Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of contributors
- Acknowledgments
- The philosophy of animal minds: an introduction
- 1 What do animals think?
- 2 Attributing mental representations to animals
- 3 Chrysippus' dog as a case study in non-linguistic cognition
- 4 Systematicity and intentional realism in honeybee navigation
- 5 Invertebrate concepts confront the generality constraint (and win)
- 6 A language of baboon thought?
- 7 Animal communication and neo-expressivism
- 8 Mindreading in the animal kingdom
- 9 The representational basis of brute metacognition: a proposal
- 10 Animals, consciousness, and I-thoughts
- 11 Self-awareness in animals
- 12 The sophistication of non-human emotion
- 13 Parsimony and models of animal minds
- 14 The primate mindreading controversy: a case study in simplicity and methodology in animal psychology
- Glossary of key terms
- References
- Index
2 - Attributing mental representations to animals
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2012
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of contributors
- Acknowledgments
- The philosophy of animal minds: an introduction
- 1 What do animals think?
- 2 Attributing mental representations to animals
- 3 Chrysippus' dog as a case study in non-linguistic cognition
- 4 Systematicity and intentional realism in honeybee navigation
- 5 Invertebrate concepts confront the generality constraint (and win)
- 6 A language of baboon thought?
- 7 Animal communication and neo-expressivism
- 8 Mindreading in the animal kingdom
- 9 The representational basis of brute metacognition: a proposal
- 10 Animals, consciousness, and I-thoughts
- 11 Self-awareness in animals
- 12 The sophistication of non-human emotion
- 13 Parsimony and models of animal minds
- 14 The primate mindreading controversy: a case study in simplicity and methodology in animal psychology
- Glossary of key terms
- References
- Index
Summary
INTRODUCTION
We quite naturally attribute mental representations in order to explain actions. The cat is scratching at the door because he wants to come in the house and believes that scratching at the door will get him into the house. The dog is following me because she wants some of my food and believes that by following me she can get some of my food. Some of our attributions of mental representations are without doubt fanciful (does my car really not like to start on cold mornings?), but some of these attributions are accurate. For example, some, if perhaps not all, of the actions of adult human beings are properly explained by their desires and their beliefs about how to achieve those desires. What about the behavior of (non-human) animals? Are belief-desire explanations the right explanations of their actions? I argue that some (non-human) animal behavior is properly so explained, and thus that some animals truly have beliefs and desires. There are two strands of evidence which separately support this conclusion. First, behavior that is appropriately explained in terms of mental states such as beliefs and desires is behavior directed at a goal relative to which the agent is able to learn; and since human behavior meets this criterion, I argue, we should expect, on evolutionary grounds, that some animal behavior meets this criterion as well.
Keywords
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- The Philosophy of Animal Minds , pp. 35 - 51Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2009
- 10
- Cited by