Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T22:08:07.921Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

23 - Articulatory binding

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 February 2010

John Kingston
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Mary E. Beckman
Affiliation:
Ohio State University
Get access

Summary

The mismatch between phonological and phonetic representations

The division of the stream of speech into a string of discrete segments represents the number of places where contrast between the current speech event and others is possible. Discrete segments may be employed not only to represent phonological contrasts in speech events, however, but also in the plans for actually uttering them. Beyond isomorphism with phonological representations, the appropriateness of discrete segments at some level in the plans speakers employ to produce utterances is demonstrated by the fact that the vast majority of speech errors reorder entire segments rather than parts of segments or features (Shattuck- Hufnagel and Klatt 1979). This speech error evidence does not, however, reveal whether a segment-sized unit is employed at all levels in the plan for producing an utterance, nor what principles govern the coordination of articulators.

Since more than one articulator is moving or otherwise active at any point in time in a speech event, the notion of a segment implies a specification for how these independent movements are coordinated. However, articulatory records of speech events cannot be divided into discrete intervals in which all movement of articulators for each segment begins and ends at the same time, nor can these records be obtained by a simple mapping from discrete underlying phonological segments. The continuous and coarticulatory properties of actual speech events instead make it very unlikely that the plans for producing them consist of nothing more than a string of discrete segments (Ohman 1966, 1967; Fowler 1980; Browman and Goldstein 1985, 1986; but cf. Henke 1966; Keating 1985).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×