has a different cause: the phlegm. Yet another different illness is typhōmania, a disease that arises when the two humours mix without one taking over the other, and without determining as a consequence a purely phrenitic or a purely lethargic state’; cf. Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 3.1 (107.17–108.5 Diels = 16.707–09 K.); Com. 2.12–14 (187.29–188.21 Mewaldt = 7.653–55 K.).

55 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.6, 22.13–16 Diels = 16.528 K.; see above, pp. 114–18.

56 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.1 (6.18–7.14 Diels = 16.496–97 K).

57 188 Mewaldt = 7.655–56 K.

58 This portion of the text is preserved only in a Latin translation.

59 Cf. Com. 1.4 (182.15–21 Mewaldt = 7.645–46 K.): ‘Hippocrates too was in doubt about the whole combination of symptoms [agrypnia and kōma], whether it was opportune to call them phrenitics, or what else. For one should avoid calling them phrenitics, because they are not yet deranged. But when all the symptoms appear to be phrenitic, the pain in the head, loins, hypochondrion and neck, one should not be afraid of mistakes or ignorance. No one will deny that these have an obvious probability (of being phrenitic), however not sufficiently.’ Again Com. 4.1 (192.12–19 Mewaldt = 7.663 K.), on a similar concern, the distinction between ‘comatose kataphora’ and ‘non-comatose phrenitis’; here, as elsewhere, phrenitis provides the ideal arena for methodological discussion.

60 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.4 (15.11–15 Diels = 16.514 K.).

61 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, i.5 (20.22–24 Diels = 16.525 K.). Cf. Loc. Aff. 5.4 (8.329–30 K.) ‘disturbed sleep, frightful and disturbed dreams, awful nightmares with screams and startling, forgetfulness’.

62 Comm. Hipp. Epid. I, 3.19 (132.22–23 Wenkebach = 17a.264 K.).

63 See also Comm. Hipp. Epid. III, 3.64 (146.16–147.3 Wenkebach = 17a.713 K.) ‘Comatose in particular were phrenitics and sufferers from kausos, but also in the case of all the other most important diseases, when they occur with fever. The comatose state creates a density of matter especially in those whose head is affected. It suffers this primarily in phrenitics, but in sufferers from kausos it occurs incidentally [or accidentally], for [in them] the heat of the fever brings up the bad fluids (tous mochthērous chymous) to the head (pros tēn kephalēn); in that case, those of the crude and cold type (hoi ōmoi kai psychroi) were abundant.’ I thank P. N. Singer for help with this translation.

64 12.6–7 Diels = 16.507 K.

65 36.4–16 Diels = 16.556–57 K.

66 35.18–29 Diels = 16.555 K.

67 131.16–23 Wenkebach = 17a.684–85 K.

69 36.6–16 Diels = 16.556–57 K.

70 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.19, 35.21–25 Diels = 16.555 K. ‘Whenever in a phrenitis a paraphrosynē generates a hot and dry affection, the dryness in it is transmitted to the pipe, making it rough, and the metallic voice (he phōnē klangōdēs) follows, just like a hoarse voice (branchōdēs) in cases of accumulated humidity, but not as identifying markers of phrenitis; for these occur in other diseases as well, nor do they occur continuously in cases of phrenitis.’ On hē phōnē klangōdēs, cf. Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.17, 34.12–17 Diels = 16.553 K. ‘Vomit with nausea is a symptom common to these cases with the malignant fevers, just like the metallic voice.’

71 De motu musc. 2.4 (32.24–27 Rosa = 4.438 K.), Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.28 (41.27–42.18 Diels = 16.568–70 K.).

72 Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.6 (22.23–24 Diels = 16.529 K.).

73 The tradition of urological prognostics had great success in the late-antique and Byzantine world, as exemplified by Theophilus Protospatharius’ seventh-century De urinis, with an overview of traditional doctrines. Stephanus in his In Magni Sophistae librum de urinis 11 (436.5–7 Bussemaker) writes that ‘abundant, thin and white urine passed during fevers signals an interruption in the quartan fever; for he passes thin, white urine during the peaks of fever due to the excess of phlegmatic bile in those who have an unnaturally cold liver’. Cf. ps.-Galen, De urinis ex Hippocrate, Galeno et aliis quibusdam 19.610.19 K. ‘In chronic diseases, by and large, there is transparent, white urine because of the state of weakness …; it signals blockage, as is clear in phrenitic cases’, and 19.621.17 K. ‘He passes thin, white urine also in burning fevers, and it signals sharp, severe phrenitis (phrenitida aploun megalēn)’.

74 28.14–30.14 Diels = 16.541–44 K.

75 15.18–25 Diels = 16.514–15 K.

76 17b.759–60 K.

