Ackers, S. H. and Slobodchikoff, C. N. (1999). Communication of stimulus size and shape in alarm calls of Gunnison's prairie dogs, Cynomys gunnisoni. Ethology, 105, 149–162.
Aizawa, K. (1997). Explaining systematicity. Mind & Language, 12, 115–136.
Akaike, H. (1973). Information theory as an extension of the maximum likelihood principle. In Petrov, B. and Csaki, F. (eds.), Second International Symposium on Information Theory. Budapest: Akademiai Kiado.
Allen, C. (1992). Mental content. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 537–553.
Allen, C.(1999). Animal concepts revisited: the use of self-monitoring as an empirical approach. Erkenntnis, 51, 33–40.
Allen, C.(2006). Transitive inference in animals: reasoning or conditioned associations? In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Allen, C. and Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Allen, C. and Bekoff, M. (2005). Animal play and the evolution of morality: an ethological approach. Topoi, 24, 125–135.
Allen, C. and Hauser, M. (1991). Concept attribution in nonhuman animals: theoretical and methodological problems in ascribing complex mental processes. Philosophy of Science, 58, 221–240.
Allen, C. and Saidel, E. (1998). The evolution of reference. In Cummins, D. and Allen, C. (eds.), Evolution of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Alp, R. (1997). “Stepping-sticks” and “seat-sticks”: new types of tools used by wild chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) in Sierra Leone. American Journal of Primatology, 41, 45–52.
Ambrose, (1961). Hexameron. In Savage, J. (trans.), The Fathers of the Church: A New Translation, vol. 42. New York: Fathers of the Church, Inc.
Anderson, A. and Kacelnik, A. (2004). Don't call me bird-brain. New Scientist, 12 June, 46–47.
Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychological Review, 85, 249–277.
Aristotle, (1941). De Anima. In McKeon, R. (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle. New York: Random House.
Aristotle, (1980). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Ross, W. D., revised by Akrill, J. and Urmson, J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Armstrong, D. (1997). What is consciousness? In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Arnold, K. and Zuberbühler, K. (2006). Language evolution: semantic combinations in primate calls. Nature, 441, 303.
Arnold, K. and Zuberbühler, K. (2008). Meaningful call combinations in a non-human primate. Current Biology, 18, 202–203.
Babb, S. and Crystal, J. (2005). Discrimination of what, when, and where: implications for episodic-like memory in rats. Learning and Motivation, 36, 177–189.
Baillargeon, R. (2004). Infants' reasoning about hidden objects: evidence for event-general and event-specific expectations. Developmental Science, 7, 391–424.
Balakrishnan, K., Bousquet, O., and Honavar, V. (1999). Spatial learning and localization in rodents: a computational model of the hippocampus and its implications for mobile robots. Adaptive Behavior, 7, 173–216.
Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bar-On, D. and Chrisman, M. (in press). Ethical neo-expressivism. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume iv.
Bastian, J. R. (1965). Primate signalling systems and human languages. In Devore, I. (ed.), Primate Behavior: Field Studies in Monkeys and Apes. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Bekoff, M. (1995). Play signals as punctuation: the structure of social play in canids. Behavior, 132, 419–429.
Bekoff, M. and Allen, C. (1992). Intentional icons: towards an evolutionary cognitive ethology. Ethology, 91, 1–16.
Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D. (1991). Reflective ethology, applied philosophy, and the moral status of animals. In Bateson, P. and Klopfer, P. (eds.), Perspectives in Ethology. New York: Plenum Publishing Corporation.
Beninger, R., Kendall, S., and Vanderwolf, C. H. (1974). The ability of rats to discriminate their own behaviours. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 28, 79–91.
Bennett, J. (1988). Thoughtful brutes. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 62, 197–210.
Bermúdez, J. L. (1994). Peacocke's argument against the autonomy of nonconceptual representational content. Mind & Language, 9, 402–418.
Bermúdez, J. L. (1998). The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2003a). Thinking Without Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2003b). Nonconceptual content: from perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. In Gunther, Y. H. (ed.), Essays in Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). Philosophy of Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge.
Bermúdez, J. L. (in press). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blair, R. (1995). A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition, 57, 1–29.
Blaisdell, A., Sawa, K., Leising, K., and Walmann, M. (2006). Causal reasoning in rats. Science, 311, 1020–1022.
Boesch, C. (1991). Teaching in wild chimpanzees. Animal Behaviour, 41, 530–532.
Boyd, R. (1990). Observations, explanatory power and simplicity. In Boyd, R., Glasper, J., and Trout, J. D. (eds.), The Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Jackson, F. (1996). Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, 1st edn. Oxford: Blackwell.
Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Jackson, F. (2007). Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, 2nd edn. Oxford: Blackwell.
Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Breland, K. and Breland, M. (1951). A field of applied animal psychology. American Psychologist, 6, 202–204.
Breland, K. and Breland, M. (1961). The misbehavior of organisms. American Psychologist, 16, 681–684.
Brown, A. S. (1991). A review of the tip-of-the-tongue experience. Psychological Bulletin, 109, 204–223.
Browne, D. (2004). Do dolphins know their own minds?Biology and Philosophy, 19, 633–653.
Burge, T. (2005). Truth, Thought, and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Burkart, J. and Heschl, A. (2007). Understanding visual access in common marmosets, Callithrix jacchus: perspective taking or behavior reading?Animal Behaviour, 73, 457–469.
Burnham, K. and Anderson, D. (2002). Model Selection and Multimodel Inference – a Practical Information-Theoretic Approach, 2nd edn. New York: Springer.
Byrne, A. (1998). Interpretivism. European Review of Philosophy, 3, 199–223.
Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A. (1988). Machiavellian Intelligence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A. (1990). Tactical deception in primates: the 1990 database. Primate Report, 27, 1–101.
Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A. (1991). Computation and mindreading in primate tactical deception. In Whiten, A. (ed.), Natural Theories of Mind: Evolution, Development, and Simulation of Everyday Mindreading. Oxford: Blackwell.
Call, J. (2004). Inferences about the location of food in the great apes. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 118, 232–241.
Call, J. (2006). Descartes's two errors: reason and reflection in the great apes. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Call, J. (2007). Apes know that hidden objects can affect the orientation of other objects. Cognition, 105, 1–25.
Call, J. and Carpenter, M. (2001). Do apes and children know what they have seen?Animal Cognition, 4, 207–220.
Call, J. and Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 187–192.
Camp, E. (2004). The generality constraints and categorical restrictions. Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 209–231.
Camp, E. (2006). Contextualism, metaphor, and what is said. Mind & Language, 21, 280–309.
Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 145–182.
Camp, E. (2009). Putting thoughts to work: concepts, systematicity, and stimulus-independence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78.2, 275–311.
Campbell, J. (1993). The body image and self-consciousness. In Bermúdez, J., Marcel, T., and Eilan, N. (eds.), The Body and the Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carnap, R. (1937). The Logical Syntax of Language. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Caro, T. M. and Hauser, M. D. (1992). Is there teaching in nonhuman animals?Quarterly Review of Biology, 67, 151–174.
Carruthers, P. (1989). Brute experience. The Journal of Philosophy, 86, 258–269.
Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2002). The cognitive functions of language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 657–726.
Carruthers, P. (2004). On being simple-minded. American Philosophical Quarterly, 41, 205–220.
Carruthers, P. (2005). Consciousness: Essays from a Higher-Order Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2006). The Architecture of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2007a). The creative-action theory of creativity. In Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., and Stich, S. (eds.), The Innate Mind, Volume iii. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2007b). The illusion of conscious will. Synthese, 159, 197–213.
Carruthers, P. (2008). Meta-cognition in animals: a skeptical look. Mind & Language, 23, 58–89.
Carruthers, P. (2009a). An architecture for dual reasoning. In Evans, J. and Frankish, K. (eds.), In Two Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2009b). Introspection: divided and partly eliminated. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78.
Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. K. (eds.) (1996). Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carver, S. C. and Scheier, M. F. (1998). On the Self-regulation of Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Casati, R. and Varzi, A. (1999). Parts and Places. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cheney, D. and Seyfarth, R. (1990). How Monkeys See the World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Cheney, D. and Seyfarth, R. (2007). Baboon Metaphysics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Child, W. (1994). Causality, Interpretation, and the Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Chittka, L., Kunze, J., Shipman, C., and Buchmann, S. L. (1995). The significance of landmarks for path integration in homing honeybee foragers. Naturwissenschaften, 82, 341–343.
Clark, A. (2003). Connectionism and cognitive flexibility. In Gunther, Y. (ed.), Essays in Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind. Analysis, 65, 1–11.
Clarke, E., Reichard, , U., and Zuberbühler, K. (2006). The syntax and meaning of wild gibbon songs, PLoS One, 1, e73, doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0000073.
Clayton, N., Bussey, T., and Dickinson, A. (2003). Can animals recall the past and plan for the future?Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 685–691.
Clayton, N., Emery, N., and Dickinson, A. (2006). The rationality of animal memory: complex caching strategies of western scrub jays. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Collett, M., Harland, D., and Collett, T. S. (2002). The use of landmarks and panoramic context in the performance of local vectors by navigating honeybees. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 205, 807–814.
Collett, T. and Collett, M. (2002). Memory use in insect visual navigation. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 3, 542–552.
Collett, T. S., Fry, S. N., and Wehner, R. (1993). Sequence learning by honey bees. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 172, 693–706.
Connor, R. and Peterson, D. (1994). The Lives of Whales and Dolphins. New York: Holt.
Craik, K. (1943). The Nature of Explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Crockford, C. and Boesch, C. (2005). Call combinations in wild chimpanzees. Behavior, 142, 397–421.
Cussins, A. (1992). Content, embodiment and objectivity: the theory of cognitive trails. Mind, 101, 651–688.
Dacke, M., and Srinivasan, M. V. (2007). Honeybee navigation: distance estimation in the third dimension. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 210, 845–853.
Dally, J. M., Emery, N. J., and Clayton, N. S. (2006). Food-caching western scrub jays keep track of who was watching when. Science, 312, 1662–1665.
Damasio, A. R., Everitt, B. J., and Bishop, D. (1996). The somatic marker and hypothesis and the possible functions of the prefrontal cortex. Philosophical Transactions. Biological Sciences, 351, 1413–1420.
Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (1980). Mental events. In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davidson, D. (1982). Rational Animals. Dialectica, 36, 318–327.
Davidson, D. (1983/1986). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In LePore, E. (ed.), Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Davidson, D. (1984a). Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (1984b). Thought and talk. In Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (1985). Rational animals. In Lepore, E. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. New York: Basil Blackwell.
Davidson, D. (1997). The emergence of thought. Erkenntnis, 51, 7–17.
Davidson, D. (2005). Problems of Rationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davies, M. and Stone, T. (1995). Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Dawkins, M. S. (1993). Through Our Eyes Only?Oxford: Freeman Press.
Dawkins, R. and Krebs, J. R. (1978). Animal signals: information or manipulation? In Krebs, J. R. and Davies, N. B. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.
DeGrazia, D. (1996). Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Deigh, J. (2004). Primitive emotions. In Solomon, R. (ed.), Thinking about Feeling. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dennett, D. (1969). Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.
Dennett, D. (1971). Intentional systems. Journal of Philosophy, 8, 87–106.
Dennett, D. (1975). Brain writing and mind reading. In Gunderson, K. (ed.), Language, Mind, and Knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Dennett, D. (1978). Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (1983). Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: the “Panglossian paradigm” defended. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 343–390.
