Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T08:11:06.934Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Ecology and a new account of rationality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 January 2010

Kristin S. Shrader-Frechette
Affiliation:
University of South Florida
Earl D. McCoy
Affiliation:
University of South Florida
Get access

Summary

a decade ago, Dan Simberloff bemoaned the fact that essentialism and determinism were still dominant, if not rampant, in ecology. He attributed their persistence to ecologists' physics envy and to their diffidence in the face of the “apparent sloppiness” of their discipline (Simberloff 1982, p. 83). If the arguments of the previous chapters are correct, then Simberloffs criticisms are well placed. Essentialism appears to be driving some conceptions of “stability” (chapters 2 and 3) and of “species” (chapter 5) that run counter to the theory of evolution. Indeed, because of their heuristic power, deterministic models have been used to undergird some hypotheses about proposed community structures (chapter 3; see Simberloff 1982, p. 85). Yet, as we have argued, such hypotheses often fly in the face of the apparent uniqueness and randomness of ecological situations. Part of the reason why scientists appear to have underestimated this uniqueness and randomness, we suggested (chapter 4), is that ecology is permeated by a misguided and naive positivism and by the belief that science can avoid value judgments (see, for example, Peters 1982; see also Fretwell 1975; Rosenzweig 1976; Mclntosh 1982, pp. 27ff.). Our revisionist account of ecological method, as applied to conservation problems, is premised on the need to accept the shortcomings of positivistic, hypotheticodeductive science, even as we attempt to make ecology more rigorous, empirical, and testable. We believe that the uniqueness and randomness of ecological phenomena, as well as the lack of conceptual and theoretical clarity in the discipline, often suit it to a “bottom-up” rather than a “top-down” account of scientific explanation (see section 5.3 of the previous chapter).

Type
Chapter
Information
Method in Ecology
Strategies for Conservation
, pp. 149 - 169
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×