Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T10:02:09.902Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - The nature of law and why it matters

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 October 2014

W. Bradley Wendel
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Get access

Summary

Law, morality, and legal ethics

Lawyers have obligations, stated in officially promulgated codes of conduct and other authoritative sources of law, to do things such as keep their clients’ secrets and be effective advocates for their clients’ positions. It is therefore quite tempting to try to justify the conduct of lawyers by referring to the law, for example.: “The law requires lawyers not to disclose confidential information.” Think about it for a minute, though. The law may create obligations, but it may not follow that it creates moral obligations. Suppose someone says, of the lawyer representing the real killer, Wilson, in the wrongful conviction case from Chapter 1, “You did wrong morally by keeping Wilson’s secret.” it is not necessarily an adequate answer for the lawyer to say, “I had a legal obligation to do so.” There is potentially a gap between legal and moral obligation. Perhaps there is a way across that gap (another bridge!), but it has to be made clear whether, and under what circumstances, a legal obligation makes any difference in the domain of morality.

In an article that was somewhat scandalous when it was first published in the Harvard Business Review, Albert Carr, a former advisor to US President Harry Truman, heaped scorn on those who argued that businesspeople ought to be guided by the standards of ordinary morality (which Carr identified as the morality taught in religious traditions). Instead, Carr argued, business ought to be understood as a game, like poker, and the ethical norms of business ought to be only to follow the rules of the game. As long as some action is not illegal, it is ethical as long as it complies with the rules of the game, and the game of business, as it turns out, permits a variety of seeming wrongs, including industrial espionage, deceptive labeling of food products, firing older workers to reduce pension costs, indifference by auto manufacturers to the safety of their products, and the substitution of inexpensive, possibly dangerous ingredients in health care products.

Type
Chapter
Information
Ethics and Law
An Introduction
, pp. 62 - 88
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Carr, Albert Z., “Is Business Bluffing Ethical?,” Harvard Business Review (Jan.–Feb. 1968), p. 143–53Google Scholar
Zabella v. Pakel, 242 F.2d 452 (7th Cir. 1957)
Simon, William H., The Practice of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1998), p. 37Google Scholar
Kramer, Matthew H., Objectivity and the Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2007), p. 143CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (London: J. Murray 1832)Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2d edn., 1994)Google Scholar
Green, Leslie, “Law and Obligations,” in Coleman, Jules and Shapiro, Scott, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2002)Google Scholar
Lyons, David, Ethics and the Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1984), pp. 70–71Google Scholar
Schauer, Frederick, The Force of Law (manuscript, forthcoming 2014), § 3.3
Coleman, Jules, “Negative and Positive Positivism,” in Cohen, Marshall, ed., Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld 1983), p. 31Google Scholar
Shapiro, Scott J., Legality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 2011), pp. 269–70Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” Harvard Law Review 71: 593–629 (1958)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, Lon L., “Positivism and Fidelity to Law – A Reply to Professor Hart,” Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72 (1958)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, Lon L., The Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2d ed., 1964)Google Scholar
Baumgarth, William P. and Regan, Richard J., eds., Aquinas on Law, Morality, and Politics (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2d edn., 2002)
Finnis, John, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1980)Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 41–42Google Scholar
Murphy, Mark C., Natural Law in Jurisprudence and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cover, Robert M., Justice Accused (New Haven: Yale University Press 1975)Google Scholar
Alexy, Robert, The Argument from Injustice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Paulson, Bonnie Litschewski and Paulson, Stanley L., trans., 2002)Google Scholar
Marmor, Andrei, Philosophy of Law (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press 2011), p. 114Google Scholar
Luban, David, “Natural Law as Professional Ethics: A Reading of Fuller,” in Legal Ethics and Human Dignity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2007), p. 110CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, “The Model of Rules I,” in Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1977)Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Law’s Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1986), p. 19Google Scholar
Shapiro, Scott J., “The ‘Hart-Dworkin’ Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed,” in Ripstein, Arthur, ed., Ronald Dworkin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2007)Google Scholar
Fried, Charles, Contract as Promise (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1981)Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×