77 What is being discussed here is the Hippocratic Aph. 4.72 (426.7–8 Magdelaine = 2.528 L.): ‘Those in whom urine is transparent, whitish, bad: it mostly appears in phrenitics.’

78 31.1–26 Diels = 16.545–47 K.

79 39.8–21 Diels = 16.562–63 K.

80 At Anonymus Parisinus 1.2.1 (3.23–24 Garofalo), phrenitis is indicated by ‘pulse doubled, small, thick; respiration continuous and not entirely dilating the chest’. On the phrenitic pulse, Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1981/2006) 86.

81 Cf. Caus. Puls. 4.14 (9.186 K.) ‘Spasmodic intermission in the movement and not stopping briefly throughout belongs to phrenitics, as when the heat takes over and the organs become hard’; De puls. ad Tirones 12 (8.483 K.) ‘The pulse of phrenitics is small; on some very rare occasions, it appears large and has a moderate tone. It is also hard and sinewy, frequent and very rapid. It also has something wavy. Sometimes it might appear to you to tremble slightly, and sometimes to cut off spasmodically’; and at Caus. Puls. 14 (9.185K.). ‘Just as the peripleumonic pulse is rarely double-beating, because it is least involved in hardness, so the phrenitic one is very rarely wavy, because it is least involved in softness.’

82 Cf. Rufus (first/second century ce) in Synopsis de pulsibus 6.4 (227.3–10 Daremberg) on the phrenitic pulse; 8.2.3 (230 Daremberg); ps.-Alexander of Aphrodisias, Probl. 4.25.1, where the rapid pulse of phrenitics is also mentioned and opposed to that of lethargics (hoi phrenitikoi men mikrosphyktoi, megalosphyktoi de hoi lēthargikoi).

83 On the ‘organs of respiration’ in Galen and the earlier tradition, see Reference DebruDebru (1996) 94–124, 211–42 on pathologies of respiration in ancient medicine.

84 At greater length, see Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.1 (4.1–9.6 Diels = 16.491–501 K.), where Galen assesses the association between respiration and the cognitive sphere, the muscular explanation and the mental-encephalic one (also Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.4, 13.25–20.9 Diels = 16.511–24 K.).

85 Cf. Prognosis through pulse 4.8 (9.405–12 K.) on lēthargos and other conditions, prognosis, respiration, mental states and sleep.

87 33.9–26 Diels = 16.550–52 K.

88 Galen even considers a textual variant that points in the direction of a lack of awareness of one’s disease or physiology: ‘Some wrote brachypoptai, meaning paying attention to/hearing the most exiguous sounds. And they say this is proven by the fact that he says “troubled by noise”, which means being in distress about matters that are quite exiguous (hypotopeisthai), i.e. “to be suspicious/hypersensitive”’ (33.23–26 Diels = 16.551–52 K.).

89 Compare how later, at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I, 1.28 (42.13–18 Diels = 16.569 K.), Galen insists that urine passed unawares ‘is a sign of an abundance of crude humours either being cooked or being filled with pneuma …, and not of phrenitis, although this can also happen at times in phrenitics, or not happen, just like any other symptom which is neither proper nor contrary to phrenitis’.

90 138.9–12 Wenkebach = 17a.698 K.

91 Galen seems to admit the existence of phrenitides caused by psychological, emotional circumstances, although, significantly, this remains only a hint: at Symp. Caus. 1.8 (7.144 K.), after a physiological claim regarding our disease, he inserts the corrective: ‘[This is the case for] those [phrenitides] at least that do not arise from pain or some anxiety (hosai ge mē dia lypēn ē tina phrontida synistantai).’

92 By this term, I refer to the titles in which Galen engages with human ethical flourishing and its preservation (i.e. those published in Reference Singer, Nutton, Davies and SingerSinger 2013).

94 34.7–15 Diels = 16.552–53 K.

95 Compare the corporis vana fortitudo mentioned by Caelius, Morb. Ac. (42.20 Bendz).

96 59.15–22 Diels = 16.605–06 K.

98 On this as recurring symptom (symptôm constant), see Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1981/2006) 82–86.

99 See Reference ThumigerThumiger (2017) 152–53 on these and on the neurology of this symptom; Reference WalsheWalshe (2016) 100 on the medical event; Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1987/2010) 124–26 on Galen and hallucinations in cases of crocydism and other phrenitis-relevant themes.

100 See p. 145.

101 Just as in other patients afflicted by an overflow of humours to the head, who see images distorted in size and colour; see also Alexander’s Comm. Arist. Metaph. 3.5 (312.21 Hayduck), where individuals with jaundice or phrenitis are telling examples of persons whose judgement and perception of size and colour are impaired.

