Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T20:08:33.114Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Imperatives with conditional meanings

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 July 2014

Mark Jary
Affiliation:
Roehampton University, London
Mikhail Kissine
Affiliation:
Université Libre de Bruxelles
Get access

Summary

In the last chapter, we looked at a range of uses of the imperative and suggested that, given an adequate characterisation of directive force, the imperative mood could safely be seen as having the communicative function of conveying that force. However, we argued that it did not necessarily follow from this that directive force is the encoded meaning of imperative morpho-syntax, but suggested, rather, that a suite-of-features approach was an attractive and viable alternative. In this chapter, we consider further data that might lend support to this view, in that they appear to show that the imperative is sometimes used to convey a conditional meaning, often without an associated directive force.

These data are important because if it can be shown that the imperative can receive a non-directive interpretation, then the case for viewing the imperative as encoding directive force is considerably weakened. Furthermore, these data might provide insights into the encoded meaning of the imperative that are occluded in directive uses. However, a number of authors have argued that, despite appearances to the contrary, some or all cases of what, following Davies (1986), we will call ‘imperative-like conditionals’ or ‘ILCs’ do not, in fact, contain imperatives. Rather, they argue, we are misled into seeing imperatives where there are none by the fact that English uses uninflected root forms for imperatives. Such a claim might be supported by showing that morpho-syntactic behaviour associated with less controversial imperatives is not exhibited by such cases. We therefore need to consider the data carefully before proceeding. At the same time, it will be useful to consider what Davies (1986) refers to as ‘imperative-like ultimatums’ or ‘ILUs’, which are similar, at least superficially, to ILCs in terms of structure and interpretation.

Type
Chapter
Information
Imperatives , pp. 110 - 162
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×