Dennett, D. (1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (1990). The myth of original intentionality. In Said, K., Newton-Smith, W., Viale, R., and Wilkes, K. (eds.), Modeling the Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dennett, D. (1991a). Mother nature vs. the walking encyclopedia. In Ramsey, W., Stich, S., and Rumelhart, D. E. (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Dennett, D. (1991b). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 27–51.
Dennett, D. (1995). Do animals have beliefs? In Roitblat, H and Meyer, J.-A. (eds.), Comparative Approaches to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. (1996). Kinds of Minds. New York: Basic Books.
Dere, E., Kart-Teke, E., Huston, J., and Silva, D. (2006). The case for episodic memory in animals. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 30, 1206–1224.
Descartes, R. (1637/1988). Discourse on the method. In Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, (trans.), Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Descartes, R. (1641/1984). Fourth objections. In Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, (trans.), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Volume ii. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Descartes, R. (1644/1988). Principles of Philosophy. In Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, (trans.), Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Devitt, M. (2006). Ignorance of Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dretske, F. (2000). Perception, Knowledge and Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of Language. London: Duckworth.
Dummett, M. (1993). The Seas of Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dummett, M. (1996). Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dyer, F. C. (1985). Nocturnal orientation by the Asian honeybee, Apis dorsata. Animal Behaviour, 33, 769–774.
Dyer, F. C. (2002). The biology of the dance language. Annual Review of Entomology, 47, 917–949.
Dyer, F. C. and Dickinson, J. A. (1994). Development of sun compensation by honey bees: how partially experienced bees estimate the sun's course. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 91, 4471–4474.
Edelman, G. and Tononi, G. (2001). A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. New York: Basic Books.
Edrich, W. (1981). Night-time sun-compass behaviour of honeybees at the equator. Physiological Entomology, 6, 7–13.
Eichenbaum, H., Fortin, N., Ergorul, C., Wright, S., and Agster, K. (2005). Episodic recollection in animals: “If it walks like a duck and quacks like a duck…”. Learning and Motivation, 36, 190–207.
Emery, N. and Clayton, N. (2001). Effects of experience and social context on prospective caching strategies in scrub jays. Nature, 414, 443–446.
Erdőhegyi, Á., Topál, J., Vrányi, Z., and Miklósi, Á. (2007). Dog-logic: inferential reasoning in a two-way choice task and its restricted use. Animal Behavior, 74, 725–737.
Evans, C. S. and Marler, P. (1995). Language and animal communication: parallels and contrasts. In Roitblat, H. L. and Meyer, J.-A. (eds.), Comparative Approaches to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Evans, J. and Over, D. (1996). Rationality and Reasoning. Hove, Sussex: Psychology Press.
Fitzpatrick, S. (2006). Simplicity, Science and Mind. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Philosophy, University of Sheffield.
Fitzpatrick, S. (2008). Doing away with Morgan's canon. Mind & Language, 23, 224–246.
Flavell, J. H. (2004). Theory-of-mind development: retrospect and prospect. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 50, 274–290.
Flombaum, J. and Santos, , , L. (2005). Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Current Biology, 15, 447–452.
Floridi, L. (1997). Skepticism and animal rationality: the fortune of Chrysippus's dog in the history of Western thought. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 79, 27–57.
Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, J. (1981). Representations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1983). The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1991). Replies. In Loewer, B. (ed.), Meaning in Mind. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Fodor, J. (1998). Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fodor, J. (2003). Review of Bermúdez's Thinking Without Words. London Review of Books, 25, 16–17.
Fodor, J. and McLaughlin, B. (1990). Connectionism and the problem of systematicity. Cognition, 35, 183–204.
Fodor, J. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and the cognitive architecture of mind. Cognition, 28, 3–71.
Fodor, J. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1995). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. In MacDonald, C. and MacDonald, G. (eds.), Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation. Oxford: Blackwell.
Forster, M. and Sober, E. (1994). How to tell when simpler, more unified, or less ad hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45, 1–36.
Fouts, R., Fouts, D., and Shoenfeld, D. (1984). Sign language conversational interactions between chimpanzees. Sign Language Studies, 34, 1–12.
Frankish, K. (2004). Mind and Supermind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Frege, G. (1892/1951). On concept and object, trans. Geach, P. T. and Black, M.. Mind, 60, 168–180.
Frisch, K. (1967). The Dance Language and Orientation of Bees. Cambridge, MA: Belknap/Harvard.
Fry, R. (2002). The engineering of cybernetic systems. Bayesian Inference and Maximum Entropy Systems in Science and Engineering: American Institute of Physics Conference Proceedings, 617, 497–528.
Galef, B. (1996). Tradition in animals: field observations and laboratory analyses. In Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D. (eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Galen, C. (1999). Sun stalkers: flowers and sun. Natural History, May.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The Organization of Learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. R. (2003). Conditioning from an information processing perspective. Behavioural Processes, 62, 89–101.
Gallup, G. (1977). Self-recognition in primates: a comparative approach to the bidirectional properties of consciousness. American Psychologist, 32, 330–338.
Gallup, G., Anderson, J., and Shillito, D. (2002). In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gardener, R. A. and Gardener, B. (1969). Teaching sign language to a chimpanzee. Science, 165, 664–672.
Gärdenfors, P. (2003). How Homo Became Sapiens: On the Evolution of Thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gennaro, R. (1993). Brute experience and the higher-order thought theory of consciousness. Philosophical Papers, 22, 51–69.
Gennaro, R. (1996). Consciousness and Self-consciousness: A Defense of the Higher-Order Thought Theory of Consciousness. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Gennaro, R. (2004a). Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Gennaro, R. (2004b). Higher-order thoughts, animal consciousness, and misrepresentation: a reply to Carruthers and Levine. In Gennaro, R. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Gennaro, R. (2006). Review of Peter Carruthers' Consciousness: Essays From a Higher-Order Perspective. Psyche, 12, http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/book_reviews/carruthers3/Carruthers.pdf.