102 See also Comm. Hipp. Aph. 7.12 (18a.112–13 K.) on the Hippocratic statement ‘phrenitis coming on peripleumonia, bad’: ‘Whenever peripleumonia arises due to a heated humour, sending up many vapours to the head, it fills the head with vapours and causes phrenitis.’

103 237.8–19 Heeg = 18b.73–74 K.

104 237.26–238.6 Heeg = 18b.75 K.

105 Thus explicitly Galen, Aretaeus, Caelius Aurelianus and the encyclopaedists. This distinction remains firm in the following centuries. See below pp. 243, 258, 261 on Avicenna and others; Reference PigeaudPigeaud (1987/2010) 67–69.

106 See Chapter 3.

107 97.23–28 Hude.

108 Cf. ‘heartburn’ (97.10 Hude).

109 See above, pp. 22, 23–27, 32.

110 351.4–8 Wenkebach = 17b.343–44 K.

111 The ps.-Galenic Definitiones Medicae (19.414–15 K.) confirm the importance of the theme of sleep and oppressive torpor, the katochos Galen discusses at length in various places, bringing together phrenitis and lēthargos: ‘katochos is lack of sensation of the soul with a fixing of the whole body. There are three types of katochos. For one is somnolent, which happens in lēthargos. The second is wakeful, in which tetanos and the so-called hysterikē pnix appear. The third kind of katochos is that which one would not inappropriately call phrenitic katochos. It arises from a mixture of two sicknesses, katochos and phrenitis, just as is the case with typhōmania.’

112 On the methodological complexity of Galen’s position vis-à-vis conceptualizing the ‘diseases of the soul’, with which we cannot engage here, see the important discussion in Reference DevinantDevinant (2020), with key conclusions at 298–302; also Reference DevinantDevinant (2018).

113 306.25–307.14 Helmreich = 15.802–03 K.

114 91.32–92.2 Wenkebach = 17a.182 K.

115 88.26–89.6 Wenkebach = 17a.175–76 K.

116 Cf. Comm. Hipp. Epid. I, 2.20 (58.22–59.21 Wenkebach = 17a.112–14 K.) on the connection between these two kinds of fever.

117 518.19–20 De Lacy = 5.695 K.

118 17b.645–46 K.

119 Commenting on Aph. 3.30 (408.11–13 Magdelaine = 4.500 L.): ‘for those beyond this age, wheezing, cases of pleuritis, cases of peripneumonia, lēthargos, phrenitis, kausos, cholera, chronic diarrhoea … cases of dysentery, haemorrhoids/haemorrhages’.

120 186.4–10 Mewaldt = 7.651 K.

121 Galen seems to distance his understanding most radically from the Hippocratic interpretation of phrenitis as a winter ailment, as his attempt to bring his predecessor into agreement with himself testifies. At Comm. Hipp. Epid. I, 2.76 (89.10–19 Wenkebach = 17a.176–77 K.), he comments on the discordant Hippocratic statement that ‘there were (a) few cases of phrenitis also in the summer’ (the majority, it seems to be implied, were normally in winter), and explains this as follows: ‘Part of [the summer], until the Dog [i.e. the heliacal rising of the star Sirius, in July–August, n.d.t.], was cold; but part, until Arcturus [the rising of the star α-Boötis, or Ursa Maior, in spring] was hot and dry. For this reason, the summer was not such as to cause replenishment of the head in this period, nor could the south wind, which arises around Arcturus until the equinox. Nor was the weather wet, moist or stable for some time in the period between the Dog and Arcturus. But (clearly) what [Hippocrates] says is that when abundant bile was poured into the regions around the head, then also cases of phrenitis occurred (hoti cholēs pollēs enechtheisēs en tois kata ton enkephalon chōriois kai phrenitides egenonto).’ On phrenitis and summer heat, see also ps.-Alexander of Aphrodisias, Probl. 1.76, which discusses the example of dogs maddened in the summer and evokes phrenitis: ‘Why do only dogs become mad (lyttōsin) in the summer? Because of the prolēpsis of the dry mixture: for they are dry by nature, and especially during the summer heat. And so the humid components and krasis in them burns ardently when they are heated and dried. They thus rave (mainontai) just as phrenitics do (kathaper phrenitiōntes).’ On the construct ‘sun disease’, see Appendix 1.

