Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgments
- PART I LIBERALISM AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
- PART II LIBERALISM AND NEUTRALITY
- 4 Liberalism and the neutral state
- 5 Liberalism and neutral public discourse
- 6 Moral personality and liberal theory
- 7 Pluralism and social unity
- PART III LIBERALISM WITHOUT NEUTRALITY
- PART IV FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE IN THE LIBERAL STATE
- Notes
- Index
6 - Moral personality and liberal theory
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2012
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgments
- PART I LIBERALISM AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
- PART II LIBERALISM AND NEUTRALITY
- 4 Liberalism and the neutral state
- 5 Liberalism and neutral public discourse
- 6 Moral personality and liberal theory
- 7 Pluralism and social unity
- PART III LIBERALISM WITHOUT NEUTRALITY
- PART IV FROM THEORY TO PRACTICE IN THE LIBERAL STATE
- Notes
- Index
Summary
In Chapter 5, I distinguished three variants of contemporary liberal theory – perfectionist, pragmatic, and political – and I explored one important strand of political liberalism, its conception of neutral public dialogue. In this chapter and the next, I continue the discussion of political liberalism by focusing on the recent work of its prime exponent, John Rawls.
Recall that, as Charles Larmore put it, political liberalism is a theory at once minimal (in that it allows wide scope for free choice and diversity) and moral (in that it appeals to individual motivations other than self-interest). Some interpreters of A Theory of Justice regarded it as “pragmatic” in the sense in which I am using the term, that is, as an effort to derive a conception of justice simply from the rational calculations of self-interested agents. Since the beginning of the 1980s, starting with the Dewey Lectures, Rawls has made it clear that he does not wish to be viewed in this fashion. Justice as fairness, he now insists, has at its core a moral conception, an (allegedly Kantian) understanding of moral personality. By fleshing out this idea, he says, he hopes to prevent misinterpretations of his theory,
for example, that it is intended to be morally neutral, or that it models only the notion of [instrumental] rationality, and therefore that justice as fairness attempts to select principles of justice purely on the basis of a conception of rational choice as understood in economics or decision theory. […]
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Liberal PurposesGoods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State, pp. 118 - 139Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 1991