Gibson, J. (1966). The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gibson, J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Giurfa, M. (2007). Behavioral and neural analysis of associative learning in the honeybee: a taste from the magic well. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 193, 801–824.
Glock, H.-J. (1999). Animal minds: conceptual problems. Evolution and Cognition, 5, 174–188.
Glock, H.-J. (2000). Animals, thoughts, and concepts. Synthese, 123, 35–64.
Glouberman, M. (1976). Prime matter, predication, and the semantics of feature-placing. In Kasher, A. (ed.), Language in Focus. Boston: Reidel.
Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goodall, J. (1986). The Chimpanzees of Gombe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gopnik, A. and Schulz, L. (2007). Causal Learning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gould, J. (1986). The locale map of bees: do insects have cognitive maps?Science, 232, 861–863.
Gould, J. and Gould, C. (1988). The Honey Bee. New York: Science American Library.
Gould, J. and Gould, C. (1994). The Animal Mind. New York: Scientific American Library.
Grandin, T. and Johnson, C. (2005). Animals in Translation. New York: Scribner.
Grau, J. W. (2002). Learning and memory without a brain. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. M. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377–388.
Griffin, D. (1976). The Question of Animal Awareness. New York: Rockefeller University Press.
Griffin, D. (2001). Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Gruber, O. and Cramon, D. Y. (2003). The functional neuroanatomy of human working memory revisited. NeuroImage, 19, 797–809.
Grünwald, P. (2007). The Minimum Description Length Principle. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gunther, Y. H (ed.) (2003). Essays on Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Güzeldere, G., Nahmias, E., and Deaner, R. (2002). Darwin's continuum and the building blocks of deception. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hadley, R. F. (2004). On the proper treatment of semantic systematicity. Minds and Machines, 14, 145–172.
Hampton, R. (2001). Rhesus monkeys know when they remember. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences U.S.A., 98, 5359–5362.
Hampton, R.(2005). Can rhesus monkeys discriminate between remembering and forgetting? In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hare, B., Addessi, E., Call, J., Tomasello, M., and Visalberghi, E. (2003). Do capuchin monkeys, Cebus apella, know what conspecifics do and do not see?Animal Behaviour, 65, 131–142.
Hare, B., Brown, M., Williamson, C., and Tomasello, M. (2002). The domestication of social cognition in dogs. Science, 298, 1634–1636.
Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., and Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59, 771–785.
Hare, B., Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2001). Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know?Animal Behaviour, 61, 139–151.
Hare, B. and Tomasello, M. (2004). Chimpanzees are more skilled in competitive than in cooperative cognitive tasks. Animal Behaviour, 68, 571–581.
Hauser, M. D. (1996). The Evolution of Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hauser, M. D. (2000). Wild Minds. New York: Holt.
Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N., and Fitch, W. (2002). The faculty of language: What is it, who has it, and how did it evolve?Science, 298, 1569–1579.
Herman, L. (2002). Exploring the cognitive world of the bottlenosed dolphin. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Heyes, C. M. (1998). Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 101–134.
Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (1996). Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hume, D. (1739/1978). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hurley, S. (2003). Animal action in the space of reasons. Mind & Language, 18, 231–315.
Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (2006). Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hyatt, C. W. and Hopkins, W. D. (1994). Self-awareness in bonobos and Chimpanzees: a comparative approach. In Parker, S., Mitchell, R., and Boccia, M. (eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Inman, A. and Shettleworth, S. J. (1999). Detecting metamemory in nonverbal subjects: a test with pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavioral Processes, 25, 389–395.
Jackson, R. and Li, D. (2004). One-encounter search-image formation by araneophagic spiders. Animal Cognition, 7, 247–254.
Jacob, P. and Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of Seeing: The Scope and Limits of Visual Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jamieson, D. (2002). Morality's Progress. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Jamieson, D. and Bekoff, M. (1993). On aims and methods of cognitive ethology. Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 110–124.
Jeffrey, R. (1985). Animal interpretation. In Lepore, E. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. New York: Basil Blackwell.
Jensen, K., Hare, B., Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2006). What's in it for me? Self-regard precludes altruism and spite in chimpanzees. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 273, 1013–1021.
Johnson, K. (2004). On the systematicity of language and thought. The Journal of Philosophy, 101, 111–139.
Johnson-Laird, P. (1983). Mental Models. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jolly, A. (1999). Lucy's Legacy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: a perspective on intuitive judgment and choice. Nobel laureate acceptance speech, http://nobelprize.org/economics/laureates/2002/kahneman-lecture.html.
Kaye, L. (1995). The languages of thought. Philosophy of Science, 65, 92–110.
Kennedy, J. (1992). The New Anthropomorphism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kinsbourne, M. (2005). A continuum of self-consciousness that emerges in phylogeny and ontogeny. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kitchin, R. (1994). Cognitive maps: what are they and why study them?Journal of Environmental Psychology, 14, 1–19.
Knill, D. and Richards, W. (1996). Perception as Bayesian Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Koriat, A. (2000). The feeling of knowing: some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Consciousness and Cognition, 9, 149–171.
Koriat, A. (2007). Metacognition and consciousness. In Zelazo, P., Moscovitch, M., and Thomson, E. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Koriat, A., Ma'ayan, H., and Nussinson, R. (2006). The intricate relationships between monitoring and control in metacognition: lessons for the cause-and-effect relation between subjective experience and behavior. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 36–69.
Kornell, N., Son, L., and Terrace, H. (2007). Transfer of metacognitive skills and hint seeking in monkeys. Psychological Science, 18, 64–71.
