Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T15:05:04.310Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Milk, Honey, and the Good Life on Moral Twin Earth

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 July 2009

David Copp
Affiliation:
University of Florida
Get access

Summary

Moral naturalism is the view that moral properties, such as rightness and goodness, are in some important sense ‘natural’ properties. Some naturalists have sought to make good on this idea by deploying a kind of semantics proposed by Hilary Putnam and others. Putnam himself suggested this strategy, and Richard Boyd has pursued it. The kind of semantics proposed by Putnam allows for true synthetic property identity statements, such as that water is H2O. If this approach can be applied to moral predicates, it therefore opens the door to a kind of ‘synthetic semantic moral naturalism’ according to which, for any moral property, there is a synthetic truth to the effect that the property is identical to a certain natural property. This strategy has come under attack, however, in an argument by Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons known as the “Moral Twin Earth argument.” On the one hand, Horgan and Timmons argue, G. E. Moore's “open question argument” defeated the idea that there are any analytically true sentences to the effect that a given moral property is identical to a natural property. On the other hand, they argue, the Moral Twin Earth argument undermines the idea that there are any synthetic truths to the effect that a given moral property is identical to a natural property. If they are correct, naturalism is in trouble.

Are they correct? I will argue that they are not. A close look shows that the Moral Twin Earth argument poses no threat to moral naturalism.

Type
Chapter
Information
Morality in a Natural World
Selected Essays in Metaethics
, pp. 203 - 229
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Boyd, Richard. 1988. “How to Be a Moral Realist.” In Essays on Moral Realism, ed. Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey, 181–228. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Copp, David. 1995. Morality, Normativity, and Society. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gampel, Eric H. 1997. “Ethics, Reference, and Natural Kinds.” Philosophical Papers 26: 147–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Horgan, Terence, and Timmons, Mark. 1990–1991. “New Wave Moral Realism Meets Moral Twin Earth.” Journal of Philosophical Research 16: 447–465.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence and Timmons, Mark. 1992a. “Troubles on Moral Twin Earth: Moral Queerness Revived.” Synthèse 92: 221–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence and Timmons, Mark. 1992b. “Troubles for New Wave Moral Semantics: The ‘Open Question Argument’ Revived.” Philosophical Papers 21: 153–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth, England: Penguin.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1903. Principia Ethica. Ed. Baldwin, Thomas. Rpt., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975a. “Language and Reality.” In Putnam 1975c: 272–290.
Putnam, Hilary. 1975b. “The Meaning of ‘Meaning.’” In Putnam 1975c: 215–271.
Putnam, Hilary. 1975c. Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. 1997. “‘Good’ on Twin Earth.” Philosophical Issues 8: 267–292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sturgeon, Nicholas L. 1984. “Moral Explanations.” In Morality, Reason, and Truth: New Essays on the Foundations of Ethics, ed. Copp, David and Zimmerman, David, 49–78. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×