Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qs9v7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T17:58:25.787Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Narrative and Point of View

from Part III - Narrating and Structuring

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Daniel Altshuler
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

We examine a previously undiscussed interaction between tense and predicates of personal taste (PPTs). While disagreements involving delicious or fun are generally considered faultless – they have no clear fact of the matter – we observe that, in joint oral narratives, this faultlessness varies with tense: if the narrative is told in the historical present, disagreements involving a PPT are not faultless. Drawing on narrative research in psychology and discourse analysis, we propose that this contrast reflects a pragmatic convention of the narrative genre that participants construct a consensus version of what happened from a unitary perspective. To link this pragmatics with the semantics, we adopt a bicontextual semantics, where the perspectival parameters for both PPTs and tense are located in a context of assessment (and not context of utterance). We show that when these contextual parameters are constrained by the unitary perspective of narratives, the present tense leads to nonfaultless disagreements, as its semantics tightly binds the temporal location of an event to the parameter relevant for appraisal. The past tense, by contrast, enables both faultless and nonfaultless disagreements. We derive this flexibility by revising the existing semantics for past tense, engendering a new perspective on crosslinguistic variation in tense usage.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abusch, D. (1997). Sequence of tense and temporal de re. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20, 150.Google Scholar
Anand, P. (2009). Kinds of Taste. Ms., University of California, Santa Cruz.Google Scholar
Anand, P., & Korotkova, N. (2018). Acquaintance content and obviation. Sinn und Bedeutung, 22, 5572.Google Scholar
Anand, P., & Toosarvandani, M. (2017). Unifying the canonical, historical, and play-by-play present. Sinn und Bedeutung, 21, 1934.Google Scholar
Anand, P., & Toosarvandani, M. (2018). No explanation for the historical present: Temporal sequencing and discourse. Sinn und Bedeutung, 22, 7390.Google Scholar
Anand, P., & Toosarvandani, M. (2020). Embedded presents and the structure of narratives. In Rhyne, J., Lamp, K., Dreier, N., & Kwon, C. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 30 (pp. 801–820).Google Scholar
Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2003). Logics of Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bylinina, L. (2017). Judge-dependence in degree constructions. Journal of Semantics, 34, 291331.Google Scholar
Caenepeel, M. (1989). Aspect, Temporal Ordering, and Perspective in Narrative Fiction. PhD dissertation, University of Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Carroll, N. (2007). Narrative closure. Philosophical Studies, 135, 115.Google Scholar
DeRose, K. (1991). Epistemic possibilities. Philosophical Review, 100, 581605.Google Scholar
Dickey, M. W. (2001). The Processing of Tense: Psycholinguistic Studies on the Interpretation of Tense and Temporal Relations. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Dowty, D. (1986). The effects of aspectual class on the temporal structure of discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy, 9, 3761.Google Scholar
Eckardt, R. (2012). Hereby explained: An event-based account of performative utterances. Linguistics and Philosophy, 35, 2155.Google Scholar
Eckardt, R. (2015). Speakers and narrators. In Birke, D. & Köope, T. (Eds.), Author and Narrator: Transdisciplinary Contributions to a Narratological Debate (pp. 153186). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.Google Scholar
Eckardt, R. (2021). In search of the narrator. In Maier, E. & Stokke, A. (Eds.), The Language of Fiction (pp. 157185). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Edwards, D., & Middleton, D. (1986). Joint remembering: Constructing an account of shared experience through conversational discourse. Discourse Processes, 9, 423459.Google Scholar
Ekeocha, J. O., & Brennan, S. E. (2008). Collaborative recall in face-to-face and electronic groups. Memory, 16, 245261.Google Scholar
Forster, E. M. (1927). Aspects of the Novel. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and Company.Google Scholar
Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in English. London: Longman.Google Scholar
Hinrichs, E. (1986). Temporal anaphora in discourses of English. Linguistics and Philosophy, 9, 6382.Google Scholar
Hirst, W., Manier, D., & Apetroaia, I. (1997). The social construction of the remembered self: Family recounting. In Snodgras, J. G. & Thompson, R. L. (Eds.), The Self across Psychology: Self-recognition, Self-awareness, and the Self Concept (pp. 163188). New York: New York Academy of Sciences.Google Scholar
Hobbs, J. R. (1979). Coherence and coreference. Cognitive Science, 3, 6790.Google Scholar
Hobbs, J. R. (1990). Literature and Cognition. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar
