Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Introduction
- Part I The Calculus as Algebra
- Part II Selected Writings
- 1 The Mathematician, the Historian, and the History of Mathematics
- 2 Who Gave You the Epsilon? Cauchy and the Origins of Rigorous Calculus
- 3 The Changing Concept of Change: The Derivative from Fermat to Weierstrass
- 4 The Centrality of Mathematics in the History of Western Thought
- 5 Descartes and Problem-Solving
- 6 The Calculus as Algebra, the Calculus as Geometry: Lagrange, Maclaurin, and Their Legacy
- 7 Was Newton's Calculus a Dead End? The Continental Influence of Maclaurin's Treatise of Fluxions
- 8 Newton, Maclaurin, and the Authority of Mathematics
- 9 Why Should Historical Truth Matter to Mathematicians? Dispelling Myths while Promoting Maths
- 10 Why Did Lagrange “Prove” the Parallel Postulate?
- Index
- About the Author
3 - The Changing Concept of Change: The Derivative from Fermat to Weierstrass
from Part II - Selected Writings
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Introduction
- Part I The Calculus as Algebra
- Part II Selected Writings
- 1 The Mathematician, the Historian, and the History of Mathematics
- 2 Who Gave You the Epsilon? Cauchy and the Origins of Rigorous Calculus
- 3 The Changing Concept of Change: The Derivative from Fermat to Weierstrass
- 4 The Centrality of Mathematics in the History of Western Thought
- 5 Descartes and Problem-Solving
- 6 The Calculus as Algebra, the Calculus as Geometry: Lagrange, Maclaurin, and Their Legacy
- 7 Was Newton's Calculus a Dead End? The Continental Influence of Maclaurin's Treatise of Fluxions
- 8 Newton, Maclaurin, and the Authority of Mathematics
- 9 Why Should Historical Truth Matter to Mathematicians? Dispelling Myths while Promoting Maths
- 10 Why Did Lagrange “Prove” the Parallel Postulate?
- Index
- About the Author
Summary
First the derivative was used, then discovered, explored and developed, and only then, defined.
Some years ago while teaching the history of mathematics, I asked my students to read a discussion of maxima and minima by the seventeenth-century mathematician, Pierre Fermat. To start the discussion, I asked them, “Would you please define a relative maximum?” They told me it was a place where the derivative was zero. “If that's so,” I asked, “then what is the definition of a relative minimum?” They told me, that's a place where the derivative is zero. “Well, in that case,” I asked, “what is the difference between a maximum and a minimum?” They replied that in the case of a maximum, the second derivative is negative.
What can we learn from this apparent victory of calculus over common sense?
I used to think that this story showed that these students did not understand the calculus, but I have come to think the opposite: they understood it very well. The students' answers are a tribute to the power of the calculus in general, and the power of the concept of derivative in particular. Once one has been initiated into the calculus, it is hard to remember what it was like not to know what a derivative is and how to use it, and to realize that people like Fermat once had to cope with finding maxima and minima without knowing about derivatives at all.
Historically speaking, there were four steps in the development of today's concept of the derivative, which I list here in chronological order.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- A Historian Looks BackThe Calculus as Algebra and Selected Writings, pp. 147 - 162Publisher: Mathematical Association of AmericaPrint publication year: 2010