Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T02:37:33.295Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - The Ecological Niche

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2021

James Justus
Affiliation:
Florida State University

Summary

At least until Hubbell’s neutral theory emerged, no concept was thought more important to ecological theorizing than the niche. Without it – and its highly abstract definition by Hutchinson in particular – technically sophisticated and well-regarded theories of character displacement, community assembly, limiting similarity, and many others would seemingly never have been developed. To cite just one example among many, grasslands in the central plains of North America and Africa share a similar structure and exhibit similar dynamics because they are claimed to instantiate roughly the same system of niches, albeit with different species. The niche concept is also the centerpiece of perhaps the best candidate for a distinctively ecological law, the competitive exclusion principle. But the incongruous array of proposed definitions of the concept squares poorly with its apparent scientific centrality. I argue this definitional diversity reflects a problematic conceptual imprecision that challenges its putative indispensability in ecological theory. Recent attempts to integrate these disparate definitions into a unified characterization fail to resolve the imprecision. The niche is not the conceptual cornerstone of ecological science.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Philosophy of Ecology
An Introduction
, pp. 14 - 37
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Perhaps no concept has been thought more important to ecological theorizing than the niche. Without it, technically sophisticated and well-regarded accounts of character displacement, ecological equivalence, limiting similarity, and others would seemingly never have been developed. The niche is also widely considered the centerpiece of the best candidate for a distinctively ecological law, the competitive exclusion principle (see Chapter 2 on ecological laws).

The received view in ecology has therefore been that the niche is indispensable, despite occasionally vocal protests from a small minority. After all, the concept is often said to simply explicate the idea that species make their biological livelihoods in different ways, and what could be more central to ecology? Many (if not most) influential analyses in the 1960–1970s bore the “niche” label, often paying homage to Hutchinson’s (Reference Hutchinson1957) highly abstract definition in particular. Mechanistic models of resource consumption that predominated subsequent decades (e.g., Tilman Reference Tilman1982) are taken to extend and refine the same approach, the niche similarly at their core. More recently, Hubbell’s (Reference Hubbell2001) unified neutral theory certainly perturbed the prevailing assessment, but it fell far short of upending it (see Odenbaugh forthcoming). A prominent book responding to neutralist theories in favor of niche-based theorizing, for instance, proclaims that “the niche has provided and can continue to provide the central conceptual foundation for ecological studies” (Chase and Leibold Reference Chase and Leibold2003, 17).

In this case, however, the naysayers were right. The incongruous array and imprecise character of proposed definitions of the concept square poorly with its apparent scientific centrality. Rather than reflect innocuous semantic differences or a potentially useful integrative pluralism, this definitional diversity and imprecision reflects a problematic conceptual indeterminacy that challenges its putative indispensability in ecology. The niche has not and cannot – at least as it has been characterized thus far – do the substantive, foundational work it is claimed to do in ecology. The conceptual content tethered to the term “niche” is just too problematically disjoint and amorphous to play that role. Unsurprisingly, although the term frequently received lip service, the content specified in its proposed definitions actually contributed little to the analyses mentioned above.

This gap between conceptual aspiration and scientific practice permeates appraisals of ecological theorizing to the present in many different, multifaceted ways. This chapter focuses specifically on the concept’s origins in the work leading up to and in many ways culminating in Hutchinson’s highly abstract n-dimensional hypervolume definition. The same kind of shortcoming is exhibited throughout this development, for different reasons. Section 1 describes the emergence of the ecological niche in Joseph Grinnell and Charles Elton’s work. From the very beginning, the concept’s content was unmistakably disjoint: environments and how they impact species was one focus; how species function in communities, particularly via trophic interactions, was the other. Beyond the bivalent focus, the concept was also problematically imprecise. This point is illustrated by considering the contentious idea of “vacant” niches and the significant indeterminacy about their possibility.

Despite the widespread view that the niche concept is the centerpiece, Section 2 argues the niche concept is not the centerpiece of perhaps the best candidate for a distinctively ecological law, the competitive exclusion principle. (See Chapter 2 on ecological laws for an analysis of whether the principle should be considered a law.) Gause’s (Reference Gause1934) paramecium experiments and putatively mechanistic explanation of competitive dynamics with Lotka–Volterra equations are widely taken to supply the first compelling grounds for a niche-based version of the exclusion principle (see Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1978). But the evidence for this judgment is pretty thin. Gause’s explanation actually makes little use of niche ideas. His semantically suggestive – but thoroughly non-niche – term “vacant places” may have led many later commentators astray. And what little he did say about niches provides little guidance about how niche considerations might be brought to bear on models of competitive dynamics, via competition coefficients, for instance. This serious deficiency is a quite general problem, one shared by later attempts to characterize the concept, including the most influential definition of the concept in ecology.

That definition is Hutchinson’s n-dimensional hypervolume characterization of the niche, the focus of Section 3. As judged by the attention it received, his definition had an enormous impact on ecology. But judged by the content conveyed, the impact seems disproportionate. Hutchinson made highly questionable and significantly limiting assumptions in characterizing the concept, and at least one conceptual confusion seems to render the concept quite intractable. The most serious deficiency, however, is the same kind of conceptual indeterminacy exhibited by earlier attempts to pinpoint the concept. Chase and Leibold’s (Reference Chase and Leibold2003) more recent revival of the niche is problematic in the same way. Rather than convey information about community dynamics, information that helps represent and analyze those dynamics, the niche superfluously supervenes on them on their account of the concept.

Problems with the concept aside, the actual work done under the niche rubric could be useful, and frequently was. Being able to define the concept, or even reliably identify species’ niches, is not very important. What is important, potentially, is recognizing possible patterns across biological systems: even evolutionarily distant communities in different geographical regions sometimes (perhaps often) realize a similar causal structure. That commonality can then serve as a basis for extrapolation and generalization. Section 4 concludes by describing a defensible kind of community-level – as opposed to species-level – causal inference that might underlie Elton’s (and perhaps Grinnell’s) niche discussions. It also raises a general issue about how the utility of concepts should be gauged in science.

