Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T08:13:21.042Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part II - Describing and Referring

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Daniel Altshuler
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2003). Logics of Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Beaver, D., Geurts, B., & Maier, E. (2005). Discourse representation theory. In Zalta, E. (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University.Google Scholar
Brasoveanu, A., & Farkas, D. (2009). Exceptional scope as discourse reference to quantificational dependencies. In Bosch, D. G. P. & Lang, J. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 7th International Tbilisi Symposium on Language, Logic and Computation (pp. 165179). Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Brasoveanu, G., & Dotlačil, J. (2020). Computational Cognitive Modeling and Linguistic Theory. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Carlson, G., & Pelletier, F. (1995). The Generic Book. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Chastain, C. (1975). Reference and context. In Gunderson, K. (Ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, VII). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Chiriacescu, S., & von Heusinger, K. (2010). Discourse prominence and pe- marking in Romanian. International Review of Pragmatics, 2, 298332.Google Scholar
Clark, H. H. (1996). Using Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coppock, E. (2021). On definite descriptions: Can familiarity and uniqueness be distinguished? In Altshuler, D. (Ed.,) Linguistics Meets Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Beaver, D. (2015). Definiteness and determinacy. Linguistics and Philosophy, 38, 377435.Google Scholar
Coppock, l., & Beaver, D. (2014). A superlative argument for a minimal theory of definiteness. In Snider, T. (Ed.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 24 (pp. 177196).Google Scholar
Evans, J., & Altham, J. (1973). The causal theory of names. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 47, 187225.Google Scholar
Fraurud, K. (1990). Definiteness and the processing of noun phrases in natural discourse. Journal of Semantics, 7(4), 395433.Google Scholar
Grosz, B. (1977). The Representation and Use of Focus in Dialogue Understanding. Berkeley: University of California.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1982 [1988]). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. New York: Garland Press.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2003). Einstellungszustände und Einstellungszuschreibungen in der Diskursrepräsentationstheorie. In Haas-Spohn, U. (Ed.), Intentionalität zwischen Subjektivität und Weltbezug (pp. 209289). Paderborn: Mentis.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamp, H. (2015). Using proper names as intermediaries between labeled entity representations. Erkenntnis, 80, 263312.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2021a). Entity representations and articulated contexts. an application to the analysis of deictic demonstratives. In Alden Pepp, J. & Almog, J. (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan, Thirty Years Later. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2021b). The links of causal chains. Theoria 88(2), 296–325.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2021c). Unpublished notes for a graduate course in Linguistics offered at the University of Texas, Austin.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2021d). Sharing real and fictional reference. In Maier, E. & Stokke, A. (Eds.), The Language of Fiction (pp. 3786). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2022). Entity Representations and Articulated Contexts. To appear as a monograph in the Open Access series ‘Topics at the Grammar–Discourse Interface’.Google Scholar
Kamp, H., & Bende-Farkas, A. (2019). Epistemic specificity from a communication-theoretic perspective, Journal of Semantics, 36(1), 151.Google Scholar
Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From Discourse to Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Kamp, H., van Genabith, J., & Reyle, U. (2011). Discourse representation theory: An updated survey. In Gabbay, D. (Ed.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. XV (pp. 125394). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1963). Semantical considerations on modal and intuitionistic logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 8394.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1979). Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. In French, P., Uehling, T., & Wettstein, H. (Eds.), Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. First appeared in D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of Natural Language, Reidel, 1972.Google Scholar
Peregrin, J., & von Heusinger, K. (2004). Dynamic semantics with choice functions. In Kamp, H. & Partee, B. (Eds.), Context Dependence in the Analysis of Linguistic Meaning (pp. 255274). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.Google Scholar
Schwarz, F. (2009). Two Types of Definites in Natural Language. PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1958). Proper names. Mind, 67, 166173.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (1982). Proper names and intentionality. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63(3), 205225.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

References

Aguilar-Guevara, A., Pozas-Loyo, J., & Maldonado, V. V. R. (Eds.). (2019). Definiteness across Languages: Studies in Diversity Linguistics. Berlin: Language Science Press.Google Scholar
