Introduction
In the Introduction, I pointed out six theological tendencies that flourished in early to mid-second-century Alexandria. Alexandrian Christian theologians, adapting themes and techniques from Hellenized Jewish thought, emphasized universalizing themes that intersected with (mainly Platonic and Pythagorean) philosophical tendencies, including the idea of a wholly transcendent God, distinct creative agencies, theandry, the transmigration of souls, the rejection of corruptible flesh, and the deification of the mind. This chapter explores our richest example of Hellenized Jewish thought in Alexandria, namely the works of Philo.
Philo is by no means representative of all Jews in Alexandria. At the same time, due to the extent of his surviving work, his education, and his era (early first century ce), he provides the best window into Alexandrian Jewish intellectual culture before the advent of the Jesus movement(s). It pays dividends, then, to begin with him to see if he can help to specify the intellectual trends that would appear in Christian sources after him. In Chapter 3, I explore what Philo tells us about Jewish social history in Alexandria.Footnote 1
Life and Work
Philo belonged to a tiny minority. He was a wealthy aristocrat, and his wealth may have been in the family for generations. His brother, Alexander (called “the Alabarch”), was a tax official who loaned money to kings and plated nine gates of the Jerusalem temple with gold.Footnote 2 Although Philo never spoke of it, it is likely that he owned income-producing estates as well as household slaves. Whether or not Philo was a citizen of Alexandria, he obtained an education as if he was one. Money went a long way in this department, paving the way not only for Philo’s encyclical studies (geometry, music, astronomy, grammar) but also for the heights of philosophical learning.Footnote 3
Possibly Philo set up a kind of school in his home where he trained students, not just in any philosophy, but in the distinctly Jewish philosophy that claimed Moses for its master.Footnote 4 The Alexandrian’s teaching was duly calibrated for different audiences. He wrote three commentary series: (1) an allegorical series focusing on a detailed exegesis of Genesis, (2) a question-and-answer series focusing on exegetical problems in Genesis and Exodus, and (3) an expository series focusing on the creation story, the Mosaic law, and the lives of the Hebrew patriarchs. On top of all this, he wrote several in-depth philosophical tractates.
Philo was familiar with every Hellenistic philosophy and melded elements from Neo-Pythagoreanism, Platonism, and Stoicism to create a mosaic of Mosaic philosophy.Footnote 5 Plato was Philo’s most revered and most influential philosopher. At the same time, Philo did not comment on the works of Plato but on those of Moses. To outsiders, the Pentateuch seemed a rough-hewn block of myths and laws, but for Philo, these pages contained the deepest of sacred mysteries. It was Philo’s mission as a writer to smooth out the problems in scripture and – for an initiated audience – to reveal the deeper mysteries of Mosaic lore.Footnote 6
On the face of it, Philo’s methods foreshadow developments in later rabbinic literature.Footnote 7 He constantly compared scripture with scripture – often multiple scriptures – before circling back to his main text. Unlike the rabbis, however, Philo’s mind was suffused with the categories and characters of Platonic philosophy (the Forms, the Logos, the intelligible world, the passions, the virtues). Philo would admit that the surface meaning of his sacred text contained problems and improbabilities (God walking in the garden, a boat holding every kind of animal, Moses killing an Egyptian, and so on). But understanding the literal meaning of the text was not the end goal. What the text meant in a higher sense was known only to the initiates endowed with advanced knowledge – in short, to allegorical readers.