1 Grinnell and Elton’s Niches

The first director of the Museum of Vertebrate Zoology at the University of California at Berkeley, Joseph Grinnell, was not the first to use “niche” in an ecological sense,Footnote 1 but he was the first to do so with any significance. His most well-known paper doing so – the first ecological publication with “niche” in the title – contains three instances all in the penultimate paragraph:

These various circumstances, which emphasize dependence upon cover, and adaptation in physical structure and temperament thereto, go to demonstrate the nature of the ultimate associational niche occupied by the California Thrasher. This is one of the minor niches which with their occupants all together make up the chaparral association. It is, of course, axiomatic that no two species regularly established in a single fauna have precisely the same niche relationships.

The “circumstances” are the chaparral habitat’s physical characteristics, for which the thrasher’s phenotypic properties are especially well suited. Its dense undercanopy foliage prevents all but short bursts of flight, complementing the thrasher’s small, compact wings. Its inconspicuous drab-brown plumage also enhances predator evasion in that foliage.

The allusions to occupation are important. Grinnell’s primary focus was animal species; the vegetation they inhabit was conceptualized as part of their physical environments. Niches are then units of that physical, partly biotic environment for Grinnell, units species can occupy. With evolutionary history in mind, relationships between occupants and what is occupied can therefore be explanatory: properties of niches, as actual bits of physical space, can account for why organisms residing in them possess the (adaptive) phenotypic properties they do.

Although a minority view, there are contrasting readings of Grinnell. Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson1978, 157) claimed, “it is evident that [for Grinnell] the space occupied by ‘just one species’ is an abstract space that cannot be a subdivision of the ordinary habitat space.” But such abstraction coheres poorly with Grinnell’s extensive descriptions of actual portions of environments as niches. The emphasis on the concrete is quite clear in later papers:

Habitats have been variously classified by students of geographical distribution. Some of us have concluded that we can usefully recognize, as measures of distributional behavior, the realm, the region, the life-zone, the fauna, the subfauna, the association, and the ecologic or environmental niche. The latter, ultimate unit, is occupied by just one species or subspecies; if a new ecologic niche arises, or if a niche is vacated, nature hastens to supply an occupant, from whatever material may be available. Nature abhors a vacuum in the animate world as well as in the inanimate world.

(Grinnell Reference Grinnell1924, 227)

Note that habitats are being classified with different measures of geographical distribution, the unit of finest resolution being the “ecologic or environmental” niche (synonymy implied).Footnote 3 The idea that an abstraction is really what is being invoked therefore appears implausible. That Hutchinson favored and developed an abstract-space approach himself may be relevant.

In one of ecology’s founding works, Animal Ecology, Charles Elton (Reference Elton1927, 63–64) described a very different concept:

Animals have all manner of external factors acting upon them – chemical, physical, and biotic – and the “niche” of an animal means its place in the biotic environment, its relations to food and enemies. The ecologist should cultivate the habit of looking at animals from this point of view as well as from the ordinary standpoints of appearance, names, affinities, and past history. When an ecologist says “there goes a badger” he should include in his thoughts some definite idea of the animal’s place in the community to which it belongs, just as if he had said “there goes the vicar.”

Elton recognized the impacts of abiotic (“chemical,” “physical”) factors, but unlike Grinnell his niche focuses on biotic interactions. The one diagram presented in the “Niches” section, for example, illustrates the “niche occupied by small sapsuckers, of which one of the biggest groups is the plant-lice or aphids” (Reference Elton1927, 66), with a “food cycle” – “food web” in current terminology – comprised solely of biological nodes (Figure 1).

Figure 1 Elton’s diagram of a “food cycle” intended to illustrate the niche of the “small sapsuckers.”

From Elton 1927, 66

This figure and reference to a “small sapsuckers” niche (note the plural) reveals an interesting aspect of Elton’s concept absent from Grinnell’s. For Elton, what individuates niches partially depends on how fine-grained the relations between organisms comprising a biological community are conceptualized. On this point Elton (Reference Elton1927, 64) was quite explicit:

[W]e might take as a niche all the carnivores which prey upon small mammals, and distinguish them from those which prey upon insects. When we do this it is immediately seen that the niches about which we have been speaking are only smaller subdivisions of the old conceptions of carnivore, herbivore, insectivore, etc., and that we are only attempting to give more accurate and detailed definitions of the food habits of animals.

Degree of representational resolution therefore determines what counts as a niche. And since that degree differs across scientific contexts, species are constituents of many distinct niches with different extensions. The claim that coexisting species cannot have the same niche – one gloss on the competitive exclusion principle that Grinnell expressed in the first quote above – would thus sound foreign to Elton. It relies on a much narrower niche conception. This greater generality may account for the fact, noted by Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson1978, 152), that Elton never used the niche concept to explain competition.Footnote 4 It likely also explains why he was never tempted to elevate competitive exclusion to the axiomatic or principle status.

Dependence on representational resolution therefore marks an important contrast between Grinnell’s and Elton’s understandings of niche. But the contrast also seems to stem from a much deeper and more significant divergence of habitat versus functional conceptions. Unlike Grinnell’s markedly physical conception, Elton’s vicar analogy manifests the latter. Just as vicars are identified by functional roles in religious institutions, an animal’s “place in the community” is similarly functionally individuated by its role in networks of biotic interactions.

Some resist this bipartite judgment (e.g., Schoener Reference Schoener and Cherrett1989; Griesemer Reference Griesemer, Keller and Lloyd1992). Griesemer rightly stresses that Grinnell and Elton had different research foci – primarily, how evolutionary dynamics influence species distributions versus how trophic interactions determine community structure – and that that probably partially explains their divergent uses of “niche.” He also correctly highlights that each recognized the importance of biotic and abiotic factors, while obviously believing one was more salient than the other. The claim that Elton and Grinnell possessed distinct biotic and abiotic concepts should therefore be rejected. These differences, though nontrivial, only indicate different conceptual emphases for Griesemer, not different concepts: “Grinnell and Elton both identified the niche as the place/role a species happens to occupy in an environment” (Reference Griesemer, Keller and Lloyd1992, 235).