122 In his translation of this passage, Pfaff wrote ‘Schlaflosigkeit’ rather than ‘Schlafsucht’ (my lēthargos) because the single Arabic manuscript available to him contained the term sahar (cf. Comm. Hipp. Epid. VI, 506.8–11 Pfaff: ‘wo ich das Wesen der Epilepsie, der Aphasie, der Paralyse, der kalten Phrenesie, die Schlafsucht heißt, der heißen Phrenesie, der Melancholie, der Traurigkeit’, ‘I have presented the nature of epilepsy, aphasia, paralysis, cold phrenitis that is called lethargy, hot phrenitis, melancholy, sadness)’. The correct reading sahw, which corresponds to lēthargos and confirms my interpretation, is preserved in Ḥunayn ibn Isḥāq’s summary of the commentary, the Masāʾil. I thank Uwe Vagelpohl for this clarification; he translates 'absent-mindedness', however, which fails to express the symmetry of phrenitis-lēthargos as hot and cold brain fever respectively I am discussing here.

123 153.20–23 Wenkebach = 17a.725 K.

124 109.21–23 Wenkebach = 17a.984 K.

125 186.11–187.4 Wenkebach = 17a.791 K.

126 Cf. Chapter 6.

127 The lack of sensation of phrenitics vis-à-vis their locus affectus is interesting and a suitable bridge to the ethical and delocalized history of the disease; see pp. 109–10 and below, pp. 203–05.

128 Cf. Euporista 1.5 (154.5–12 Wellmann) along similar lines.

129 E.g. Morb. Ac. 1.1 (68.9–11 Bendz) concerning phrenitis.

130 255.17–24 Wenkebach = 17b.226–27 K.

131 See above, Chapter 3, pp. 80–81.

132 See e.g. ps.-Alexander of Aphrodisias, Probl. 2.67: excessive heat is again significant for phrenitic patients and the affection they suffer in the brain, and the state of the enkephalon is always central to this pathology.

133 On Oribasius, see Reference GäbelGäbel (2022) 4–5.

134 See below, Chapter 7.

135 Localization in the brain is exposed in sufficient detail in Galen when he discusses epilēpsia at Loc. Aff. 3.9 = 8.174–75 K., as well as at Comm. Hipp. Prorrh. I (see above, p. 142 n. 31).

136 In addition, in a discussion of embrocations (Coll. Med. 9.22.3, 24.19–22 Raeder) he explains that ‘one needs to know that in the case of phrenitics one should focus on the forehead and temples, and stay away from the top of the head and the posterior parts: for these do not bring about cooling, as the origin of the nerves is located there’.

137 On Aetius on diseases of the brain, see now at length Reference GäbelGäbel (2022).

138 A (perhaps) fourth-century medical author; cf. Reference GäbelGäbel (2020), (Reference Gäbel2022) 23–25.

139 See above, n. 135.

140 The localization in Nemesius, Nature of Man 13 (69.17–20 Morani; 13.54–65) is even more precise: ‘The organ of memory, too, is the posterior cavity of the brain, which they call the cerebellum and the enkranis, and the psychic pneuma within it’ (20); cf. Reference SiraisiSiraisi (1987) 212–14; Reference RoccaRocca (2003) 245–47; Reference AhonenAhonen (2014) 158 Footnote n. 77; Reference WrightWright (2016) 129–30, 182–94; Reference WrightWright (2018). On the reception of these localizations in the brain by a set of Arabic and Hebrew readers of Galen, see Reference WolfsonWolfson (1935) 74–77; Reference Marshall and MagounMarshall and Magoun (1998) 27–42 for an illustrated survey of the ventricles throughout the history of Western medicine.

141 See above, p. 22.

142 Cf. also 3.6.2 (145.25–27 Heiberg) on the sympatheia between the two parts.

143 See above, p. 142.

144 This bipolarity was traditional already in the Hippocratics, e.g. notably with melancholy; see Reference ThumigerThumiger (2017) 57–58.

145 On this, see also 3.14 (= 274.3–5 Olivieri).

146 As in Aretaeus; see above, p. 162.

147 See above, pp. 172–73.

148 The idea that the state of the body might influence dreams and their prophetic quality was reported by Aristotle, De divinatione per somnia; see especially 463b17–19 and 464a18–28 on the connection between mental inferiority or pathology and vivid, even prophetic dreams.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Phrenitic People
  • Chiara Thumiger, Cluster of Excellence Roots, Christian-Albrechts Universität zu Kiel, Germany
  • Book: <i>Phrenitis</i> and the Pathology of the Mind in Western Medical Thought
  • Online publication: 16 November 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009241311.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Phrenitic People
  • Chiara Thumiger, Cluster of Excellence Roots, Christian-Albrechts Universität zu Kiel, Germany
  • Book: <i>Phrenitis</i> and the Pathology of the Mind in Western Medical Thought
  • Online publication: 16 November 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009241311.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Phrenitic People
  • Chiara Thumiger, Cluster of Excellence Roots, Christian-Albrechts Universität zu Kiel, Germany
  • Book: <i>Phrenitis</i> and the Pathology of the Mind in Western Medical Thought
  • Online publication: 16 November 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009241311.005
Available formats
×