Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T20:32:26.529Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2014

Andrew Janiak
Affiliation:
Duke University, North Carolina
Get access

Summary

In the preceding books I have presented principles of philosophy that are not, however, philosophical but strictly mathematical - that is, those on which the study of philosophy can be based. These principles are the laws and conditions of motions and of forces, which especially relate to philosophy. But in order to prevent these principles from becoming sterile, I have illustrated them with some philosophical scholia, treating topics that are general and that seem to be the most fundamental for philosophy, such as the density and resistance of bodies, spaces void of bodies, and the motion of light and sounds. It still remains for us to exhibit the system of the world from these same principles.

… to treat of God from phenomena is certainly a part of natural philosophy.

– Isaac Newton

Newton as natural philosopher

Isaac Newton’s influence is ubiquitous 300 years after his death. We employ Newtonian mechanics in a wide range of cases, students worldwide learn the calculus that he co-discovered with Leibniz, and the law of universal gravitation characterizes what is still considered a fundamental force. Indeed, the idea that a force can be “fundamental,” irreducible to any other force or phenomenon in nature, is largely due to Newton, and still has currency in the twenty-first century. Remarkably, Newton’s status as a theorist of motion and of forces, and his work as a mathematician, is equaled by his status as an unparalleled experimentalist.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Snyder, Laura, The Philosophical Breakfast Club (New York: Broadway, 2011), 1–7.Google Scholar
Somerville, Mary’s book, On the Connexion of the Physical Sciences (The Quarterly Review 51 [1834], 59).Google Scholar
French, Roger and Cunningham, Andrew, Before Science: The Invention of the Friars’ Natural Philosophy (Brookfield: Scholar’s Press, 1996),Google Scholar
Grant, Edward, A History of Natural Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, Howard, “Newton’s Metaphysics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Newton, ed. Cohen, I. Bernard and Smith, George (Cambridge University Press, 2002),Google Scholar
Janiak, Andrew, Newton as Philosopher (Cambridge University Press, 2008),CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Domski, Mary, “Newton’s Empiricism and Metaphysics,” Philosophy Compass 5 (2010), 525–34,CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ducheyne, Steffen, The Main Business of Natural Philosophy (Dordrecht: Springer, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newton, ’s influence on the eighteenth century, see “Isaac Newton and the Eighteenth Century,” Enlightenment and Dissent 25 (2009), ed. Stephen SnobelenGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael, Kant’s Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (Cambridge University Press, 2012).Google Scholar
Neiman, Susan, “Metaphysics, Philosophy: Rousseau on the Problem of Evil,” in Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls, ed. Reath, Andrews, Herman, Barbara and Korsgaard, Christine (Cambridge University Press, 1997).Google Scholar
De Pierris, Graciela, “Newton, Locke and Hume,” in Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays, ed. Janiak, Andrew and Schliesser, Eric (Cambridge University Press, 2012).Google Scholar
McGuire, J. E. and Tamny, Martin (eds.), Certain Philosophical Questions: Newton’s Trinity Notebook (Cambridge University Press, 1983).Google Scholar
Newton, ’s extremely long letter of November 14, 1690 in The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, ed. Turnbull, Herbert, Scott, John, Hall, A. R., and Tilling, Laura (Cambridge University Press, 1959–77), vol. iii, 83–129.Google Scholar
Oeuvres complètes de Christiaan Huygens, ed. Vollgraff, Johan Adriaan (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1888–1950), vol. x, 602Google Scholar
Newton, ’s work, both of which are reprinted in Isaac Newton’s Papers and Letters on Natural Philosophy, ed. Cohen, I. Bernard and Schofield, Robert, revised edn (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978,);Google Scholar
Sabra, A. I., Theories of Light from Descartes to Newton, 2nd edn (Cambridge University Press, 1981), 264–7.Google Scholar
Boyle, first appeared in The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, ed. Birch, Thomas (London, 1744), vol. i, 70–4.Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre, Newtonian Studies (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965),CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heilbron, John, Elements of Early Modern Physics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982), 30.Google Scholar
Gascoigne, John, Cambridge in the Age of the Enlightenment (Cambridge University Press, 1985), 54–5 and 143–5).Google Scholar
Unpublished Scientific Writings of Isaac Newton, ed. Hall, A. R. and Hall, Marie Boas (Cambridge University Press, 1962)Google Scholar
Dobbs, , The Janus Faces of Genius: The Role of Alchemy in Newton’s Thought (Cambridge University Press, 1991), 141–6,Google Scholar
Ruffner, Jim raises important doubts concerning earlier interpretations, concluding that the text must have been written before Halley’s famous visit to Newton in 1684 – see “Newton’s De gravitatione: A Review and Reassessment,” Archive for the History of the Exact Sciences 66 (2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, presents this interpretation of Newton’s Principia in his classic essay, “Newtonian Space-Time,” in The Annus Mirabilis of Sir Isaac Newton 1666–1966, ed. Palter, Robert (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1970).Google Scholar
The Optical Papers of Isaac Newton, ed. Shapiro, Alan (Cambridge University Press, 1984), vol. i, 86–7Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre, who first noted that Newton uses the word “feign” in a parallel discussion in English: From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1957), 229 and 299 n. 12.Google Scholar
Cohen, I. Bernard, “Hypotheses in Newton’s Philosophy,” Physis: Rivista Internazionale di Storia della Scienza 8 (1966), 163–84.Google Scholar
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Mathematische Schriften, ed. Gerhardt, C. (Berlin, 1849), vol. vi, 149,Google Scholar
Meli, Domenico Bertoloni, Equivalence and Priority: Newton vs. Leibniz (Oxford University Press, 1993), 128–9.Google Scholar
Hesse, Mary, Forces and Fields: The Concept of Action at a Distance in the History of Physics (London: Nelson, 1961).Google Scholar
Ducheyne, Steffen, “Newton on Action at a Distance and the Cause of Gravity,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42 (2011), 154–9;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henry, John, “Gravity and De Gravitatione: The Development of Newton’s Ideas on Action at a Distance,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42 (2011), 11–27;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schliesser, Eric, “Newton’s Substance Monism, Distant Action, and the Nature of Newton’s Empiricism,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42 (2011), 160–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Janiak, ’s reply to their criticisms in “Three Concepts of Cause in Newton,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013): 397–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, Lisa (ed.), The Correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007),Google Scholar
Lewis, Genevieve (ed.), Descartes: Correspondance avec Arnauld et Morus, texte Latin et traduction (Paris: Librairie philosophique Vrin, 1953).Google Scholar
Gabbey, Alan, “Philosophia Cartesiana Triumphata: Henry More (1646–1671),” in Problems of Cartesianism, ed. Lennon, Thomas et al. (Kingston and Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Reid, Jasper, “The Spatial Presence of Spirits among the Cartesians,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (2008), 91–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Janiak, , “Substance and Action in Newton and Descartes,” The Monist 93 (October 2010), 657–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kochiras, Hylarie: “Gravity and Newton’s Substance Counting Problem,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40 (2009), 267–80,CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DiSalle, Robert, Understanding Space-Time (Cambridge University Press, 2006), ch. 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Introduction
  • Edited by Andrew Janiak, Duke University, North Carolina
  • Book: Newton: Philosophical Writings
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107326347.001
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Introduction
  • Edited by Andrew Janiak, Duke University, North Carolina
  • Book: Newton: Philosophical Writings
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107326347.001
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Introduction
  • Edited by Andrew Janiak, Duke University, North Carolina
  • Book: Newton: Philosophical Writings
  • Online publication: 05 August 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107326347.001
Available formats
×