Correctly judging when differences in conceptual emphasis signify distinct concepts requires a theory of concept individuation, which is beyond the purview of Griesemer’s analysis (or this one). But some of the dissimilarities seem to make concept-individuating differences. For instance, the clause “occupy in an environment” in Griesemer’s characterization is problematic in Elton’s case. Elton did mention an animal’s place in the “biotic environment” – though just once in Animal Ecology (see above) – but the immediate, emphasized paraphrase (“its relations to food and enemies”) strongly suggests the functional sense given explicitly two sentences later in the vicar analogy with the very similar phrase “animal’s place in the community.”

Elton’s recognition of a small-mammal-consuming-carnivore niche or carnivore niche in toto reinforces this conclusion. These classes are characterized not in relation to environments their members occupy, but rather by their functional role in communities: consuming fleshy prey. On this issue Elton was unambiguous. The “Niches” section begins, “[A]lthough the actual species of animals are different in different habitats, the ground plan of every animal community is much the same. In every community we should find herbivorous and carnivorous and scavenging animals.” After giving specific examples the paragraph continues, “It is therefore convenient to have some term to describe the status of an animal in its community, to indicate what it is doing and not merely what it looks like, and the term used is ‘niche’” (Reference Elton1927, 63). Niches are thereby characterized in terms of this common “ground plan”: an abstract pattern of basic functional relations underlying all communities according to Elton. But that plan is contrasted with the different habitats species inhabit. Irrespective of whether niches are “places” or “roles” – two terms that often have very different connotations – for Elton they are not parts of environments. This concept, unlike Grinnell’s, is thoroughly functional.Footnote 5

There is, however, a more general perspective from which this difference can appear artifactual. Both Grinnell and Elton describe niches as components of broader patterns, be they structures in physical environments or networks of functional interactions. If these patterns derive from or simply are causal relations, then both ecologists are giving causal representations, the only difference being the nature of the causal relata.Footnote 6 For Elton the relata would be functionally individuated sets of species (e.g., primary producers, herbivores, carnivores, guilds, and possibly individual species), which obviously depends on the resolution of the representation. For Grinnell the relations would be between more finely individuated biological units (species) and portions of the environment. This difference would then just reflect Grinnell’s and Elton’s different investigative priorities and explanatory commitments; the underlying content of the niche concept would be the same. The unified characterization would then be:

Niche: a node in a nexus of causal interactions with abiotic and biotic factors occupied by a species.

In a fine-grained, species-specific way, “niche” would then simply convey causal information about ecological systems.

Despite the theoretical allure of unification, this proposal clearly fails. The problem is that Grinnell and Elton both countenanced the possibility of empty or vacant niches: unoccupied parts of environments (see Grinnell Reference Grinnell1924, 227, quoted above) or biologically uninstantiated constituents of food webs (see Elton Reference Elton1927, 27). The causally focused, species-specific characterization above seems unable to capture this broader notion; tracking the causal habits of nonexistent species is quite difficult. And this was not a superfluous conceptual aside. The idea was thought to do important work. Vacant niches feature prominently in Grinnell’s explanations of the adaptiveness of species’ phenotypes for specific environments, and Elton’s explanations of putative ecological equivalents in distinct biological communities.Footnote 7

One might think there is an easy fix, simply add “or not” to the characterization above. But the vacant disjunct is not so conceptually innocuous. Its addition seems to abandon the very causal information upon which the unified characterization is based. If it is the web of causal relations a species realizes that indicates the contours of the niche it occupies, no indication occurs in empty cases (from nonexistent species). Yet Grinnell and Elton were committed to the idea that niches endure rather than expire when those causal relations cease to exist (when niches are vacated). So they presumably cannot be (part of?) what individuates a niche. But what, then, is the relationship between the causal relations species participate in when they occupy a niche and whatever it is that characterizes that niche? Far from being “formalized by Grinnell” (Chase and Leibold Reference Chase and Leibold2003, 8), without an answer to this question the niche concept in its Grinnellian, Eltonian, or causal-unificatory guises is problematically vague.

Vagueness is not always problematic in science. Imprecision can accurately represent appropriate uncertainty about how a phenomenon is best described, or capture precisely the right level of generality when explaining it. It is problematic here because vagueness precludes clarity about what individuates niches. And clear individuation standards are certainly necessary if the concept is to perform the substantive function it is thought to in ecological theorizing. This kind of criticism has a well-established track record in biology. It is the same kind of charge made against adaptationism in an evolutionary context:

The niche is a multidimensional description of all the relations entered into by an organism with the surrounding world.… To maintain that organisms adapt to the environment is to maintain that such ecological niches exist in the absence of organisms and that evolution consists in filling these empty and preexistent niches. But the external world can be divided up in an uncountable infinity of ways, so there is an uncountable infinity of conceivable ecological niches. Unless there is a preferred or correct way in which to partition the world, the idea of an ecological niche without an organism filling it loses all meaning.

(Levins and Lewontin Reference Levins and Lewontin1985, 68)

Putting aside the allusion to uncountable infinities, and that the infinite divisibility of the world does not strictly entail that an infinity of niches is conceivable, it certainly does not seem that Grinnell’s or Elton’s accounts provide much guidance about how to affect the required partitioning.

The general problem is epistemological and evidentiary, not metaphysical and ontic. Vacant niches do not pose a problem because they violate some metaphysical criterion, such as that the causal approach would require niches be tokened (occupied). Ontologically, they could be construed as untokened components of causal type relations, uninstantiated dispositions, or in terms of counterfactuals with false antecedents. Knowing how to determine these types, dispositions, or counterfactuals is the difficulty. Without these theoretical possibilities being realized by occurrent species that would reveal such information, it is quite unclear how their nature can be ascertained.