Philo indefatigably allegorized; at the same time, he was careful to maintain Jewish practices. The Sabbath was a symbol of nonaction on the part of creation, but it was also a time when Jews did not light fires, plow soil, carry loads, demand deposits, or recover loans.Footnote 8 Circumcision symbolized the slicing away of the passions, but Philo also believed that actual foreskins should be removed from male Jewish babies.Footnote 9 The animals forbidden in the Torah were symbols of vices, but they were still off Philo’s actual menu.Footnote 10 The Jewish temple was a symbol of the cosmos, and the true temple was the mind.Footnote 11 Nevertheless, Philo went on pilgrimage to Jerusalem and stood in awe of the physical edifice.Footnote 12
Toward the end of his life, Philo was wrenched away from scholarly seclusion and selected to lead a five-man embassy to the emperor after a horrible pogrom (August 38 ce). He sailed to Rome and likely stayed there until 41 ce. While he waited for an interview with the emperor – who was assassinated in early 41 ce – Philo probably wrote his political tractates Against Flaccus and the initial sections of his Embassy to Gaius. While it is true that Philo’s outlook became explicitly political at this stage, his intellectual stance probably did not undergo a revolutionary change from Platonism to Roman Stoicism. Nor is it safe to say that Philo wrote his entire expository series and philosophical works in Rome.Footnote 13 When Philo perished is unknown, but if he was unable to finish his “palinode” attached to his Embassy, this would suggest a death not too far into the reign of Claudius (41–54 ce).Footnote 14
Select Teachings
Following contemporary currents in Platonism, Philo supported a transcendent God: a God transcending even his Neo-Pythagorean and Platonic counterparts. God was “superior to the Good, purer than the One, and more primordial than the Monad.”Footnote 15 Human reason “cannot attain to God, who is totally untouchable and unattainable,” nor is nature a clear mirror for knowing the divine essence.Footnote 16
Philo confessed God’s oneness as his most sacred creed; but God’s unity was complex.Footnote 17 In human perception, at least, the Godhead was refracted in various ways. The ultimate and unknowable God was “the Existent” (ὁ ὢν or τὸ ὄν).Footnote 18 Since this ultimate deity was Being itself, Philo did not think that a human could share the nature of the Existent. The Existent is the primal God, the ultimate father of the Universe.Footnote 19 He may not have directly made the structures made of matter, but he was still the creator.
The Existent became known on the level of the Logos, which can be thought of as God’s Mind, an intelligible being who represents the fullness of divinity as far as it can be known to human minds.Footnote 20 Philo could call the Logos a “second God,” but he was not a being independent of God.Footnote 21 Below the Logos are the Existent’s two “Powers,” namely the “Beneficent” and “Ruling” Powers (whom Philo named “God” and “Lord,” respectively).Footnote 22 The stars, including sun and moon, for Philo, were divine on some level.Footnote 23 Under these cosmic divinities were the “heroes” and “daimones” of the Greeks whom Philo called “angels” in accordance with his scriptures.Footnote 24 To a certain extent, even humans could participate in divinity at its lower levels.
The Existent could not come into contact with limitless and chaotic matter. Instead, the Existent used bodiless potencies to shape boundless matter.Footnote 25 The chief of these Powers was the Logos, the active cause of creation.Footnote 26 The Logos was the chief instrument by which God made the world.Footnote 27 He (or it) contained the model of all creations,Footnote 28 made the four elements distinct, and carved out the shapes of animals and plants.Footnote 29
The Existent is utterly unlike humanity.Footnote 30 That is why the model for humanity is the derived divinity of the Logos.Footnote 31 Philo identified the human made in God’s image and likeness (Gen 1:26) with an ideal or form (ἰδέα τις).Footnote 32 The archetype for this form was the “intelligible and incorporeal” Logos.Footnote 33 The relationship implies that the Logos is the model for the human mind, a mind which Philo called the “true human” within.Footnote 34 Philo named the Logos, “the iconic Human” (ὁ κατ’ εἰκόνα ἄνθρωπος, based on Gen 1:26) and “God’s Human” (ἄνθρωπον θεοῦ, based on Gen 42:11).Footnote 35 He considered the Logos to be the source and father of humans.