Kort, S., Dickinson, A., and Clayton, N. (2005). Retrospective cognition by food-caching western scrub-jays. Learning and Motivation, 35, 159–176.
Kosslyn, S. M., Thompson, W. L., and Ganis, G. (2006). The Case for Mental Imagery. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Krebs, J. R. and Dawkins, R. (1984). Animal signals: mind reading and manipulation. In Krebs, J. R. and Davies, N. B. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.
Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kummer, H. (1982). Social knowledge in free-ranging primates. In Griffin, D. (ed.), Animal Mind – Human Mind. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Laurence, S. and Margolis, E. (2001). The poverty of the stimulus argument. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 217–276.
Laurence, S. and Margolis, E. (2007). The ontology of concepts: abstract objects or mental representations?Noûs, 41, 561–593.
Lemon, O. and Pratt, I. (1998). On the insufficiency of linear diagrams for syllogisms. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 39, 573–580.
Levin, D. T. (2004). Thinking and Seeing: Visual Metacognition in Adults and Children. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Liebenberg, L. (1990). The Art of Tracking: The Origin of Science. Cape Town: David Philip.
Lindauer, M. (1957). Sonnenorientierung der Bienen unter der Aequatorsonne und zur Nachzeit. Naturwissenschaften, 44, 1–6.
Lindauer, M. (1960). Time-compensated sun orientation in bees. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology, 25, 371–377.
Loewer, B. (1987). From information to intentionality. Synthese, 70, 287–317.
Lurz, R. (2002). Neither HOT nor COLD: An alternative account of consciousness. Psyche, 9, http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v9/psyche-9-01-lurz.html.
Lurz, R. (2004). Either FOR or HOR: a false dichotomy. In Gennaro, R. C. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Lurz, R. (2006). Conscious beliefs and desires: a same-order approach. In Kriegel, U. and Williford, K. (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lurz, R. (2007). In defense of wordless thoughts about thoughts. Mind & Language, 22, 270–296.
Lurz, R. (2008). Animal minds. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, www.utm.edu/research/iep/.
Lurz, R. (2009). If chimpanzees are mindreaders, could behavioral science tell? Toward a solution of the logical problem. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 305–328.
Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lycan, W. G. (2001). A simple argument for a higher-order representation theory of consciousness. Analysis, 61, 3–4.
Malcolm, N. (1972). Thoughtless brutes. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 46, 5–20.
Mann, J., Connor, R., Tyack, P., and Whitehead, H. (2000). Cetacean Societies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Marcus, G. (2001). The Algebraic Mind: Integrating Connectionism and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Marler, P. (1989). Learning by instinct: birdsong. American Speech-Language-Hearing Association (AHSA), 31, 75–79.
Marler, P. (1992). Functions of arousal and emotion in primate communication: a semiotic approach. In Nishida, T., McGrew, W. C., Marler, P., Pickford, M., and Waal, F. B. (eds.), Topics in Primatology, Vol. I: Human Origins. Tokyo: University of Tokyo Press.
Matsuzawa, T. (1994). Field experiments on use of stone tools by chimpanzees in the wild. In Wrangham, R., McGrew, W. C., Waal, F. B. M., and Heltne, P. (eds.), Chimpanzee Cultures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Matsuzawa, T. and Yamakoshi, G. (1996). Comparison of chimpanzee material culture between Bossou and Nimba, West Africa. In Russon, A., Bard, K., and Parker, S. (eds.), Reaching into Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and World, 2nd edn. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McGrew, W. C. (1992). Chimpanzee Material Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McLaughlin, B. (1998). Connectionism. In Craig, E. (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.
Melis, A., Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2006). Chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) conceal visual and auditory information from others. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 120, 154–162.
Menzel, C. (2005). Progress in the study of chimpanzee recall and episodic memory. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Menzel, R., Brandt, R., Gumbert, A., Komischke, B., and Kunze, J. (2000). Two spatial memories for honeybee navigation. Proceedings of the Royal Society: London B, 267, 961–966.
Menzel, R., Geiger, K., Joerges, J., Müller, U., and Chittka, L. (1998). Bees travel novel homeward routes by integrating separately acquired vector memories. Animal Behaviour, 55, 139–152.
Menzel, R. and Giurfa, M. (2006). Dimensions of cognition in an insect, the honeybee. Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews, 5, 24–40.
Menzel, R., Greggers, U., Smith, A., Berger, S., Brandt, R., Brunke, S., Bundrock, G., Hülse, S., Plümpe, T., Schaupp, F., Schüttler, E., Stach, S., Stindt, J., Stollhoff, N., and Watzl, S. (2005). Honeybees navigate according to a map-like spatial memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 102, 3040–3045.
Mercado, E., Murray, R., Uyeyama, R., Pack, A., and Herman, L. (1998). Memory for recent actions in the bottlenosed dolphin (Tursiops Truncates): repetition of arbitrary behaviors using an abstract rule. Animal Learning & Behavior, 26, 210–218.
Metcalfe, J. and Shimamura, A. P. (1994). Metacognition: Knowing about Knowing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Miles, H. L. W. (1993). Language and the orang-utan: the old “person” of the forest. In Cavalieri, P. and Singer, P. (eds.), The Great Ape Project. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. G. (1993). White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. G. (1995). Pushmi-Pullyu. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–200.
Minsky, M. (1975). A framework for representing knowledge. In Winston, P. (ed.), The Psychology of Computer Vision. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Mitchell, R. (1994). Multiplicities of Self. In Parker, S. T., Mitchell, R., and Bocca, M. (eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mithen, S. (1996). The Prehistory of the Mind. London: Thames and Hudson.
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1894). An Introduction to Comparative Psychology, 1st edn. London: Walter Scott.
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1903). An Introduction to Comparative Psychology, 2nd edn. London: Walter Scott.