For the kind of purpose Grinnell and Elton often seemed to have in mind when discussing niches, however, the inability to partition might be only marginally problematic, if at all. Rather than attempting to ecologically carve nature at some joint – one strictly inhabitable by a single species – they were often concerned with analogical inferences across dynamically and structurally similar communities. Evolutionarily distant communities in geographically remote areas sometimes seem to exhibit similar dynamics. If this African grassland community has a large species guild performing critical ecosystem function X, then that ostensibly analogous American grassland community exhibiting patterns quite similar to X might also have a guild performing that function. This type of inference is particularly clear in Elton’s allusion to a basic “ground plan” underlying all animal communities. But the same idea plausibly underlies Grinnell’s descriptions of how species are adapted to properties of their physical environments, and how at very disparate geographical locations one still sometimes finds similar kinds of species if their environments are similar. Lawton’s (Reference Lawton1982) bracken study is another example of the same kind of inference.

These analogical inferences depend on recognizing broad causal patterns that indicate similarities of structure or dynamics: the similarities make the analogies apt when they are. But analogy aptness does not require isomorphism, homomorphism, or any other fine-grained correspondence of dynamics or structure, the kind of close correspondence a fruitful niche concept that determinately partitioned the environment (Grinnell) or functional community relations (Elton) would arguably afford. Of course, analogical inferences are notoriously difficult to assess and highly defeasible. But when they are fruitful, it is characteristically not because such a high degree of correspondence precision can be established. Such precision in fact cuts against the less constrained connections analogies trade on. Biologically informed pattern recognition, not a foundational and systematic niche concept, seems to underpin the cross-community, cross-environment inferences Elton and Grinnell were making.

One might think the allusion to pattern recognition opens the door for a more positive evaluation of the niche. Judging that different biological systems exhibit similar patterns, it might be objected, is sufficient to ground the concept’s utility, albeit in a vague form that matches the imprecision of “pattern.” On, say, Elton’s functional approach, considering the role played by species (or guilds, carnivores, or even more inclusive classes) would ground judgments of pattern similarity. On what other basis could such similarity be judged?

That biological communities do not seem to instantiate a universal or even widely generalizable “ground plan” at anything other than the most generic organizational level – and certainly not at the level of species – exposes one serious limitation of this claim. But the more basic problem is that it incorrectly reverses the direction of dependency. As noted earlier, Elton characterized niches in terms of this ground plan. Only via reference to that latter does the former acquire meaning; just as “vicar” acquires significance only in certain religious and institutional contexts.Footnote 8

2 The Struggle for Existence and Competitive Exclusion

The shortcoming discussed above squares poorly with the prevalent view of the niche’s role in perhaps the best candidate for a distinctively ecological law, the competitive exclusion principle (CEP). Simply put, it says complete competitors cannot coexist (Hardin Reference Hardin1960) or, in niche-theoretic terms, species with identical niches cannot coexist. This principle has a long history in ecology. Grinnell, for instance, arrived at an exclusionary principle early in the twentieth century, perhaps drawing on suggestive passages from Darwin (see Hardin Reference Hardin1960).Footnote 9 But the CEP’s most compelling development and elevation to “principle” status is largely credited to Georgy Gause, his influential The Struggle for Existence in particular.

Despite its pedigree and pretensions to lawhood, the CEP is controversial. With Popperian flare, Peters (Reference Peters1991) deemed it tautologous. Even more methodologically tolerant ecologists have called it “untestable” and “of little scientific utility” (Pianka Reference Pianka2000, 248). The present task is not to render judgment on these claims (see Chapter 2 on ecological laws). Rather, it is to evaluate what could be considered the received view about the contribution the niche concept makes to CEP, which Griesemer (Reference Griesemer, Keller and Lloyd1992, 237) captures: “Gause’s and Park’s experiments showed that the concept of niche, in the guise of determinants of relations of competitive exclusion, was central to an understanding of population dynamics and the evolutionary structuring of communities.” But if the concept is as problematically imprecise as indicated in Section 1, such centrality would be perplexing. No concept that indeterminate can do that much heavy theoretical lifting. Fortunately, a close reading of Gause’s reasoning shows that although he used the term, the concept actually contributes little.

In several ingenious experiments, Gause (Reference Gause1934) studied competitive dynamics in paramecium and yeast species. In constant ecological conditions (e.g., nutrient levels, medium temperature, turbidity) and absent refugia that might mitigate interspecific competition effects, one species inevitably outcompeted the other to extinction. This result matches what classical Lotka–Volterra competition equations predict (exclusion), and Gause believed this furnished a compelling case for CEP. The key question is what the niche concept contributes to this case.

Gause (Reference Gause1934, 19) first mentioned “niche” in a context-setting discussion of “general principles” zoologists had developed in connection with competition. After citing Elton’s (Reference Elton1927) “place in a community” definition referencing “habits, food, and mode of life,” Gause then stated, “It is admitted that as a result of competition two similar species scarcely ever occupy similar niches, but displace each other in such a manner that each takes possession of certain peculiar kinds of food and modes of life in which it has an advantage over its competitor.”Footnote 10 The clause “It is admitted” reflects Gause’s awareness that Lotka, Volterra, and J. B. S. Haldane (Reference Haldane1924) had already demonstrated exclusion with mathematical models of competition, models in which “niche” is absent (see below). The CEP was definitely “in the air” well before The Struggle.

But what is most striking about Gause’s claim is how little Elton (Reference Elton1927) actually tied the niche concept to competition, and that he did not entertain anything resembling the CEP. In fact, Elton allowed that two species might occupy one niche (see Section 1). While many ecologists at the time were seeing competition as the prime driver of community structure (Kingsland Reference Kingsland1995), Elton never shared this confidence. Elton was also quite skeptical of the ecological salience of mathematical approaches to studying natural systems; he thought they typically oversimplified their subject (Crowcroft Reference Crowcroft1991). Gause’s effort to situate his project within the influential work of the day – Animal Ecology having had an immense impact on the incipient science – therefore seems to run a bit roughshod over the actual content of Elton’s niche concept.

