Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T17:34:25.581Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Materialism and the radical intelligentsia: the 1860s

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

G. M. Hamburg
Affiliation:
Claremont McKenna College, California
Randall A. Poole
Affiliation:
College of St. Scholastica, Minnesota
Get access

Summary

Materialism, or the philosophical proposition that the world consists entirely of matter, has existed since the ancient Greeks. The implications of this proposition, however, have changed considerably over time. In Russia in the late 1850s and early 1860s, radicals were principally interested in the consequences of materialism for theories of the way the mind operates. Contradicting Christian conceptions, they argued that there is no such thing as an immortal soul, responsible for all thoughts and decisions and capable of exercising free will. Nor, they claimed, are there any innate ideas. All thoughts are the results of sensory stimuli, formed into perceptions and ideas inside an entirely material mind.

These assertions were based on scientific theories that were still controversial in the mid-nineteenth century. Even so, Russian radical journalists elevated materialism to the status of a worldview that contained the answers to the country's most pressing political and social problems. The sweeping nature of their claims led the conservative critic Mikhail Katkov (1818–1887) to denounce materialism as a new “religion” in 1861, a view famously repeated by the philosopher Nikolai Berdiaev in the early twentieth century.

From 1858, the two leading radical journals, The Contemporary and The Russian Word, became synonymous with materialism. It was not long, however, before some radical writers began to voice significant doubts about their religion.

Type
Chapter
Information
A History of Russian Philosophy 1830–1930
Faith, Reason, and the Defense of Human Dignity
, pp. 69 - 89
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×