Murphy, D. and Stich, S. (2000). Darwin in the madhouse: evolutionary psychology and the classification of mental disorders. In Carruthers, P. and Chamberlain, A. (eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.
Nebel, B. (1999). Frame-based systems. In Wilson, R. A. and Keil, F. (eds.), MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nelson, K. (2005). Emerging levels of consciousness in early human development. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nelson, T. O. and Narens, L. (1992). Metamemory: a theoretical framework and new findings. In Nelson, T. O. (ed.), Metacognition: Core Readings. New York: Allyn & Bacon.
Neu, J. (2000). A Tear is an Intellectual Thing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nisbett, R. and Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know. Psychological Review, 84, 231–295.
Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70, 647–670.
Nowak, M. A., Plotkin, J., and Jansen, V. (2000). The evolution of syntactic communication. Nature, 404, 495–498.
Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O'Keefe, J. and Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a Cognitive Map. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Panksepp, J. and Burgdorf, J. (2003). “Laughing” rats and the evolutionary antecedents of human joy? Physiology and Behavior, 79, 533–547.
Parker, S. T. (1994). Incipient mirror self-recognition in zoo gorillas and chimpanzees. In Parker, S. T., Mitchell, R., and Boccia, M. (eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Patterson, F. and Gordon, W. (1993). The case for the personhood of gorillas. In Cavalieri, P. and Singer, P. (eds.), The Great Ape Project. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Peacocke, C. (1992). A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Peacocke, C. (1994). Content, computation and externalism. Mind & Language, 9, 303–335.
Peacocke, C. (1997). Concepts without words. In Heck, R. (ed.), Language, Thought, and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Peacocke, C. (2001). Phenomenology and nonconceptual content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 609–615.
Pearle, J. (2000). Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Penn, D., Holyoak, K., and Povinelli, D. (in press). Darwin's mistake: explaining the discontinuity between human and non-human minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 109–178.
Penn, D. and Povinelli, D. (2007a). Causal cognition in humans and non-human animals: a comparative, critical review. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 97–118.
Penn, D. and Povinelli, D. (2007b). On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a “theory of mind.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 362, 731–744.
Phillips, H. (2006). Known unknowns. New Scientist, December 16, 28–31.
Pietroski, P. and Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren't equal: saving ceteris paribus. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 81–110.
Pinker, S. and Bloom, P. (1990). Natural language and natural selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13, 707–784.
Plotnik, J., Waal, F., and Reiss, D. (2006). Self-recognition in an Asian elephant. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 103, 17053–17057.
Plutarch, (1957). Moralia: De Solertia Animalium, vol. xii, trans. Cherniss, H. and Helmbold, W.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Povinelli, D. (1996). Chimpanzee theory of mind? In Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. (eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Povinelli, D. (2000). Folk Physics for Apes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Povinelli, D. and Eddy, T. J. (1996). What young chimpanzees know about seeing. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 61, 1–152.
Povinelli, D. and Vonk, , , J. (2006). We don't need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee's mind. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pratt, I. (1993). Map semantics. In Frank, A. and Campari, I. (eds.), Spatial Information Theory: A Theoretical Basis for GIS. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Premack, D. and Premack, A. J. (1994). Levels of causal understanding in chimpanzees and children. Cognition, 50, 347–362.
Premack, D. and Woodruff, , , G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 515–526.
Proust, J. (1997). Comment l'Esprit Vient aux Bêtes, Essai sur la Représentation. Paris: Gallimard.
Proust, J. (1999). Mind, space and objectivity in nonhuman animals. Erkenntnis, 51, 41–58.
Proust, J. (2006). Rationality and metacognition in nonhuman animals. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Proust, J. (2007). Metacognition and metarepresentation: is a self-directed theory of mind a precondition for metacognition? Synthese, 2, 271–295.
Proust, J. (2009). What is a mental function? In Brenner, A. and Gayon, J. (eds.), French Philosophy of Science. Boston: Springer.
Putnam, H. (1992). Renewing Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. (1973). What the mind's eye tells the mind's brain: a critique of mental imagery. Psychological Bulletin, 80, 1–24.
Pylyshyn, Z. (1981). The imagery debate: analogue media versus tacit knowledge. Psychological Review, 88, 16–45.
Pylyshyn, Z. (1986). Computation and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and Visualizing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. (2004). Seeing and Visualizing: It's Not What You Think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Raby, C., Alexis, D., Dickenson, A., and Clayton, N. (2007). Planning for the future by western scrub-jays. Nature, 445, 919–921.
Radick, G. (2007). The Simian Tongue: The Long Debate on Animal Language. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Reiss, D. and Marino, L. (2001). Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: a case of cognitive convergence. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98, 5937–5942.
Rendall, D. and Owren, M. J. (2002). Animal vocal communication: say what? In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. M. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives on Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rescorla, M. (in press a). Cognitive maps and the language of thought. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
Rescorla, M. (in press b). Predication and cartographic representation. Synthese.
Rescorla, R. A. and Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of pavlovian conditioning: variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In Black, A. H. and Prokasy, W. F. (eds.), Classical Conditioning II. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Rey, G. (1981). What are mental images? In Block, N. (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. ii. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rey, G. (1995). A not “merely empirical” argument for a language of thought. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 201–222.
Rey, G. (2002). Physicalism and psychology: a plea for substantive philosophy of mind. In Gillet, C. and Loewer, B. (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rey, G. (2007). Resisting normativism in psychology. In Cohen, J. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.), Blackwell Debates in Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell.
Rey, G. (2008). Externalism and inexistence in early content. In Schantz, R. (ed.), Prospects for Meaning. New York: Walter De Gruyter.
Reynolds, A. M., Smith, A. D., Reynolds, D. R., Carreck, N. L., and Osborne, J. L. (2007). Honeybees perform optimal scale-free searching flights when attempting to locate a food source. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 210, 3763–3770.