Immediately after mentioning Elton’s niche, Gause (Reference Gause1934, 19–20) illustrated the idea of closely related species with different niches with an example of phylogenetically close sympatric tern species. They appeared to minimize competition by having distinct food sources. But the importance of differential feeding behaviors in communities composed of related species was well known long before Elton (or Grinnell) ecologically coined “niche,” at least since Darwin’s discussion of Galapagos finches. Moreover, modeling work bereft of niche considerations Gause knew well demonstrated the same result. Gause (Reference Gause1934) cited Lotka’s (Reference Lotka1932) analysis of competitive equations, which showed competitors could coexist by utilizing different food sources. The analysis never mentioned “niche,” and Elton and Grinnell are not referenced. Without something beyond the mere fact that Elton’s niche includes food, it therefore appears the concept contributes little to Gause’s case for CEP in this part of The Struggle.

The aim of Gause’s initial discussion was context-setting, however. And at the section’s end Gause (Reference Gause1934, 19) emphasized, “we shall endeavor to express all these relations [food sources on competition] in a quantitative form.” His explanation twenty-five pages later of how Lotka–Volterra differential equations represent competitive dynamics supplies that quantification, and it contains the next “niche” reference. If the niche concept is to make a significant contribution to the CEP, this is the place.

At first glance, the intended contribution seems clear. “Niche” first occurs in this section in Gause’s (Reference Gause1934, 45–46) discussion of α, a coefficient of interspecific competition in the equations:

This coefficient α shows the degree of influence of one species upon the unutilized opportunity for growth of another. In fact, if the interests of the different species do not clash and if in the microcosm they occupy places of a different type or different “niches” then the degree of influence of one species on the opportunity for growth of another, or the coefficient α, will be equal to zero. But if the species lay claim to the very same “niche,” and are more or less equivalent as concerns the utilization of the medium, then the coefficient α will approach unity.

Putting the potential significance of scare quotes aside, niches – via “places” – then seem to factor explicitly into Gause’s (Reference Gause1934, 47) word-equation explanation of the equations given one page later (see Figure 2).Footnote 11

Figure 2 Gause’s word equation representing standard Lotka–Volterra competition equations.

Immediately after this verbal description, Gause (Reference Gause1934, 47) gave their mathematical representation:

dN1dt=b1N1K1N1+αN2K1(1a)
dN2dt=b2N2K2N2+βN1K2(1b)

where N1,2 represent competing species; b1,2 represent birth rates; K1,2 represent “maximally possible” carrying capacity population sizes; and α, β are competition coefficients representing the effect of N1 individuals on N2 individuals, and vice versa. These equations for the “struggle for existence,” Gause (Reference Gause1934, 48) clarified, “express quantitatively the process of competition between two species for the possession of a certain common place in the microcosm.” Note “place” here and in the word equation of Figure 2.

“Degree of realization of the potential increase” in the far-right term designates the “drag” factors represented in competition equations. Equation (1) shows there are two: intraspecific density-dependent drag captured by the logistic element (the second term: b1,2N1,2N1,2)K1,2) and interspecific density-dependent drag captured by the competition element (the third term: αβb1,2N2,1N1,2)K1,2). These factors, the word equation tells us, depend on the “number of still vacant places.” What else could those places be but the same “places” Gause considered when discussing α and “niches” a single page before, or the “place” in Elton’s niche characterization Gause referred to explicitly? The first chapter of The Struggle pays Darwin significant tribute for largely founding its scientific subject matter; perhaps Gause was harkening back to his niche-like use of “place” (see Pearce Reference Pearce2010).Footnote 12

The terminological convergence here, however, is highly misleading. By “place” in “vacant places” and “common place in the microcosm” Gause meant something very specific, and entirely distinct from “place” in Elton’s “place in a community.” The former sense is made clear in Gause’s earlier discussion of the logistic equation’s representation of intraspecific density-dependence. For species N in a specific environment at a particular time, “The difference between the maximally possible and the already accumulated population (KN), taken in a relative form, i.e., divided by the maximal population ((KN)/K), shows the relative number of ‘still vacant places’” (Gause Reference Gause1934, 34–35). That is, “vacant places” simply numerically measure how much more a population can grow given intraspecific density-dependence and – when competing with another species – interspecific density-dependence. “Common places” are then actually arithmetic units of population size, realized or potential (vacant), that species “compete” for according to Gause.Footnote 13 Function-laden Eltonian notions of habit, feeding behavior, and mode of life are orthogonal to this numeric “place” notion. The former therefore does not help make the case for CEP via the latter.Footnote 14

But this portion of The Struggle – the mathematically rich explanation of competition – is arguably its most compelling core: “Gause’s great achievement was to give a clear exposition of the way that competitive exclusion, so often previously noted, actually worked” (Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1978, 152). The ostensibly mechanistic detail of the account of competitive dynamics made it so convincing. If niche considerations contribute little if anything to that account, what real work is the concept doing in Gause’s case for CEP?

The remaining five “niche” references in The Struggle bolster this judgment. They occur (with occasional scare quotes again) fifty pages later in Gause’s discussion of several paramecium experiments that resulted in competitive exclusion. All those references appear in one passage questioning the result’s relevance to real-world biological systems:

However, there is in nature a great diversity of “niches” with different conditions, and in one niche the first competitor possessing advantages over the second will displace him, but in another niche with different conditions the advantages will belong to the second species which will completely displace the first. Therefore side by side in one community, but occupying somewhat different niches, two or more nearly related species … will continue to live in a certain state of equilibrium.

But nowhere did Gause explain how different niches must be to ensure coexistence, how niches could be individuated, or, most important, how niche considerations could help determine the competition coefficients required by the Lotka–Volterra competition equations. That different species typically utilize different food sources was well known well before Darwin, and existing models of competition had already captured the resulting interspecific dynamics with mathematical precision (e.g., Lotka Reference Lotka1932). Rather than constitute the indispensable conceptual core of Gause’s work supporting CEP, his allusions to the niche seem more gloss than grist.