Holmberg, D., Orbuch, T. L., & Veroff, J. (2004). Thrice Told Tales: Married Couples Tell Their Stories. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Hunter, J., & Abrusán, M. (2017). Rhetorical structure and QUDs. In Otake, M., Kurahashi, S., Ota, Y., Satoh, K., & Bekki, D. (Eds.), New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence: JSAI-isAI 2015 Workshops, LENLS, JURISIN, AAA, HAT-MASH, TSDAA, ASD-HR, and SKL Kanagawa, Japan, November 16–18, 2015 (pp. 4157). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamp, H. (2017). Openers. Ms., University of Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From Discourse to Logic: Introduction to Modeltheoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Logic, and Discourse Representation Theory. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Kehler, A. (2002). Coherence, Reference, and the Theory of Grammar. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar
Kellas, J. K. (2005). Family ties: Communicating identity through jointly told family stories. Communication Monographs, 72, 365389.Google Scholar
Klauk, T., Köppe, T., & Onea, E. (2016). More on narrative closure. Journal of Literary Semantics, 45, 2148.Google Scholar
Klein, W. (1994). Time in Language. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kölbel, M. (2003). Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 5373.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1998). More structural analogies between pronouns and tense. In Strolovich, D. & Lawson, A. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 8, (pp. 92–110).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Kuppevelt, J. (1995). Main structure and side structure in discourse. Linguistics, 33, 809833.Google Scholar
Labov, W., & Waletzky, J. (1966). Narrative analysis: Oral version of personal experience. In Heim, J. (Ed.), Essays on the Verbal and Visual Arts (pp. 1244). Seattle: University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
Lascarides, A., & Asher, N. (1993). Temporal interpretation, discourse relations, and commonsense entailment. Linguistics and Philosophy, 16, 437493.Google Scholar
Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28, 643686.Google Scholar
Lasersohn, P. (2017). Subjectivity and Perspective in Truth-Theoretic Semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, J. (2003). Future contingents and relative truth. The Philosophical Quarterly, 53, 321336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment Sensitivity: Relative Truth and Its Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mann, W. C., & Thompson, S. A. (1988). Rhetorical Structure Theory: Towards a functional theory of text organization. Text, 8, 243281.Google Scholar
Molendijk, A., & de Swart, H. (1999). L’inversion causale en français. Travaux de Linguistique, 39, 7796.Google Scholar
Moltmann, F. (2012). Two kinds of first-person-oriented content. Synthese, 184, 157177.Google Scholar
Ninan, D. (2014). Taste predicates and the acquaintance inference. In Snider, T., D’Antonio, S., & Weigand, M. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 24 (pp. 290–309).Google Scholar
Onea, E. (2016). Potential Questions at the Semantics–Pragmatics Interface. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Partee, B. H. (1973). Some structural analogies between tenses and pronouns in English. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 601609.Google Scholar
Partee, B. H. (1984). Nominal and temporal anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy, 7, 243286.Google Scholar
Pearson, H. (2013). A judge-free semantics for predicates of personal taste. Journal of Semantics, 30, 103154.Google Scholar
Pinto, G., Tarchi, C., & Bigozzi, L. (2018). Is two better than one? Comparing children’s narrative competence in an individual versus joint storytelling task. Social Psychology of Education, 21, 91109.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. (2007). Imagining De Se. Ms., Institut Jean Nicod, Paris.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1947). Elements of Symbolic Logic. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Riester, A. (2019). Constructing QUD trees. In Zimmermann, M., von Heusinger, K., & Gaspar, V. E. O. (Eds.), Questions in Discourse, Volume 2: Pragmatics (pp. 164193). Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Roberts, C. (2012). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5(6), 169.Google Scholar
Roberts, C. (2016). Coherence and Anaphora. Ms., The Ohio State University.Google Scholar
Schiffrin, D. (1981). Tense variation in narrative. Language, 57, 4562.Google Scholar
Schlenker, P. (2004). Context of thought and context of utterance (a note on free indirect discourse and the historical present). Mind & Language, 19, 279304.Google Scholar
Sharvit, Y. (2004). Free indirect discourse and ‘de re’ pronouns. In Young, R. B. (Ed.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 14 (pp. 305–322).Google Scholar
Sharvit, Y. (2008). The puzzle of free indirect discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 353395.Google Scholar
Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 487525.Google Scholar
von Stutterheim, C., & Klein, W. (1989). Referential movement in descriptive and narrative discourse. In Dietrich, R. & Graumann, C. F. (Eds.), Language Processing in Social Context (pp. 3976). Amsterdam: North-Holland.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, L., & Beaver, D. (2016). Question-based models of information structure. In Féry, C. & Ishihara, S. (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Information Structure (pp. 86107). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vendler, Z. (1982). Speaking of imagination. In Simon, T. W. & Scholes, R. J. (Eds.), Language, Mind, and Brain (pp. 3543). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Webber, B. L. (1988). Tense as discourse anaphora. Computational Linguistics, 14, 6173.Google Scholar
Wolfson, N. (1979). The conversational historical present alternation. Language, 55, 168182.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×