Published online by Cambridge University Press: 13 April 2024
As explained in Chapter 1, the normativity of linguistic meaning – whether expressed in rules of grammar or implicit in our language use – is at the core of Wittgenstein's philosophy of language. Over the last decades, however, that idea has been persistently attacked. In this chapter, I shall consider the semantic anti-normativist challenge to Wittgenstein's account of language.
Types of obligations
It is useful to distinguish three types of obligations:
1. Moral obligations
2. Socially enforced obligations
3. Freely adopted obligations
The concept of a moral obligation is logically very different from that of a legal obligation in that it has freed itself from its socially enforced origin. For example, as children, we first accept an obligation not to steal because we understand that it will be enforced – that theft is severely sanctioned. But then most of us internalise this socially enforced obligation and also accept it as a moral obligation. That is to say, we take the step from:
(a) I shouldn't steal because I get into trouble if I do.
to
(b) I shouldn't steal because it's morally wrong.
Thus, moral obligations typically grow out of socially enforced obligations but free themselves (at least logically) from their grounding in social sanctions. In both directions:
(i) Something can be socially enforced without being morally correct.
(ii) Something can be morally correct without being socially enforced.
Obviously, the most important moral obligations tend to also be socially enforced by law. In that case, we are obliged in two different senses, roughly speaking: by the police and by our conscience.
Note that if I accept a moral obligation that is not socially enforced, it is not, for that matter, (what I call) a freely adopted obligation [3.] either, because I don't freely choose to find something morally right or wrong. It is, as it were, dictated to me by my conscience (which, if you are a moral realist, you may believe to track some metaphysical facts).
What, then, would be an example of a freely adopted obligation [3.]? For example, when solving a crossword puzzle, I put myself under an obligation to follow the rules. I would not get into trouble if I entered some nonsense words instead, nor would it be morally wrong to do so.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.