3 Hutchinson’s n-Dimensional Hypervolume

For many ecologists, Hutchinson’s definition in “Concluding Remarks” (Reference Hutchinson1957) was a watershed moment:

it was not until Hutchinson’s “Concluding Remarks” that the niche concept was rigorously defined and its relationship to competition and species diversity rigorously explored … Hutchinson succeeded in combining both the Eltonian and Grinnellian concepts of niche into one model.

(Real and Levin Reference Real, Levin, Real and Brown1991, 180–181)

This “revolutionary” account (Schoener Reference Schoener and Cherrett1989; Chase and Liebold Reference Chase and Leibold2003) set the trajectory of niche-based theorizing in ecology for several decades.

Hutchinson’s definition, which first appeared in a footnote of an earlier limnological paper (Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1944),Footnote 15 characterizes two concepts, a species’ fundamental and realized niche. For a specific species S1, consider all the environmental variables x1, x2, … , xn that affect S1, which Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson1957, 416) emphasized includes both biological and (nonbiological) physical factors. If these variables are conceptualized as axes, they define an abstract n-dimensional space. The subset of this space in which S1 can persist indefinitely (i.e., have positive fitness) is the fundamental niche of S1, with an important qualification: persistence is assessed in the absence of all competing species. Not all other species are excluded in this assessment, as is sometimes incorrectly claimed, because some of the environmental variables that define the space are in fact species (e.g., S1’s food resources, or obligate symbionts). Of course, species often do face competitors that constrict their range. The subset of the fundamental niche actually realized by S1 given competitive dynamics is its realized niche.

In significant ways, Hutchinson’s account breaks sharply with earlier work. Unlike Grinnell’s niche but similar to Elton’s, the fundamental and realized niches are abstractions, not portions of real-world environments. Any Hutchinsonian niche might correspond to highly disjoint sets of areas in the real world. The sole figure in “Concluding Remarks” illustrates this relationship, “biotop space” being the actual environment of the two species (see Figure 3).

Figure 3 Hutchinson’s diagram of two fundamental niches.

From Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1957, 421

Abstraction can make empirical concepts less tractable, and Elton’s concept is often contrasted unfavorably with Grinnell’s in this regard (Griesemer Reference Griesemer, Keller and Lloyd1992). But Hutchinson’s abstract definition is coupled with a significant conceptual shift that greatly enhances tractability: niches are strictly defined in relation to species, persistence of the latter determining the boundaries of the former (for fundamental niches). By definitionally tethering niches to species, Hutchinson’s account is much clearer about how niches are individuated: positive fitness delimits the niche-relevant portion of a species’ causal nexus. Concerns about how niches are delineable that plagued Grinnell’s and Elton’s conceptions do not gain nearly the same purchase. It may be exceedingly empirically difficult to ascertain, but in principle at least it is clear how species’ niches can be delimited.Footnote 16

Gains in precision and tractability, however, came with significant costs. Hutchinson himself highlighted some shortcomings. For example, he claimed that the definition assumes all points comprising the hypervolume entail equal probability of persistence (Reference Hutchinson1957, 417).Footnote 17 In reality, (absolute) fitness will vary markedly in any plausibly realistic niche space. Capturing these important differences requires explicit representation of the relevant ecological dynamics, that is, the more fine-grained causal details that determine whether and how species persist. The definition also assumes all the environmental variables characterizing the space can be linearly ordered; however, Hutchinson admitted, “In the present state of knowledge this is obviously not possible” (Reference Hutchinson1957, 417). It is not entirely clear what precisely the difficulty is, and Hutchinson did not elaborate. Schoener (Reference Schoener and Cherrett1989, 90) mentioned prey species and vegetation type as examples of non-linearly orderable environmental variables, without further explanation. It seems, however, that prey species can be ordered by their abundance, or frequency of encounter. If particular vegetation types are required for species persistence, and their existence is binary and not a matter of degree, then these environmental variables would not be linearly orderable. But such bivalence seems quite unrealistic. As habitats, patches of vegetation of different types presumably come in different degrees of suitability for different species. Suitability then seems to impose an ordering, from the optimally fitness-enhancing to the barely positive-fitness-maintaining. But this task does face the necessity of representing fine-grained causal details discussed immediately above.

Hutchinson also stipulated, but apparently did not perceive as problematic, that the environmental variables were independent and thus determined spaces with orthogonal axes. But this assumption is false in most cases. In the limnological systems for which Hutchinson first formulated the definition, for example, temperature, nutrient availability, light penetration, and other variables impacting species are all dependent on depth. Temperature and precipitation are interrelated for most if not all ecological systems. Nonindependence does not prevent construction of an abstract niche space, but it necessitates nonorthogonal, skewed axes and coordinate systems to do so. Besides making visualization much more difficult, it also renders inapplicable some techniques used to analyze the detailed dynamics on which niche spaces depend (e.g., the Fourier method for partial differential equations representing those dynamics). And Hutchinson obviously could not have just stipulated that only independent variables delimit the (fundamental) niche on pain of losing information relevant to persistence. Nonindependent variables may nevertheless jointly bear on a species’ persistence.

These are nontrivial problems, but they pale in comparison with the limitation imposed by the significant conceptual shift away from Grinnell’s and Elton’s account: defining niches in terms of species persistence. That relativization, for instance, makes the limited notion of a vacant niche Hutchinson’s definition does afford much less explanatorily potent.Footnote 18 A niche absent an occupying species with the same explanatory potential as Grinnell’s and Elton’s is impossible because the former is definitionally dependent on the latter.