Amfo, A. N. (2007). Akan demonstratives. In Payne, D. L. & Peña, J. (Eds.), Selected Proceedings of the 37th Annual Conference on African Linguistics (pp. 134–148).Google Scholar
Arkoh, R. (2011). Semantics of Akan bí and nʊ. MA thesis, University of British Columbia.Google Scholar
Arkoh, R., & Matthewson, L. (2013). A familiar definite article in Akan. Lingua, 123, 130. doi:10.1016/j.lingua.2012.09.012Google Scholar
Barker, C. (2005). Possessive weak definites. In Kim, Y.-Y., Lander, Y., & Partee, B. H. (Eds.), Possessives and Beyond: Semantics and Syntax (pp. 89113). Amherst: GSLA Publications.Google Scholar
Barker, C., & Shan, C.-C. (2008). Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding. Semantics and Pragmatics, 1(1), 140.Google Scholar
Barlew, J. (2014). Salience, uniqueness, and the definite determiner-tè in bulu. In Snider, T., D’Antoni, S., & Weigand, M. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 24 (pp. 619–639).Google Scholar
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Beaver, D., & Coppock, E. (2015). Novelty and familiarity for free. In Proceedings of the 2015 Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 50–59).Google Scholar
Bombi, C. (2018). Definiteness in Akan: Familiarity and uniqueness revisited. In Maspong, S., Stefánsdóttir, B., Blake, K., & Davis, F. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 28 (pp. 141–160).Google Scholar
Bumford, D. (2017). Split-scope definites: Relative superlatives and Haddock descriptions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 40(6), 549593.Google Scholar
Bumford, D. (2018). Binding into superlative descriptions. In Maspong, S., Stefánsdóttir, B., Blake, K., & Davis, F. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 28 (pp. 325344).Google Scholar
Carlson, G., & Sussman, R. (2005). Seemingly indefinite definites. In Kesper, S. & Reis, M. (Eds.), Linguistic Evidence: Empirical, Theoretical, and Computational Perspectives (pp. 2630). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Charlow, S. (2014). On the Semantics of Exceptional Scope. Dissertation, New York University.Google Scholar
Chierchia, G. (1995). Dynamics of Meaning: Anaphora, Presupposition, and the Theory of Grammar. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, R. (1979). The interpretation of pronouns. In Heny, F. & Schnelle, H. (Eds.), Selected Papers from the Third Groningen Round Table: Syntax and Semantics 10 (pp. 6192). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, R. (1996). The role of situations in generalized quantifiers. In Lappin, S. (Ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory (pp. 86107). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Beaver, D. (2014). A superlative argument for a minimal theory of definiteness. In Snider, T. (Ed.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 24 (pp. 177–196).Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Beaver, D. (2015). Definiteness and determinacy. Linguistics and Philosophy, 38(5), 377435. doi:10.1007/s1098Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Champollion, L. (in preparation). Invitation to formal semantics. Ms., Boston University and New York University.Google Scholar
Dayal, V., & Jiang, J. (2021). The puzzle of anaphoric bare nouns in mandarin: A counterpoint to index! Linguistic Inquiry. doi:10.1162/ling_a_00433Google Scholar
Déprez, V. (2016). Refining cross-linguistic dimension of definiteness: Variations on ‘la’. Talk presented at the Workshop on the Semantic Contribution of Det and Num, Barcelona, May 27–28.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2005). Situations and Individuals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2008). Demonstratives as individual concepts. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 409466.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2009). Bishop sentences and donkey cataphora: A response to Barker and Shan. Semantics and Pragmatics, 2(1), 17.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2013). Definite Descriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, G. (1977). Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 467536.Google Scholar
Evans, G. (1980). Pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry, 11, 337362.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. (1994). Restrictions on Quantifier Domains. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The King of France is back! (presuppositions and truth-value intuitions). In Bezuidenhout, A. & Reimer, M. (Eds.), Descriptions and Beyond (pp. 315342). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 2550. Translated as “On sense and reference” by M. Black, in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, P. Geach and M. Black (eds. and trans.), 3rd ed. Oxford: Blackwell, 1980.Google Scholar
Glanzberg, M. (2007). Definite descriptions and quantifier scope: Some Mates cases reconsidered. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 3(2), 133158.Google Scholar
Haddock, N. J. (1987). Incremental interpretation and combinatory categorial grammar. In Proceedings of the 10 International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Vol. 2 (pp. 661663). San Mateo: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
Hanink, E. A. (2017). The German definite article and the ‘sameness’ of indices. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics, 23, 9. https://repository.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1949&context=pwplGoogle Scholar