The notion of transmigration in Philo is contested since he only employed its language in passing. In one passage of his Allegorical Commentary, for instance, Philo noted that disembodied souls close to earth descend to be bound in mortal bodies. When these souls live their lives and then exit their flesh, some of them long for the “familiar and accustomed ways of mortal life” and “hurry back again” (παλινδρομοῦσιν αὖθις) to the body.Footnote 36 Παλινδρομέω in Philo almost always indicated a movement from bodiless back to bodily things, including the passions.Footnote 37
In another passage of the Allegorical Commentary, Philo argued that humans do not possess anything, even their own souls. Humans are entities that, after death, join with other bodiless entities and “hasten to rebirth” (εἰς παλιγγενεσίαν). In context, only flawed souls are reborn and – since they have already died – must be reborn in bodies.Footnote 38
In a text from the Questions and Answers series, Philo commented on Exodus 24:12, when God called Moses to ascend Mount Sinai and “be there.” The ascent to Mount Sinai was taken to be an ascent to heaven meant for stable minds divorced from flesh. Some souls, however, instead of floating up on an eagle’s wings, “settled downward again” (αὐτίκα ὑπενόστησαν), dragged to the extremes of “Tartarus.”Footnote 39 The imagery is pulled from Plato’s Phaedrus, which depicts the soul as a chariot sometimes dragged down by the horse of unsteady desire. The “true Tartarus” is the earthly body and the “flames of desire.”Footnote 40 In short, souls dragged to Tartarus are probably reincarnated to live again on earth.Footnote 41
In these passages, Philo may have appealed to preexisting traditions, but to suppose he was not committed to transmigration depends on what we mean by “commitment.”Footnote 42 Transmigration was not, admittedly, “an essential component of how scripture should be interpreted on the fate of the soul after (and also before) death.”Footnote 43 At the same time, Philo could still believe in transmigration even if it was not seen as essential or an essentially scriptural doctrine.Footnote 44 In my view, Philo thought very seriously about what traditions he passed on. He would not have written what he did if he did not on some level accept a notion of transmigration. My sense is that transmigration was a common notion among Alexandrian Platonists – including other Alexandrian Jewish Platonists. Evidently Philo was not overly concerned about criticism from other philosophers, since there was no official position on transmigration at the time, even in the Jewish community.
As a Platonist, Philo was committed to the idea that the soul or mind was superior to the fleshly body. Yet Philo also expressed at least rhetorical disdain for the coat of skin that he wore. He called the mortal body a “baneful corpse,”Footnote 45 the soul’s grave,Footnote 46 a foul prison,Footnote 47 wicked by nature, a plotter against the soul,Footnote 48 and the “dwelling place of endless calamities.”Footnote 49 The image of God within humankind was not something based on the internal and external form of mortal bodies (arms, legs, brain, speech, the feeling of love, and so on). Rather, the divine image is “embodied” only in the bodiless mind.Footnote 50 At death, the flesh is – or at least should be – definitively shed as the soul soars to higher spheres. Philo illustrated how, for instance, at the close of Moses’s life, his flesh whirled away and only his divinized mind ascended to God as if it were a beam of sunlight.Footnote 51
On the topic of Moses’s deification, Philo did not mince words: the lawgiver was “no longer human but a god.”Footnote 52 He was “divinized,” “changed into the divine,” and became “truly divine.”Footnote 53 God “appointed” Moses “as god.”Footnote 54 To be sure, Moses was not deemed a god in his own right; he was granted the name and authority of God by divine decree (Exod 7:1).Footnote 55 Philonic deification recognized the nothingness of humanity and never fostered tyrannical arrogance or a sense of entitlement. Deification was the process of becoming an entirely bodiless and purified mind (“noetification”). Such minds did not haunt the earth but stayed forever next to God in immaterial realms.