First, some clarity about what is possible on Hutchinson’s definition. Consider when a species’ realized niche is a proper subset of its fundamental niche, because of competitive exclusion as Hutchinson presumed, or other processes that prevent realization.Footnote 19 There is a clear sense in which this is an unoccupied niche on Hutchinson’s definition: a species could have occurred here but does not. But notice how confidence about the modality is acquired. It derives from knowledge of species, in particular, what affects their persistence. Given this species and these persistence-relevant facts, then the contours of its niche can be identified. The direction of dependency is clear. But without a substantive, species-independent niche concept, Hutchinson’s account is explanatorily impoverished. It does not have the resources to explain phenomena such as adaptive radiation into novel environments, degrees of “saturation” in ecosystem structure, similarities of different communities’ dynamics, and others that were squarely in Grinnell’s and Elton’s purview. Explaining these phenomena requires showing how features of the physical environment, or perhaps a ubiquitous biotic ground plan, account for species doing what they do, or what they would do in certain circumstances. Hutchinson’s approach inverts this order. It therefore does not even seem able to account for ecological equivalents. If two species appear ecologically equivalent, then that view can obviously be expressed in terms of their Hutchinsonian niches. But identifying niches as objects of any comparative interest presupposes the prior judgment of equivalence; it cannot undergird it. The former therefore does not supply resources for explaining the latter. What could explain ecological equivalence is an understanding of the fine-grained causal details of what the species do, which, as stressed above, Hutchinson’s account does not provide. In general, the idea that “the Grinnellian niche and the Eltonian niche are united through correspondence between points in N [the abstract niche space] and points in B [the biotop space]” (Real and Levin Reference Real, Levin, Real and Brown1991, 181) in Hutchinson’s definition just fails to recognize how dramatically his concept diverges from theirs, and how that divergence impacts its explanatory capabilities.

For the same reason, the Hutchinsonian niche cannot ground or otherwise be the basis of the competitive exclusion principle (CEP). As indicated above, competitive dynamics are excluded from the fundamental niche’s characterization. The realized niche, on the other hand, assumes the principle: “we should expect that, in the part of the hyperspace where the overlap occurred, competitive exclusion would take place and the overlap would either be incorporated into the niche of one or the other species or be divided between the two, producing the realized or postinteractive niches of the two species” (Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1978, 159).Footnote 20 Hutchinson, along with many ecologists at the time, thought competition was the primary driver of community structure; he called the CEP “a principle of fundamental importance” (Reference Hutchinson1957, 417). Hutchinson’s niche concepts reflect this commitment; they do not independently support it.Footnote 21

Niches as defined by Hutchinson therefore convey very little information about community dynamics. Hutchinsonian niche considerations cannot, for example, determine which of two competitors will outcompete the other, and to what degree. And even delineating niches in the first place is empirically intractable when any more than a very small number of factors influence a species’ persistence, which is rarely if ever not the case. In fact, answering most questions that ecologists find important – whether competitive exclusion will occur at all when fundamental niches overlap (without simply assuming it will), how it occurs, the dimension size n of the hyperspace, the identity of those dimensions, and so on – requires an explicit representation of species dynamics. As a tool for representing and thereby understanding the dynamics responsible for community structure and species properties, the Hutchinsonian niche is hardly the epoch-making innovation it is often heralded to be.

4 Conclusion

These shortcomings of past accounts are not a historical curiosity. In a recent effort to reinvigorate niche-based ecological theorizing after Hubbell’s (Reference Hubbell2001) influential neutral theory, Chase and Leibold review past characterizations of the concept and propose a definition aiming at synthesis:

Niche Definition #1: the joint description of the environmental conditions that allow a species to satisfy its minimum requirements so that the birth rate of a local population is equal to or greater than its death rate along with the set of per capita effects of that species on these environmental conditions.

The next sentence clarifies that the definition is “a simple joining of the two concepts that we have outlined in our historical review,” by which they mean a Grinnellian–Hutchinsonian concept and Eltonian one.Footnote 22 In effect, then, this is a bipartite notion:

Niche = def (i) all factors causally relevant to a species’ persistence;

(ii) all the species’ causal impacts on those factors.

But this characterization’s sweeping generality raises serious concerns about its scientific utility. Rather than yielding something fruitful – that would, say, provide guidance in representing and analyzing community dynamics – this niche definition simply seems to acknowledge such dynamics exist. It is as if, in a chemistry context, one were told that the concept of “matter” – with no information about what specific forms it can take, its compositional building blocks, or its connections with other properties or lawful regularities – is the key to chemical analysis. What this niche definition offers seems largely to be a superfluous gloss on the causal details actually required to assess species persistence.

Chase and Leibold do not explicitly recognize this deficiency, of course, but they may suspect something is amiss about the first definition because they offer a second they claim is more precise:

Niche Definition #2: the joint description of the zero net growth isocline (ZNGI) of an organism along with the impact vectors on that ZNGI in the multivariate space defined by the set of environmental factors that are present.

“Zero net growth isocline” is short for the population values where dN/dt = 0. Revealingly, just before definition 2, Chase and Leibold (Reference Chase and Leibold2003) say, “[W]e will use simple population dynamics models to justify a second more precise version of this definition [#1].” In other words, niches are only determinable, and this definition is only justifiable, once species interactions have already been represented in those models. That is, this niche concept contributes little or nothing to determining that representation.

In the rest of their book, this prioritization is never upended. It contains interesting extensions of resource utilization models first developed by Tilman (Reference Tilman1982) and sophisticated analyses of how empirical data might bear on them. But one despairs of finding any nonredundant contribution the niche concept, as they define it, makes to these analyses. The absence is not surprising. Tilman’s (Reference Tilman1982) highly influential book mentions “niche” exactly four times, and in each case it refers to a label used by others.

The shortcomings described above do not impugn the sophisticated modeling and empirical studies done under a “niche” rubric. But they do indicate there is not some insightful and foundational concept at the base of this work, in some way guiding and shaping it all. That work stands alone.

Footnotes

1 Apparently, Roswell Johnson was in a 1910 analysis of ladybug color patterns (see Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1978, 155–156).

2 Note the last sentence’s close similarity with what was later labeled the “competitive exclusion principle” (see Section 2).

3 “Fauna,” “subfauna,” and “association” were not categories of biological composition for Grinnell. Rather, they were hierarchical units of geography – determined primarily by abiotic factors such as humidity and temperature – within which species distributions could be classified and hypotheses about their causes evaluated (Griesemer Reference Griesemer1990).