Hawkins, J. A. (1978). Definiteness and Indefiniteness: A Study in Reference and Grammaticality. London: Croom Helm.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1982). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1990). E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13. 137177. doi:10.1007/bf00630732Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1991). Artikel und Definitheit. In von Stechow, A. & Wunderlich, D. (Eds.), Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung (pp. 487535). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1999). Notes on Superlatives. Ms., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Horn, L. R. (2001). A Natural History of Negation. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Horn, L. R., & Abbott, B. (2012). <the, a>: (in)definiteness and implicature. In Kabasenche, W. P., O’Rourke, M., & Slater, M. H. (Eds.), Reference and Referring (pp. 325355). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Jenks, P. (2015). Two kinds of definties in numeral classifier languages. In D’Antonio, S., Moroney, M., & Little, C. R. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 25 (pp. 103–124).Google Scholar
Jenks, P. (2018). Articulated definiteness without articles. Linguistic Inquiry, 49, 501536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kadmon, N. (1987). On Unique and Non-unique Reference and Asymmetric Quantification. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2018). Entity representations and articulated contexts. Unpublished manuscript, to appear as part of a tribute to David Kaplan, with the preliminary title: “Sense, reference and use – Afterthoughts on Kaplan.”Google Scholar
Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From Discourse to Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In Almog, J., Perry, J., & Wettstein, H. (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 267298). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. A. (2011). Philosophical Troubles: Collected Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Landman, F. (2004). Indefinites and the Type of Sets. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Löbner, S. (1985). Definites. Journal of Semantics, 4, 279326. doi:10.1093/jos/4.4.279Google Scholar
Löbner, S. (2000). Polarity in natural language: Predication, quantification and negation in particular and characterizing sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 213308.Google Scholar
Maldonado, V. V. R., Fajardo, J. G., Gutiérrez-Bravo, R., & Loyo, J. P. (2018). The definite article in Yucatec Maya: The case of le… o’. International Journal of American Linguistics, 84, 207242. doi:10.1086/696197CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Oliver, A., & Smiley, T. (2013). Plural Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ortmann, A. (2014). Definite article asymmetries and concept types: Semantic and pragmatic uniqueness. In Gamerschlag, T., Gerland, D., Osswald, R., & Petersen, W. (Eds.), Frames and Concept Types: Applications in Linguistics and Philosophy (pp. 293321). Cham: Springer International. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-0541-5_13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owusu, A. (2020). Clausal determiners and definite propositions. Talk presented at BU Linguistics Colloquium, November 13.Google Scholar
Prince, E. (1992). The ZPG letter: Subjects, definiteness and information status. In Thompson, S. & Mann, W. (Eds.), Discourse Description: Diverse Analyses of a Fund Raising Text (pp. 295325). Philadelphia/Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Roberts, C. (2003). Uniqueness in definite noun phrases. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 287350.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479493.Google Scholar
Schwarz, F. (2009). Two Types of Definites in Natural Language. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Soames, S. (1986). Incomplete definite descriptions. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 27, 349375.Google Scholar
Stanley, J., & Szabó, Z. G. (2000). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind & Language, 15, 219261.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59(235), 320344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szabó, Z. G. (2000). Descriptions and uniqueness. Philosophical Studies, 101, 2957.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. G. (2003). Definite descriptions without uniqueness: A reply to Abbott. Philosophical Studies, 114, 279291.Google Scholar
Szabolcsi, A. (1986). Comparative superlatives. In Fukui, N., Rapoport, T., & Sagey, E. (Eds.), Papers in Theoretical Linguistics (pp. 245265). Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.Google Scholar
Wespel, J. (2008). Descriptions and Their Domains: The Patterns of Definiteness Marking in French-Related Creoles. Dissertation, University of Stuttgart. doi:10.18419/opus-5708Google Scholar
Westerståhl, D. (1984). Determiners and context sets. In van Benthem, J. & ter Meulen, A. (Eds.), Generalized Quantifiers and Natural Language (pp. 4571). Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
Yifrach, M., & Coppock, E. (2020). Defining definiteness in Ṭuroyo. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics, 6, 124. https://doi.org/10.16995/glossa.5874Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Describing and Referring
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Describing and Referring
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Describing and Referring
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.005
Available formats
×