In principle, at least, the fate of Moses was open to all. Philo wrote that “by the grace of God, it’s reasonable for a mortal to participate in deathlessness.”Footnote 56 But grace was in part built into nature. Philo called the human mind a fragment of the Logos.Footnote 57 Thus simply by virtue of being human (that is, having mind and rationality), one already has a share in divine reality. The human mind is at least partially constituted by divine breath or spirit (πνεῦμα) breathed into the first human being.Footnote 58 Philo rooted this view in Genesis 2:7 (God “breathed into his [the first human’s] face breath of life”).Footnote 59 For Philo, the medium of πνεῦμα was the Logos.
All human beings have a reflection, fragment, or ray of the shining Logos within them.Footnote 60 Since the Logos is God – or God in relation to the world – Philo could say that God breathed into Adam a portion “of his own deity” (τῆς ἰδίου θειότητος).Footnote 61 Consequently, the human mind is “a fragment of that divine and blessed soul” – evidently referring to the Logos – and so the human soul is a “divine fragment” (ἀπόσπασμα θεῖον).Footnote 62
Humans became divine by participation in the divine. As true Being, Philo’s primal God is divine in and of itself. Other divine beings, by contrast, need to participate in the divinity of the Existent to gain the name θεός. In Philo’s thought, there were both shareable and unshareable attributes of divinity. Absolute Being and eternality are unshareable qualities enjoyed by the Existent alone, whereas immortality and ruling power can be shared. A human could become divine by participating in these shareable divine qualities among which Philo added other attributes such as repose, passionlessness, and immutability.Footnote 63
Philonic Practice
We know that Philo was a Jew and practiced the precepts of the Jewish law, but what he did on a daily basis is unknown. If Philo the urban dweller was not – or perhaps could not – be rigorously ascetic, he still lauded ascetic communities such as the Essenes and Therapeutae.Footnote 64 These communities practiced celibacy, abstention from food, and withdrawal from society. They were pictured as communities of study, of spiritual and social equality, and of worship, prayer, and singing. Their banquets were contrasted with the feasts of decadent luxury Philo was accustomed to in both Alexandria and Rome. The people of these communities lived entirely the life of the mind, as if their bodies had already worn away.
Even if Philo’s descriptions of these communities are not entirely accurate, they at least represent his own ideal. Some sort of bodily discipline is the natural outcome of Philo’s theology.Footnote 65 If the true human – the human made in the image of the Logos – is the mind, then that is what one lives for. The mortal body is an appendage – and often an annoying one. It should be regimented and deprived until it is wholly obedient to mind. What matters is study and meditation, and such activities can only be practiced without bodily distractions and social entanglements. Philo was probably married, but he wrote as if he was not. He longed for the peaceful life of his country estate(s) even though he apparently spent most of his time in the hustle and bustle of the city. He likely practiced a moderate asceticism, restricting food intake and refraining from sex after his children were born. His practice and appreciation of ascetic currents would resonate with later Christian ascetic movements in Alexandria (Chapter 8).
Conclusion
On our scale of Alexandrian theological tendencies, Philo scores a perfect six. He upheld a transcendent God (the Existent), distinguished creative powers from the Existent (the Logos and unnamed auxiliaries), upheld a manifestation of God (the Logos) as the archetypal Human, endorsed a tradition of transmigration, rejected the corruptible flesh as unworthy of salvation, and proposed the deification of the mind. As we shall see, these six theological features will later appear among Christian theologians at Alexandria. The overlap shows, first of all, that there was no strong break between Jewish and Christian theology in Alexandria during the first and second centuries ce (despite any setbacks Alexandrian Jews suffered during this time). Christians upheld Jesus as the messiah and came to identify him as the Logos, but these affirmations did not dictate the nature of their theology as a whole. Alexandria in the first and second centuries ce was vibrant and intellectually diverse. At the same time, there seems to have been a fairly distinctive intellectual climate or set of intellectual (largely Platonizing and Pythagoreanizing) tendencies there. Whether or not the earliest Christians of Alexandria read Philo, they shared a theological climate he belonged to, which helps to explain why they posited similar tenets and manifested like tendencies.