Ridge, M. (2001). Taking solipsism seriously: nonhuman animals and meta-cognitive theories of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 103, 315–340.
Riley, J. R., Greggers, U., Smith, A. D., Reynolds, D. R., and Menzel, R. (2005). The flight paths of honeybees recruited by the waggle dance. Nature, 435, 205–207.
Riley, J. R., Greggers, U., Smith, A. D., Stach, S., Reynolds, D. R., Stollhoff, N., Brandt, R., Schaupp, F., and Menzel, R. (2003). The automatic pilot of honeybees. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 270, 2421–2424.
Ristau, C. (1996). Aspects of the cognitive ethology of an injury-feigning bird, the piping plover. In Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D. (eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Roberts, R. (1988). What an emotion is: a sketch. The Philosophical Review, 97, 183–209.
Roberts, R. (1996). Propositions and animal emotion. Philosophy, 71, 147–156.
Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Roberts, R. (2009a). Emotions and the canons of evaluation. In Goldie, P. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Roberts, R. (2009b). Emotional consciousness and personal relationships. Emotion Review.
Roberts, W. (2002). Are animals stuck in time?Psychological Bulletin, 128, 473–489.
Rosenthal, D. (1986). Two concepts of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 49, 329–359.
Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ross, J. and McKinney, B. (1995). Dog Talk: Training Your Dog Through a Canine Point of View. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Rowell, T. E. and Hinde, R. A. (1962). Vocal communication by the rhesus monkey (Macaca mulatta). Proceedings of the Zoological Society of London, 138, 279–294.
Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. New York: The Macmillan Company.
Russon, A. and Galdikas, B. (1993). Imitation in free-ranging rehabilitant orangutans (Pongo Pygmaeus). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 107, 147–161.
Saidel, E. (1998). Beliefs, desires, and the ability to learn. American Philosophical Quarterly, 35, 21–37.
Santos, L., Nissen, A., and Ferrugia, J. (2006). Rhesus monkeys, macaca mulatta, know what others can and cannot hear. Animal Behaviour, 71, 1175–1181.
Savage-Rumbaugh, S., Toth, N., and Schick, K. (2006). Kanzi learns to knapp stone tools. In Washburn, D. and Rumbaugh, D. (eds.), Primate Perspectives on Behavior and Cognition. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Schwartz, B. L. (2005). Do nonhuman primates have episodic memory? In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schwartz, B. L., Hoffman, M., and Evans, S. (2005). Episodic-like memory in a gorilla: a review and new findings. Learning and Motivation, 36, 226–244.
Schwartz, B. L., Travis, D. M., Castro, A. M., and Smith, S. M. (2000). The phenomenology of real and illusory tip-of-the-tongue states. Memory and Cognition, 28, 18–27.
Seager, W. (2004). A cold look at HOT theory. In Gennaro, R. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Searle, J. (1994). Animal minds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 19, 206–219.
Sellars, W. (1963). Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Seyfarth, R. M. and Cheney, D. L. (2002). The structure of social knowledge in monkeys. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Seyfarth, R. M. and Cheney, D. L. (2003). Meaning and emotion in animal vocalizations. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1000, 32–55.
Seyfarth, R. M., Cheney, D. L., and Marler, P. (1980). Vervet monkey alarm calls: semantic communication in a free-ranging primate. Animal Behaviour, 28, 1070–1094.
Shin, Sun-Joo (1994). The Logical Status of Diagrams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Silk, J., Brosnan, S., Vonk, J., Henrich, J., Povinelli, D., Richardson, A., Lambeth, S., Mascaro, J., and Schapiro, S. (2005). Chimpanzees are indifferent to the welfare of unrelated group members. Nature, 437, 1357–1359.
Simmonds, M. (2006). Into the brains of whales. Applied Animal Behavior Science, 100, 103–116.
Skyrms, Brian (2004). The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Slobodchikoff, C. N. (2002). Cognition and communication in prairie dogs. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. M. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Slobodchikoff, C. N., Fischer, C., and Shapiro, J. (1986). Predator-specific alarm calls of prairie dogs. American Zoologist, 26, 557.
Slobodchikoff, C. N., Kiriazis, J., Fischer, C., and Creef, E. (1991). Semantic information distinguishing individual predators in the alarm calls of Gunnison's prairie dogs. Animal Behaviour, 42, 713–719.
Sloman, A. (1978). The Computer Revolution in Philosophy. Hassocks: The Harvester Press.
Sloman, S. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3–22.
Sloman, S. (2002). Two systems of reasoning. In Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., and Kahneman, D. (eds.), Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, B. C. (1996). On the Origin of Objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Smith, J. D. (2005). Studies of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition in animals. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.
Smith, J. D., Beran, M. J., Redford, J. S., and Washburn, D. A. (2006). Dissociating uncertainty responses and reinforcement signals in the comparative study of uncertainty monitoring. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 282–297.
Smith, J. D. and Schull, J. (1989). A failure of uncertainty monitoring in the rat (unpublished raw data). Cited in Shields, W., Smith, J. D., Guttmannova, K., and Washburn, D. (2005). Confidence judgments by humans and rhesus monkeys. Journal of General Psychology, 13, 165–186.
Smith, J. D., Shields, , Allendoerfer, W. E., Washburn, K. R., , D. A. (1998). Memory monitoring by animals and humans. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 127, 227–250.
Smith, J. D., Shields, W. E., and Washburn, D. A. (2003). The comparative psychology of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 317–373.
Smith, J. D. and Washburn, D. (2005). Uncertainty monitoring and metacognition by animals. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14, 19–24.
