Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T19:05:28.845Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - From transcendental idealism to political realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2013

Onora O’Neill
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Nicholas Boyle
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Liz Disley
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
John Walker
Affiliation:
Birkbeck College, University of London
Get access

Summary

The central arguments of the Critique of Pure Reason distinguish four fundamental metaphysical and epistemological claims, of which Kant rejects two and accepts two. However, the combination of empirical realism and transcendental idealism that he endorses seems at first sight to sit ill with the political realism that he endorses in some of his later writings on politics, history and human destiny. And yet, I shall argue, the combination makes good sense.

Basic Kant

Kant rejects transcendental realism – traditional metaphysical realism – arguing that its claims to show that we can have knowledge about things as they are in themselves, of that which transcends or lies beyond our experience, cannot be sustained. In denying transcendental realism he gives up the enterprise(s) of proving theism or atheism, freedom or fatalism. We have and can have no knowledge of these or other matters that lie beyond experience. However, he also rejects empirical or Berkeleian idealism, and its claims that we cannot know anything other than our own mental states.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Impact of Idealism
The Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought
, pp. 12 - 25
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Guyer, P. and Wood, A. (trans. and ed.), Critique of Pure Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Gregor, M. J. (trans. and ed.), Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (ed.), Critique of the Power of Judgment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000)Google Scholar
Kant's gesammelte Schriften, ed. Königlich preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1900–) (hereafter GS), v, 147.9–24
‘The public use of reason’, Political Theory 14 (1986), 523–51
‘Enlightenment as autonomy: Kant's vindication of reason’, in Hulme, P. and Jordanova, L. (eds.), The Enlightenment and Its Shadows (London: Routledge, 1990)Google Scholar
‘Vindicating reason’, in Guyer, P. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
‘Kant's conception of public reason’, in Gerhardt, V., Horstmann, R.-P. and Schumacher, R. (eds.), Kant und die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des ix. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2001), i, 35–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
‘Kant: rationality as practical reason’, in Mele, A. J. and Rawling, P. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 93–109Google Scholar
Zöller, G. and Louden, R. B. (eds.), Anthropology, History, and Education (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 108–9Google Scholar
O’Neill, O., ‘Historical trends and human futures’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 39 (2008), 529–34CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kleingeld, P., ‘Approaching perpetual peace: Kant's defence of a league of states and his ideal of a world federation’, European Journal of Philosophy 12 (2004), 304–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flikschuh, K., ‘Hope or prudence: practical faith in Kant's political thinking’, in Stolzenberg, Jürgen and Rush, Fred (eds.), Faith and Reason, International Yearbook of German Idealism 7 (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2009), 109Google Scholar
Henderson, G. P., ‘Idealism, realism, and the categorical imperative in Kant's “Perpetual peace”’, Commonwealth 12 (2003), 22–3Google Scholar
Kleingeld, P., Kant and Cosmopolitanism: the philosophical ideal of world citizenship (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×