Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T05:30:30.565Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

8 - What is missing from theories of information?

from Part III - Biology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 December 2010

Paul Davies
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
Niels Henrik Gregersen
Affiliation:
University of Copenhagen
Get access

Summary

Theories of information that attempt to sort out problems concerning the status and efficacy of its content – as it is understood in thoughts, meanings, signs, intended actions, and so forth – have so far failed to resolve a crucial dilemma: how what is represented could possibly have physical consequences. The legacy of this has been played out in various skeptical paradigms that either conclude that content is fundamentally relativistic, holistic, and ungrounded, or else is merely epiphenomenal and ineffectual except for its arbitrary correlation with the physical properties of the signs that convey it. In this chapter I argue that the apparent conundrums that make this notion controversial arise because we begin our deliberations with the fallacious assumption that in order for the content of information to have any genuine real-world consequences it must have substantial properties, and so must correspond to something present in some form or other. By contrast, I will show that this assumption is invalid and is the ultimate origin of these absurd skeptical consequences.

The crucial property of content that must be taken into account is exactly the opposite: its absence. But how is it possible for a specific absence to have definite causal consequences? A crucial clue is provided by Claude Shannon's analysis of information in terms of constraint on the entropy (possible variety) of signs/signals (Shannon, 1948; Shannon and Weaver, 1949). In other words, the capacity to convey information is dependent on a relationship to something that is specifically not produced.

Type
Chapter
Information
Information and the Nature of Reality
From Physics to Metaphysics
, pp. 146 - 169
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution, and Epistemology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bickhard, M. H. (1998). Levels of representationality. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 10(2): 179–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickhard, M. H. (2000). Autonomy, function, and representation. Communication and Cognition – Artificial Intelligence, 17(3–4): 111–131.Google Scholar
Bickhard, M. H. (2003). The biological emergence of representation. In Emergence and Reduction: Proceedings of the 29th Annual Symposium of the Jean Piaget Society, eds Brown, T. and Smith, L.. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 105–131.Google Scholar
Boltzmann, L. (1866). The Second Law of Thermodynamics. Reprinted in Ludwig Boltzmann: Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems, Selected Writings, ed. McGuinness, B., trans. Foulkes, P. (1974). Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co., 13–32.Google Scholar
Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 88–89.Google Scholar
Deacon, T. (2007). Shannon–Boltzmann–Darwin: Redefining information. Part 1. Cognitive Semiotics, 1: 123–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deacon, T. (2008). Shannon–Boltzmann–Darwin: Redefining information. Part 2. Cognitive Semiotics, 2: 167–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27: 279–423, 623–656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shannon, C., and Weaver, W. (1949). The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×