Smolensky, P. (1991). Connectionism, constituency and the language of thought. In Loewer, B. and Rey, G. (eds.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Smolensky, P. (1995). Reply: constituent structure and explanation in an integrated connectionist/symbolic cognitive architecture. In MacDonald, C. and MacDonald, G. (eds.), Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sober, E. (1984). The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sober, E. (1990). Let's razor Ockham's razor. In Knowles, D. (ed.), Explanation and Its Limits. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sober, E. (1998a). Black box inference: when should an intervening variable be postulated?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 469–498.
Sober, E. (1998b). Morgan's canon. In Allen, C. and Cummins, D. (eds.), The Evolution of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sober, E. (2000). Evolution and the problem of other minds. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 365–386.
Sober, E. (2001). The principle of conservatism in cognitive ethology. In Walsh, D. (ed.), Naturalism, Evolution, and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sober, E. (2005). Comparative psychology meets evolutionary biology: Morgan's canon and cladistic parsimony. In Daston, L. and Mitman, G. (eds.), Thinking with Animals: New Perspectives on Anthropomorphism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. (1998). Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Solomon, R. (1995). A Passion for Justice. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Solomon, R. (2003). Not Passion's Slave. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Son, L. K. and Kornell, N. (2005). Metaconfidence in rhesus macaques: explicit versus implicit mechanisms. In Terrace, H. S. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sorabji, R. (1993). Animal Minds and Human Morals. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanford, C. (2001). Significant Others: The Ape-Human Continuum and the Quest for Human Nature. New York: Basic Books.
Stanovich, K. (1999). Who is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Stich, S. (1979). Do animals have beliefs?Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 57, 15–28.
Stich, S. (1983/1989). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Stoerig, P. (1996). Varieties of vision: from blind responses to conscious recognition. Trends in Neurosciences, 19, 401–406.
Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. London: Methuen.
Struhsaker, T. T. (1967). Auditory communication among vervet monkeys (Cercopithecus aethiops). In Altman, S. A. (ed.), Social Communication among Primates. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tautz, J., Zhang, S., Spaethe, J., Brockmann, A., Si, A., and Srinivasan, M. (2004). Honeybee odometry: performance in varying natural terrain. Public Library of Science: Biology, 2, 915–923.
Terrace, H. S. and Metcalfe, J. (2005). The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tetzlaff, M. J. (2006). Bee-ing There: The Systematicity of Honeybee Navigation Supports a Classical Theory of Honeybee Cognition. Dissertation Abstracts International, 67, no. 03A.
Thrun, S., Burgard, W., and Fox, D. (2005). Probabilistic Robotics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Tinkelpaugh, O. (1928). An experimental study of representative factors in monkeys. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 8, 197–238.
Tolman, E. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55, 189–208.
Tolstoy, L. (2007). War and Peace, trans. Pevear, R. and Volokhonsky, L.. New York: Knopf.
Tomasello, M. and Call, J. (1997). Primate Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tomasello, M. and Call, J. (2006). Do chimpanzees know what others see – or only what they are looking at? In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tomasello, M., Call, J., and Hare, B. (2003). Chimpanzees understand psychological states – the question is which ones and to what extent. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7, 153–156.
Toribio, J. (2007). Nonconceptual content. Philosophy Compass, 2, 445–460.
Travis, C. (1994). On constraints of generality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94, 165–188.
Tschudin, A. (2001). “Mind-reading” mammals: attribution of belief tasks with dolphins. Animal Welfare, 10, S, 119–127.
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of Episodic Memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tulving, E. (2005). Episodic memory and autonoesis: uniquely human? In Terrace, H. S. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.
Tye, M. (1997). The problem of simple minds: is there anything it is like to be a honey bee?Philosophical Studies, 88, 289–317.
Tye, M. (2006). The thesis of nonconceptual content. European Review of Philosophy: The Structure of Nonconceptual Content, 6, 7–30.
Waal, F. (1991). Complimentary methods and convergent evidence in the study of primate social cognition. Behavior, 118, 297–320.
Waal, F. (2004). Brains and the beast. Natural History, 113, 53–56.
Waal, F. (2005). Our Inner Ape. New York: Riverhead Books.
Wei, C. A., Rafalko, S. L., and Dyer, F. C. (2002). Deciding to learn: modulation of learning flights in honeybees, Apis mellifera. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 188, 725–737.
White, T. (2007). In Defense of Dolphins. Oxford: Blackwell.
Whiten, A. (1996). When does smart behavior-reading become mind-reading? In Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. (eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Whiten, A. and Byrne, R. (1997). Machiavellian Intelligence II: Extensions and Evaluations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Whiten, A. and Ham, R. (1992). On the nature and evolution of imitation in the animal kingdom: reappraisal of a century of research. In Slater, P., Rosenblatt, J., Beer, C., and Milinski, M. (eds.), Advances in the Study of Behavior, Vol. xxi. New York: Academic Press.
Wilson, B., Batty, R., and Dill, L. M. (2004). Pacific and Atlantic herring produce burst pulse sounds. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B – Biological Sciences, 271, S95–S97.
Wilson, M. (1995). Animal ideas. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 69, 7–25.
Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In Bechtel, W. (ed.), Integrating Scientific Disciplines. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.
Wolpert, D. M. and Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1317–1329.
Wood, J., Glynn, D., Phillips, B., and Hauser, M. (2007). The perception of rational, goal-directed action in nonhuman primates. Science, 317, 1402–1405.
Wynne, C. D. L. (2004). Do Animals Think?Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Zentall, T. (2005). Animals may not be stuck in time. Learning and Motivation, 36, 208–225.
Zhang, S., Schwarz, S., Pahl, M., Zhu, H., and Tautz, J. (2006). Honeybee memory: a honeybee knows what to do and when. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 209, 4420–4428.
Zimmer, C. (2007). Time in the animal mind. The New York Times, April 3, F1, F6.
Zuberbühler, K. (2000). Referential labeling in Diana monkeys. Animal Behaviour, 59, 917–927.