4 It should be highlighted that Elton could have attempted such an explanation. The more precisely the functional relations being considered under the “niche” label are described, the more likely those relations could reveal competitive dynamics. For example, precisely describing the food habits of hyenas and lions would reveal they are competitors. But it then seems the description of those habits – as captured in explicit competition equations – is what yields the insight. The question is what the niche concept contributes (see below and Section 2).

5 Elton himself sharply distinguished his concept from Grinnell’s. He criticized Odum’s Fundamentals of Ecology for failing to distinguishing the two (Elton Reference Elton1954).

6 Suitably broadly construed, causal relations can represent both Elton’s and Grinnell’s target phenomena, but this general point will not be argued here.

7 A more recent example is Lawton’s (Reference Lawton1982) influential analysis of bracken herbivores in North American and Britain, and conclusion that the American communities were comparatively “unsaturated” – containing many more empty niches – and were therefore more susceptible to invasion.

8 Unsurprisingly, the view of functions that perhaps best fits function talk in ecology, Cummins’s causal role account (Reference Cummins1975), exhibits the same priority. Only after a capacity of interest in a system being represented has been delimited can system parts be judged to have causal role functions. Talk of functions untethered from such a specification is simply confused on Cummins’s account.

9 “[T]wo species of approximately the same food habits are not likely to remain long evenly balanced in numbers in the same region. One will crowd out the other” (Grinnell Reference Grinnell1904, 377).

10 Gause (Reference Gause1934) did not cite and was apparently unaware of Grinnell’s work.

11 It is worth noting that “places of a different type” clearly appears to be the intended synonym for “different niches.” The mention of clashing interests seems to be a distinct consideration, one plausibly measured by the degree of competitive intensity between species. Whether the niche concept contributes to our understanding of this measure is, of course, the issue under evaluation.

12 In fact, adding to the terminological congruence, Gause ([1934] Reference Gause2019) seemingly used it in precisely this sense on page 1: “Darwin considered the struggle for existence in a wide sense, including the competition of organisms for a possession of common places in nature, as well as their destruction of one another.”

13 This language is very strained. Cheetahs and lions compete for food, territory, and other resources. Saying they compete to “occupy” possible numerical population sizes is idiosyncratic at best.

14 Note, moreover, that Gause never connects the earlier talk of “clashing species interests” with the term “niche.”

15 “The term niche (in Gause’s sense, rather than Elton’s) is here defined as the sum of all the environmental factors acting on the organism; the niche thus defined is a region of an n-dimensional hyper-space” (Hutchinson Reference Hutchinson1944, 20, n. 5).

16 Note that what allows determination of niche boundaries is the focus on a particular species property affected by its environment, positive fitness. That focus makes it precise but also narrows the scope. If members of a species stray from their domain of nonnegative fitness and have significant impacts on other species or the abiotic environment, the source of those causal impacts would seem to fall outside the purview of Hutchinsonian niche considerations.

17 In fact, it is unclear whether his definition requires equality, and sometimes positive fitness (indefinite persistence) is fingered as the boundary of the fundamental niche (416). He also suggested that “Ordinarily there will however be an optimal part of the niche with markedly suboptimal conditions near the boundaries” (417) without any explanation of how his niche concept helps account for such variation.

18 Hutchinson sometimes failed to recognize this implication of his definition (e.g., Reference Hutchinson1957, 424; Reference Hutchinson1959, 150; Reference Hutchinson1978, 161).

19 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for bringing this case to my attention.

20 There are technical complications in assessing the relevant “overlap” that expose further challenges of Hutchinson’s hypervolume approach. First, if such overlap could be assessed in niche space, it would require determining the intersection of two subspaces in a more expansive space defined by the total set of environmental variables for both species. The fundamental niches of different species will almost always be defined with nonidentical sets of environmental variables, hence the need for the more expansive superspace. Although different species are sometimes similar in specific ways, which can generate competition, they almost always have significantly different ecological requirements and tolerances in other ways. But, second, and more important, it is unclear whether overlap can even be assessed in that abstract space. When competition occurs, it occurs in the real-world space species physically occupy (the “biotop” space). Trees compete for light and soil nutrients in geographically coincident portions of the rainforest; pelagic birds compete for nesting sites in specific cliffs of remote ocean islands. Competitive exclusion in the biotop space would then translate into exclusion in portions of the abstract (nonspatially explicit) niche space (see Figure 3) that do not intersect in any set-theoretic or geometric sense. Simply talking of overlap in an abstract hyperspace is therefore not an adequate representation of (spatially explicit) competitive dynamics.

21 That commitment, furthermore, reflects but one view of what primarily governs the structure of biological communities. Fundamental and realized niches could be defined, for instance, with predation, mutualism, or other ecological interactions at the forefront. If competition is not the main driver of patterns and processes in the ecological world, Hutchinson’s approach will miss much of what does.

22 That is inaccurate. Any partitioning of environments independent of species persistence considerations, Grinnell’s conception, is absent. Species’ functional properties that cannot be characterized relative to environments in any straightforward way, Elton’s conception, are also absent. Rather, this seems to be a recasting of Hutchinson’s notion.

Figure 0

Figure 1 Elton’s diagram of a “food cycle” intended to illustrate the niche of the “small sapsuckers.”

From Elton 1927, 66
Figure 1

Figure 2 Gause’s word equation representing standard Lotka–Volterra competition equations.

Figure 2

Figure 3 Hutchinson’s diagram of two fundamental niches.

From Hutchinson 1957, 421

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • The Ecological Niche
  • James Justus, Florida State University
  • Book: The Philosophy of Ecology
  • Online publication: 28 May 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781139626941.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • The Ecological Niche
  • James Justus, Florida State University
  • Book: The Philosophy of Ecology
  • Online publication: 28 May 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781139626941.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • The Ecological Niche
  • James Justus, Florida State University
  • Book: The Philosophy of Ecology
  • Online publication: 28 May 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781139626941.003
Available formats
×